PHILOSOPHY AND ANTHROPOSOPHY
The human soul, under
normal conditions of life and development, is liable to encounter two
obstacles which must be overcome if the soul would avoid being swept like a
rudderless ship on the waves of life. A drifting of this nature produces,
in time and by degrees, an inner insecurity eventually culminating in some
form of distress, or it may rob a man of the power of rightly disposing
himself in the order of the world according to the true laws governing
life, thus causing him to disturb and not promote this order.
Knowledge
in respect of the human self — that is, self-knowledge — is one
of the means of ensuring inner security and our true alignment in the order
of life's development. The impulse to self-knowledge is found in every
soul; it may be more or less unconscious, but it is always present. It may
vent itself in quite indefinite feelings which, welling up from the depths
of the soul, create an impression of dissatisfaction with life. Such
feelings are often wrongly explained, and their alleviation sought in the
outer circumstances of life. Though we are often unconscious of its nature,
fear of these feelings obsesses us. If we could overcome this anxiety we
should realize that no external measures, but only a thorough knowledge of
the human being, can prove helpful. But this thorough knowledge requires
that we should really feel the resistance of the two obstacles which human
knowledge is liable to encounter when it would enter more deeply into the
knowledge of the human being. They consist of two illusions, towering as
two cliffs, between which we cannot advance in our pursuit of knowledge
until we have experienced their true nature.
These two
obstacles are: Natural Science and Mysticism. Both these forms of knowledge
appear in a natural way upon the path of human life. But they must be
inwardly experienced if they are to prove helpful. Whether or not we can
acquire a knowledge of humanity depends upon our developing the strength to
reach, indeed, both obstacles, but not to remain stationary before them.
When confronted by them, we must still retain sufficient detachment to be
able to say to ourselves: neither method can lead our soul whither we would
go. But this insight can only result from a true inner experience of their
cognitive value. We must not shrink from really experiencing their nature;
in order to realize thereby that we endow them with their true value by
first advancing beyond them. We must seek access to both methods of
knowledge; once we have found them, the way of escape from them becomes
apparent. The belief that true reality is grasped by Natural Science is
revealed, to an unprejudiced insight, to be an illusion. A normal feeling
of our own human reality produces quite a definite experience. The latter
is intensified the more we tend to apply Natural Science to the
comprehension of our own human self. Man as a natural product consists of a
sum of natural operations. It may become an ideal of knowledge to
comprehend man in the light of the operative forces observed in the realm
of Nature. With genuine Natural Science this ideal is justifiable. It may
also be admitted that an incalculably distant future will reveal the method
of development according to natural law of the miraculous human
organization. Efforts in this direction must be accepted as the rightful
ideal of Natural Science. Yet it is essential that we should, in the face
of this rightful ideal, press forward to an insight promoted by a sound
feeling of reality. We must inwardly experience how the results offered us
by Natural Science become increasingly foreign to all our inner experience
of reality. The more perfect the results, the more foreign are they felt to
be to our inner life, with its thirst for knowledge. True to its ideal,
Natural Science is bound to offer us material substances; yet, if inwardly
unbiased, we cannot avoid finally encountering the difficulty experienced
by Du Bois-Reymond, when he asserted, in his famous lecture on the
“Boundaries of Natural Science,” that human knowledge would
never grapple with the phenomenon haunting space in the guise of matter. To
devote all suitable faculties to the pursuit of Natural Science is a sound
experience, but we should at the same time feel that the distance between
ourselves and reality is not thereby lessened, but increased. The results
of Natural Science should give us occasion to make this experience. We must
observe that they do not result from comprehension or feeling, and we shall
reach the point of admitting that we do not, in truth, devote ourselves to
Natural Science in order to draw nearer to reality; we believe this to be
the case in our conscious self, but the unconscious origin of our efforts
must have an altogether different significance — a significance for
human life, into which we must inquire. Knowledge of true reality does not
coincide with knowledge of Nature. This insight can prove a turning point
in the life of our soul. The knowledge is brought home to us through inner
experience that we were bound to follow the course of Natural Science, but
that we were disappointed in the expectations raised by our diligent
pursuit. This recognition is the final result of genuine experience and
insight into the natural processes. We then abandon the belief that Natural
Science, however perfect its future development, can supply us with the
knowledge of the human being. Not to have reached this standpoint and still
to cherish the hope that ideal natural scientific knowledge can enlighten
us concerning our own being, is a sign that we have not sufficiently
advanced in the experiences that are possible within the scope of Natural
Science itself.
This is
the first obstacle against which we strike in our effort to attain
knowledge of the human being. Many a thinker has felt the thrust on this
side, and has faced about towards Mysticism and mystical immersion in the
inner self. A certain progress can also be made in this direction, in the
belief that actual reality, or something in the nature of unity with the
primordial fount of all Being, can be inwardly experienced. If, however, we
press on far enough to destroy the force of illusion, we become aware that
however deep the immersion in the inner self, this experience leaves us
helpless in the face of reality. With however powerful a grip we may be
induced to feel that we have seized primal being, this inner experience
finally proves to be some effect of an unknown being; we remain incapable
of laying hold on true reality and retaining it. The mystic pursuing this
path discovers that he has inwardly abandoned the true reality which he
seeks and cannot draw near it again.
The
natural scientist reaches an outer world which illudes his inner life. The
mystic, while seeking to grasp an outer world reaches an inner life which
sinks into the void.
Our
experiences, on the one hand with Natural Science and on the other with
Mysticism, proved to be no fulfillment of our efforts to find reality, but
merely the starting-point of our path, for we are shown the chasm that
yawns between material occurrence and the inner life of the soul; we are
led to see this chasm and to gain the insight that, in respect of true and
genuine knowledge, neither Natural Science nor mere Mysticism is capable of
bridging it. The perception of this chasm leads us to seek an insight into
reality by filling the gap with cognitional experiences which are not yet
forthcoming in ordinary consciousness, but must be developed. With true
experience of Natural Science and Mysticism, we must admit that another
form of knowledge must be sought in addition to these — a knowledge
that brings the material outer world nearer to our inner life, and at the
same time immerses our inner life more deeply into the real world than this
can be the case with Mysticism.
A
cognitional method of this nature can be called anthroposophical, and the
knowledge of reality thereby attained, Anthroposophy; for at the outset,
true and genuine Man (anthropos) is held to be concealed behind the
“man” revealed by Natural Science and the inner life of
everyday consciousness. This true and genuine Man makes his presence felt
in dim feelings, in the more unconscious life of the soul. Anthroposophical
research raises him into consciousness. Anthroposophy does not lead away
from reality to an unreal imaginary world; it embodies the search for a
cognitional method in response to which the real world will reveal itself.
With due experience of Natural Science and the Mysticism confined to
ordinary consciousness, Anthroposophy presses forward to the perception
that a new consciousness must be developed, issuing from ordinary
consciousness as, for instance, waking from the dull dream consciousness.
Thus the cognitional process becomes for Anthroposophy a real inner
occurrence extending beyond ordinary consciousness, whereas Natural Science
is nothing but logical judgment and inference within the confines of
ordinary consciousness, on the basis of outwardly given material reality,
and Mysticism only a deepened inner life which, however, remains within the
pale of ordinary consciousness.
In
calling attention, at the present day, to the fact that an inwardly real
cognitional process and an anthroposophical knowledge exist, habits of
thought are encountered whose origin is due, on the one hand, to Natural
Science with its wonderful achievements and great expansion, and to certain
mystical prejudices on the other. Thus Anthroposophy is repudiated upon the
one side for supposedly not doing justice to Natural Science, while upon
the other it appears superfluous to the mystically inclined, who believe
they can themselves take their stand upon true reality. Others, who aim at
keeping “genuine” knowledge free from everything that extends
beyond ordinary consciousness, hold that Anthroposophy disowns the true
scientific character which philosophy, for instance, and its knowledge of
the world should retain, and therefore lapses into dilettantism.
The
following exposition will prove how little this reproach of dilettantism
(especially at the hands of philosophy) is justified. A short sketch of its
development will show how often philosophy has estranged itself from true
reality, through not perceiving the very two cognitional obstacles alluded
to above, and how an unconscious impulse is at the root of all
philosophical effort to steer between these obstacles and strive for
Anthroposophy. (I have dealt at greater length with this tendency of all
philosophy towards Anthroposophy in my book
Die Rätsel der Philosophie).
Philosophy is generally regarded by those concerned therewith as something
absolute, and not as something which was bound to come into existence,
under particular conditions, in the course of the development of mankind,
and be subject to transformation. Many an erroneous view of its true nature
is current. It is however precisely when dealing with philosophy that we
are in a position to name the period when it originated (and must have
originated) in the course of human development — not merely through
inner experience, but also on the basis of external historical documents.
Most exponents of the history of philosophy, especially of the older
school, have estimated this period fairly correctly. In all such
presentations we find that a beginning is made with Thales, and the course
of philosophy traced from him onwards in continuity down to our times. Some
modern writers on the history of philosophy, aiming at unusual
comprehensiveness and perspicacity, have placed the beginning of philosophy
in still earlier times, drawing upon the various teachings of ancient
wisdom. This, however, is only due to a particular form of dilettantism
wholly ignorant of the fact that all the teachings of Indian, Egyptian, and
Chaldean wisdom were entirely different, both in respect of method and
origin, from purely philosophical thought with its leaning towards the
speculative. The latter developed in the world of Greece, and there the
first thinker to be considered in this sense is, in fact, Thales.
We need
not describe at length the characteristics of the various Greek
philosophers, beginning with Thales; we need not dwell on Anaxagoras,
Heraclitus, Anaximenes, or yet on Socrates and Plato. We may begin at once
with that personality who appears as the very first philosopher in the
narrowest sense, the philosopher par excellence — Aristotle. All other
philosophies were in reality but abstractions inspired by the wisdom of the
Mysteries; in the case of Thales and Heraclitus, for instance, this could
easily be shown. [Under “Wisdom of the
Mysteries” a wisdom is meant which flourished in ancient times, and
differed essentially from later methods of knowledge. Its origin as an
inner experience of the soul whereby the secrets of the Cosmos were
revealed. During the sixth century BC, this method of
knowledge was succeeded by another which, rejecting the inner experience of
the soul, sought to gain an understanding of the world by the rational
observation of the physical and spiritual phenomena. The inner vision of
the more ancient method was sustained by an instinctive logic. In the
following period logical thought became to an increasing extent a conscious
faculty. Intuitive vision disappeared and the wisdom of the Mysteries was
succeeded by philosophical speculation. The philosophers of the earliest
period, however, were acquainted with the wisdom of the Mysteries, either
through inner vision (if they still retained this faculty) or through
tradition, and applied to it the newly evolving faculty of rational
thought. The reader will find a description of this historical transition
in the author's
Die Rätsel der Philosophie.]
Neither
Plato nor Pythagoras is a philosopher in the real sense of the word,
seership being the source from which both of them draw. The chief interest
in a characterization of philosophy as such does not centre round the fact
that someone or other expresses himself in ideas, but round the question
where the sources from which he draws are to be found. Pythagoras drew from
the wisdom of the Mysteries, which he translated into concepts and ideas.
He was a seer, only he expressed his experiences as seer in philosophic
form; and the same was the case with Plato.
But the
essential characteristic of the philosopher, manifested for the first time
in Aristotle, is the fact that he necessarily rejects all other sources (or
has no access to them), and works exclusively with the technique of ideas.
And since this may be said for the first time of Aristotle, it is not
without good historical reason that it should be precisely this philosopher
who founded logic and the science, of thought. All other efforts in this
direction had been of a precursory nature only. The way and the manner in
which concepts and judgments are formed and conclusions drawn this entire
range of mental activity was discovered by Aristotle as a kind of natural
history of subjective thought, and everything we meet within him is closely
connected with this inauguration of the technique of thought. As we shall
revert to certain points in connection with Aristotle which are of
fundamental importance for all later aspects of the subject, this short
historical indication will suffice to characterize in a few words the point
from which we depart. Aristotle remains the representative philosopher for
later times also. His achievements were not only embodied in the
post-Aristotelian period of antiquity, up to the founding of Christianity,
but he was regarded most especially in the first Christian period and
onward into the Middle Ages as that philosopher in whom direction was to be
sought in all efforts to formulate a conception of the universe. By this we
do not mean that men had Aristotle's philosophy before them as a system, as
a collection of dogmas — especially in the Middle Ages, when the
original texts were not obtainable; but thinkers had become familiar with
the process of applying the technique of pure thought and thereby ascending
step by step to knowledge, up to the point where thought encompasses the
fundamental problems of life. Aristotle became to an increasing extent the
Master of Logic. The medieval thinkers would say to themselves: whatever be
the source of the knowledge of positive facts, be it due to man's
investigation of the outer world by means of his senses, or be it due to
revelation by means of divine Grace, as through Christ Jesus, these things
have simply to be accepted, on the one hand as the deposition of the
senses, and on the other as revelation. But if any matter, however given,
is to be substantiated by a purely conceptual process, this must be done
with that technique of thinking which Aristotle discovered. And, in fact,
the inauguration of the technique of thinking was achieved by Aristotle in
so signal a fashion that Kant was but right in declaring that, since
Aristotle, logic had not advanced by so much as a single sentence.
[Little or no weight can be laid on the
objections raised against this statement of Kant in certain
quarters.] Indeed, this statement is in all essentials true of the
present day; the fundamental teachings embodying a logical system of
thought will be found today almost unaltered, if compared with what
Aristotle set down. The additions made today are due to a somewhat mistaken
attitude, prevalent even in philosophical circles, towards the conception
of logic.
Now it
was not merely the study, of Aristotle, but above all the assimilation of
his technique of thinking, that became the standard of the central period
of the Middle Ages, or the early Scholastic period, when Scholasticism was
at its prime — a period which came to a close with St. Thomas Aquinas
in the thirteenth century. When mention is made of this early
Scholasticism, it should be clearly understood that no philosophical
judgment is possible at the present time in this connection, unless we are
unhampered by all authority and dogmatic belief. It is indeed almost more
difficult nowadays to speak of these things purely objectively, than
disparagingly; for if we speak of Scholasticism with disparagement, we run
no risk of being charged with heresy by the so-called freethinkers; but if
we speak purely objectively, it is highly probable we shall be
misunderstood, because a positive and most intolerant ecclesiastical
movement of the present day often bases — its appeal upon totally
misunderstood Thomism. There is no question of discussing here what is
accepted by orthodox Catholic philosophy; neither should we be intimidated
by the possible reproach of being concerned with what is professed and
determined in dogmatic quarters. Let us rather be undisturbed by what may
be asserted on the right and on the left, and simply seek to characterize
what Scholasticism in its prime felt of science, the technique of thinking
and supernatural revelation. Early Scholasticism does not bear the
character attributed to it in a ready-made modern definition. Far from
being dualistic in nature, as many imagine, it is pure Monism. It sees the
world's primal source as an undoubted unity; only the Scholastic has a
particular feeling with regard to the perception of this primal being. He
says: there exists a certain fund of supersensible truth, a store of wisdom
which was revealed to mankind; human thought with all its technique falls
short of penetrating, of itself, into those regions which embody the
content of the highest revealed wisdom. The early Scholastic appealed to a
certain fund of wisdom which transcends the technique of thinking; that is,
it is only in so far attainable as thought is capable of elucidating the
wisdom which has been revealed. This portion of the Wisdom must be accepted
by the thinkers as revelation, and the technique of thinking merely applied
for its elucidation. What man can evolve from his inner self has its being
only in certain subordinate regions of reality, and here the Scholastic
applies active thought for the personal investigation of man. He presses
forward up to a certain boundary where revealed wisdom meets him. Thus the
content of personal research and revelation becomes united in an objective,
unified, and monistic conception of the universe. That a kind of dualism,
owing to human limitations, is associated with the matter is only of
secondary importance; this is a dualism in cognition and not a dualism in
the world whole.
The
Scholastic, therefore, pronounces the technique of thinking to be suitable
for the rational elaboration of the material gathered by empirical science
in sense-observation; further, it may press forward a stage, even up to
spiritual truth. Here the Scholastic, in all humility, presents a portion
of wisdom as Revelation, which he cannot himself discover, but which he is
called upon to accept.
Now this
special technique of thinking, as applied by the Scholastics, sprang
entirely from the soil of Aristotelian logic. There was, in fact, a twofold
necessity for the early Scholastics (whose period drew to its close in the
thirteenth century) to concern themselves with Aristotle. The first
necessity was provided by historical evolution. Aristotelianism had become
a permanency. The second arose from the fact that, as time went on, an
enemy to Christianity sprang up in another quarter.
The
teachings of Aristotle did not expand to Western countries only, but also
to the East; and everything that had been brought by the Arabs into Europe
by way of Spain was, in respect of thought technique, saturated with
Aristotelianism. It was a certain form of philosophy, in particular of
Natural Science, extending into Medicine, which had been brought over, and
which was eminently saturated with Aristotelian technique of thinking. Now
the belief had grown in that quarter that nothing but a kind of Pantheism
could be the consistent outcome of Aristotelianism — a Pantheism
which, particularly in philosophy, had evolved from a very vague
Mysticism.
There
was, therefore, in addition to the fact that Aristotle's influence was
still paramount in the technique of thinking, yet another reason for men to
concern themselves with his teachings, for in the interpretation placed
upon him by the Arabs, Aristotle is made to appear as the opponent and foe
of Christianity.
It had to
be admitted that if the Arabian interpretation of Aristotelianism were
true, the latter could provide a scientific basis adapted for the
refutation of Christianity. Now let us imagine what the Scholastics felt in
this extremity. Upon the one side they adhered firmly to the truth of
Christianity, yet upon the other they were bound by all their traditions to
acknowledge that the logic and the thought technique of Aristotle were
alone right and true. Placed in this dilemma, the Scholastics were faced by
the task of proving that Aristotle's logic could be applied and his
philosophy professed, and that it was exactly he, Aristotle, who provided
the very instrument by means of which Christianity would be really
conceived and understood. It was a task imposed by the trend of historical
development.
Aristotelianism had to be handled in such a way as to make it evident that
the teaching brought by the Arabs was not Aristotle's, but only a mistaken
conception thereof; that, in short, one had but to interpret Aristotle
correctly in order to find in his teaching a basis for the conception of
Christianity. This was the task Scholasticism set itself, to the
achievement of which the writings of St. Thomas Aquinas were largely
devoted.
Now,
however, something else happened. When the day of Scholasticism had drawn
to its close, there occurred in course of time a complete rupture along the
whole line of logical and philosophical thought-evolution. No criticism is
here intended of this fact; we do not wish even to suggest that it could
have happened otherwise; the actual course taken was necessarily such as it
was, and we merely put the case hypothetically when we say that the most
natural thing would have been to have increasingly expanded the technique
of thinking, so that ever higher and higher portions of the supersensible
world should have been grasped by thought. But the next development was not
of this nature. The fundamental conceptions, which, with St. Thomas Aquinas
for instance, were applicable to the highest regions, and which could have
received such development that the boundaries restricting human research
would have receded ever farther and upwards into the supersensible regions
— this body of thought was robbed of its power and possibility, and
survived only in the conviction that the highest spiritual truths transcend
altogether the activity of human thought and are beyond elaboration by
concepts which man can evolve from himself. By such means a break in man's
spiritual life occurred. Supersensible knowledge was pronounced to be
entirely beyond the compass of human thought and to be unattainable by
subjective cognitional nets; it must have its roots in faith. There had
always been a tendency in this direction, but it ran to extremes towards
the close of the Middle Ages.
Pains
were taken to accentuate the breach between faith on the one hand, which
must be attained by objective conviction, and, on the other hand, whatever
logical activity can elaborate as the basis of a sound judgment.
Once this
chasm was opened, it was only natural that knowledge and faith should be
increasingly thrust asunder and that Aristotle and his technique of
thinking should also become the victims of this breach occasioned by
historical development. This was more especially the case at the beginning
of the modern era. It was maintained on the scientific side (and we may
consider many of the statements as well founded) that no progress could be
made in the search for empirical truth by merely spinning out what
Aristotle had placed on record. Furthermore, the trend of historical events
was such that it became inadvisable to make common cause with the
Aristotelians; and as the era of Kepler and Galileo drew near, mistaken
Aristotelianism had become the very bane of knowledge.
It
repeatedly happens that the adherents and followers of some particular
philosophy of the universe corrupt an uncommon amount of the teaching which
the founders themselves presented in the right way. Instead of looking to
Nature herself, instead of exercising the faculty of observation, it was
found easier at the end of the Middle Ages to have recourse to the old
books of Aristotle and base all academic dissertations on his written word.
It was characteristic of the epoch that when an orthodox Aristotelian was
invited to convince himself by inspecting a dead body, that the nerves do
not proceed from the heart, as he had mistakenly gathered from Aristotle,
but that the nervous system has its centre in the brain the Aristotelian
replied: “Observation certainly shows me that this is actually the
case, but Aristotle states the reverse, and I have greater faith in
him.” The followers of Aristotle had, in fact, become a grievance;
empirical science was bound to make a clearance of this false
Aristotelianism, basing its authority on pure experience, and we find a
particularly strong impulse in the direction given by the great
Galileo.
On the
other side we see an entirely different development. An aversion to the
technique of thinking was felt by those who, so to speak, sought to save
their faith from this invasion of independent thought. They were of the
opinion that this technique of thinking was powerless when faced by the
fund of wisdom acquired through revelation. When the worldly empirics
invoked the book of Aristotle, their opponents confronted them with
arguments gathered from a different but equally misunderstood book —
namely, the Bible. This was more particularly the case at the beginning of
the modern era, as we may gather from Luther's hard words; “Reason is
deaf and purblind fool” that should have naught to do with spiritual
truths, adding further that pure faith by conviction can never be kindled
by reason in a thought founded upon Aristotle, whom he calls
“hypocrite, sycophant, and stinking goat.” These are, indeed,
hard words; but when considered from the standpoint of the new era, they
may be better understood. A deep chasm had opened between reason and its
technique of thinking on the one hand, and supersensible truth on the
other. A final expression of this break is found in a philosopher through
whose influence the nineteenth century has become entangled in a web from
which it can only with difficulty extricate itself. This philosopher is
Kant. He is, virtually, the last representative thinker whose methods can
be traced to that division which occurred in the Middle Ages. He
differentiates sharply between faith and that knowledge which man may claim
to attain. Externally the
Critique of Pure Reason
is associated with the
Critique of Practical Reason, and Practical Reason seeks to handle the
problem of Knowledge from the standpoint of rational faith. On the other
hand Kant asserts most emphatically of Theoretical Reason that it is
incapable of comprehending the Actual, the “thing-in-itself.”
Man receives impressions from the thing-in-itself, but he is circumscribed
by his own ideas and conceptions. We could not describe Kant's fundamental
error without going deeply into the nature of his philosophy and its
history; but this would lead too far from the present subject, moreover the
reader will find the question adequately treated in my
Truth and Science.
What is
of far greater interest to us at the present moment is this web in the
meshes of which the philosophical thought of the nineteenth century has
become entangled. Let us examine how this came about. Kant was especially
alive to the necessity of demonstrating to what extent something absolute
was given us in thought, something in which there could be no uncertainty,
as against the uncertainty, according to him, of everything which proceeds
from experience. Our judgment can only derive certainty from the fact that
a portion of knowledge does not originate with external things, but with
ourselves. In the Kantian sense, we see external things as through a
coloured glass; we receive them into ourselves, grouping them according to
lawful connections which we ourselves evolve. Our cognition has certain forms
— the forms of space, time, the categories of cause and effect, and so
on. These are immaterial for the thing-in-itself, at least we cannot know
whether the thing-in-itself has any existence in space, time, or causality.
The latter are forms created by the subjective mind of man and imposed upon
the thing-in-itself the moment of its appearing; the thing-in-itself
remains unknown. Thus when man finds the thing-in-itself before him, he
endows it with the forms of space and time, and finds an apparent
association of cause and effect, thus enveloping the thing-in-itself with a
self-made network of concepts and forms. For this reason man may claim a
certain security of knowledge, since, as long as he is as he is, time,
space, and causality possess actual significance for him. And whatever man
thrusts into the things he must also extract from them. Of the
thing-in-itself, however, he can have no knowledge, for he remains ever a
captive of the forms of his own mind. This view was finally expressed by
Schopenhauer in his classical formula; “The world is my
conception.”
Now this
entire process of reasoning has been transmitted to almost the entire
thought of the nineteenth century; not only to the theory of knowledge, but
also, for instance, to the theoretical principles of Physiology. Here
philosophical speculation was amplified by certain experiences. If we
consider the doctrine of the specific energies of the senses, there would
seem to be a corroboration of the Kantian theory. At all events that is how
the matter was recorded during the nineteenth century. “The eye
perceives the light”; yet, if the eye be affected by some other
means, say by pressure or by electric current, a perception of light is
also recorded. Hence it was said: the perception of the light is generated
by the specific energy of the eye and transferred to the thing-in-itself.
It was Helmholtz in particular who laid this down in the crudest manner as
a physiological-philosophical axiom, declaring that not even a pictorial
resemblance can be claimed between our perceptions and the objects exterior
to ourselves. A picture resembles its prototype, but in so called
sense-perception the resemblance to the original cannot be so close as even
in a picture. The only designation, therefore, we can find for the
experience within ourselves is “symbol” of the thing-in-itself,
for a symbol need have no resemblance to the thing it expresses.
Thus the
philosophical thought of the nineteenth century, until the present day,
became thoroughly impregnated with elements which had long been in
preparation, so that the relation of human cognition to reality could not
be conceived except in the sense of the ideas given above. I often recall a
conversation I had the privilege of having years ago with a highly esteemed
philosophical thinker of the nineteenth century, with whose views, however,
on the theory of knowledge I could by no means agree. To qualify human
conceived thought as purely subjective was, I urged, a cognitional
assertion which should not be assumed a priori. He replied that one need
only bear in mind the definition of the word “conception,”
which pronounces the latter to exist only in the soul; but since reality is
only given us by means of conceptions, it follows that we have no reality
in the act of cognition, but only a conception thereof. This truly
ingenious thinker had allowed a preconceived opinion to condense to a
definition (which, for him, was indisputable), to the effect that
conceptual thought reaches only as far as the boundary of the
thing-in-itself, and is, therefore, subjective. This habit of thought has
become so predominant in the course of time that all writers on the theory
of cognition who pride themselves on understanding Kant, consider every man
a dullard who will not agree with their definition of conceptual thought
and the subjective nature of apprehension. All this has resulted from the
split which I have described as occurring in the spiritual development of
mankind.
Now a
real understanding of Aristotle enables us to find that an entirely
different principle and theory of cognition might have resulted from a
direct, that is, from an undistorted, development of his teaching. In the
matter of the theory of knowledge, Aristotle already admitted ideas to
which man today can but slowly and gradually ascend through the
intellectualistic undergrowth which is the outcome of Kant's influence. We
must, above all things, realize that Aristotle, by means of his technique
of thinking, was able to elaborate true concepts capable of transcending
those limits which were imposed upon knowledge in the way described
above.
We need
only concern ourselves with a few of Aristotle's fundamental conceptions in
order to recognize this. It is entirely in conformity with him to say: Our
initial knowledge of the things which we apprehend around us is provided by
our sense-perception. Sense presents to us the individual thing. When we,
however, begin to think, the things group themselves; we gather diverse
things into a unit of thought. Here Aristotle finds the right connection
between this unity of thought and an objective reality (which, leads to the
thing-in-itself), in showing that if we think consistently we must conceive
the world of experience around us as composed of “matter” and
what he terms “form” — two concepts which he genuinely
differentiates in the only true and possible sense. It would entail a
lengthy exposition to treat exhaustively of these concepts and all they
involve; some elementary notions, however, in this connection will help us
to understand Aristotle's teaching of “matter” and
“form” as differentiated by him. He clearly realizes that, in
respect of our cognition, it is essential that we should grasp the
“form” of all things which constitute our world of experience,
since it is the form which is the vital principle of things, and not
matter.
There are
even in our day personalities endowed with a true comprehension of
Aristotle. Vincent Knauer, who in the 'eighties was lecturer at the
University of Vienna, was in the habit of explaining to his hearers the
difference between form and matter by means of an illustration which may,
perhaps, appear grotesque, but is none the less pertinent.
“Think,” he said, “how a wolf, after eating nothing but
lambs for a part of his life, consists, strictly speaking, of nothing but
lamb — and yet this wolf never becomes a lamb!” This argument,
if only rightly followed up, gives the difference between matter and form.
Is the wolf a wolf by reason of matter? No! His being is given him by his
form, and we find this “wolf-form” not only in this particular
wolf, but in all wolves. Thus we find form by means of a concept expressing
a universal, in contradistinction to the thing grasped by the senses, which
is always particular and single. Our thought moves altogether along
Aristotelian lines, if we, like the Scholastics, exert ourselves to conceive
the nature of form by dividing the universal into three kinds. The universal,
as essence of the form, is conceived by the Scholastics, firstly as
pre-existent to all operation and life of the form in the single thing;
secondly as permeating the single thing with life and activity; thirdly,
they found that the human soul, by observing the things inwardly, endows
the universal form with life in a manner consistent with its (the soul's)
nature. The philosophers, accordingly, differentiated the universal that
lives in the thing and comes to expression in human cognition, in the
following way:
1.
Universalia ante rem: the essence of the form before its incorporation in
the single thing.
2.
Universalia in re: the essential forms existent in the things.
3.
Universalia post rem: these essential forms abstracted from the things and
appearing in cognition as an inner experience of the soul, through the
reciprocal relation of the soul to the things.
Until we
approach this threefold difference, no genuine insight is possible, in this
connection, into what is here of importance. For only consider for a moment
what is involved. The insight is involved that man, in so far as he remains
within the universalia post rem, is confined to a subjective element.
Further (and this is especially important), that the concept in the soul is
a “representation” of universally existent real forms
(Entelechies). The latter (universalia in re) have incorporated themselves
in the things, thanks to their having previously existed as universalia
ante rem.
A purely
spiritual form of existence must be attributed to the universal essences
before their incorporation in the single things. The conception of such
essential universalia ante rem will naturally appear as a fanciful
abstraction in the eyes of those for whom only the world of sensible
objects is real. But it is of essential importance that an inner experience
should induce us to accept this conception. That experience is meant,
thanks to which the general concept “wolf” is not merely
regarded as a condensation, effected by the intellect, of all the various
single wolves, but is perceived as a spiritual reality extending beyond the
single thing. This spiritual reality enables us to recognize difference
between animal and man in a genuinely spiritual sense. What is inherent in
the species “wolf” does not find its realization in the single
wolf, but in the totality of these single wolves. In man, an entity of soul
and spirit is immediately revealed in the individual, whereas, in animals,
only through the species, in the totality of the individuals. Or, in
Aristotelian terminology with individual man the “form” finds
its immediate expression in the physical human being; in the animal world
the “form,” as such, remains in a supersensible region and
extends itself along the line of development comprising all the individuals
of the same “form.” It is permissible, in the sense of
Aristotelianism, to speak of “group-souls” (the souls of kind
or species) in the case of animals, and of individual souls in the case of
man. If we succeed in acquiring an inner experience in the light of which
the above distinction becomes equivalent to a perceived reality, we have
advanced one step farther on the path of knowledge, along which
Aristotelianism and Scholasticism had only progressed as far as the
technique of concepts and ideas. Anthroposophical Spiritual Science seeks
to prove that the above experience can be acquired. The “forms”
are then not merely the outcome of conceptual differentiation, but the
object of supersensible vision. The group-souls of the animals and the
individual souls of men are perceived as beings of similar kind. This
entire process is perceived as physical reality is perceived by the senses.
The method by which Anthroposophical Spiritual Science seeks to acquire
this experience will be indicated in the course of this treatise. At this
point the writer's intention was to show how ideas within the range of
Aristotelian doctrine can be found to corroborate Anthroposophy. There is,
however, in addition to all that we have met with in Aristotle, something
which finds less and less favour in modern times. We are required to exert
ourselves to think in concise, finely chiseled concepts, in concepts which
we have first carefully prepared. It is necessary that we should have the
patience to advance from concept to concept, and above all things cultivate
clarity and keenness of thought; that we should be aware of what we are
speaking when we frame a conception. If, for instance, we speak, in the
Scholastic sense, of the relation of a concept to that which it represents,
we are required in the first place to work our way through lengthy
definitions in the Scholastic writings. We must understand what is meant
when we find it stated that the concept is grounded “formally”
in the subject and “fundamentally” in the object; the
particular form of the concept is derived from the subject and its content
from the object. That is but a small, quite a small, example. The study of
Scholastic works involves labouring through massive volumes of definitions
most unpleasant task for the scientist of today; for this reason he looks
upon the Scholastics as learned pedants and condemns them downright. He is
totally unaware that true Scholasticism is naught but the detailed
elaboration of the art of thinking, in order that thought may provide a
foundation for the genuine comprehension of reality.
It is of
course far easier to bring a few ready-made conceptions to bear upon
everything that confronts us in the nature of higher reality — far
easier than to construct a firm foundation in the sphere of thought. But
what are the consequent results? Philosophic books of the present day leave
one with a dubious impression: men no longer understand each other on
higher questions; they are not clear in their own minds as to the nature
and scope of their conceptions. This could not have happened in the days of
the Scholastics, for thinkers of that period were necessarily acquainted
with the aspect of every concept they used. A way of penetrating to the
depths of a genuine thought-method was clearly in existence, and, had this
path been duly pursued, no entanglement in the web of Kant's
“thing-in-itself,” and the (supposedly subjective) conception
thereof, would have been possible. On the contrary, two results would have
been attained. In the first place, man would have achieved an inwardly
sound theory of knowledge; secondly (and this is of great importance), the
great philosophers who lived and worked after Kant would not have been so
completely misunderstood in accepted philosophical circles. Kant was
succeeded by Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel; what are they to the man of
today? They are held to be philosophers who sought to fashion a world from
purely abstract concepts. This was never their intention. [The author is well acquainted with certain modern
philosophic works in which reference is made to Fichte, Schelling, and
Hegel with a view to obtaining direction from the utterances of these
thinkers. But he finds such treatises deficient in a point of vital
importance for the philosophers in question, namely as regards their
attitude towards a spiritual reality which must be experienced in the soul.
A mere reference to the abstract logical element in their philosophy falls
short of attaining the vital principle therein.]
But
Kant's principles of thought were the dominating influence and prevented
the greatest philosopher in the world being understood. People will only by
degrees ripen an understanding of all that Hegel has given to the world;
only when they have east off this hampering web of theories and cognitional
phantoms. Yet this would be so simple! No more is necessary than the effort
to think naturally and without constraint, rejecting the set habits of
thought which have developed under the questionable influence of the
Kantian school. The question must clearly be settled whether man (as
proceeding from the subject) encompasses the object with a conception which
he himself constructs within that subject. But does it necessarily follow
that man is unable to penetrate into the “thing-in-itself?” Let
me give a simple example. Imagine, for instance, that you have a seal
bearing the name of Miller. Now press the seal on some sealing-wax and
again remove it. There can be no doubt, I take it, that the seal being, let
us say, of brass, no property of the brass will pass over into the wax.
Were the sealing-wax to exercise the function of cognition in the Kantian
sense, it would say: “I am entirely wax; no brass passes over into
me, there is therefore no connection whereby I may learn the nature of that
which has approached me.” And yet the point in question has in this
case been entirely neglected — namely, the fact that the name
“Miller” remains objectively imprinted upon the sealing-wax,
without any portion of the brass having adhered to it. So long as people
cling to the materialistic principle of thought that no connection is
possible unless matter passes over from one to the other, they will in
theory maintain: “I am sealing-wax and the other is brass-in-itself,
and since none of the brass-in-itself can enter me, therefore the name of
Miller can be no more than a sign. But the thing-in-itself which was in the
seal and which has impressed itself upon me so that I can read it, this
thing-in-itself remains forever unknown to me.” With this final
formula the argument is clenched. Continuing the illustration, we might
say: “Man is all wax (conception). The thing-in-itself is all seal
(that which is exterior to the conception). Now since I, being wax (the
subject conceiving), can but attain to the outer surface of the seal (the
thing-in-itself), I remain within myself and nothing passes into me from
the thing-in-itself.” So long as Materialism is allowed to encroach
upon the theory of knowledge, no understanding is possible of what is here
of importance. [It clearly follows that the
term “Materialism” must be used far more comprehensively than
is usually the case. A man is a “materialist” when his method
of thought constrains him to believe that the real thing-in-itself remains
external to his soul, because no portion of its “matter” is
transmitted. He is a materialist even though he deem himself an idealist
for admitting the soul, as such. And it is to a masked materialism that
Kant's doctrine can be traced. Viewed in this light, the modern claim that
“Science has superseded nineteenth-century materialism” appears
in all its hollowness. On the contrary, Science, failing to recognize
materialistic thought as such, has plunged still deeper into
Materialism.]
It is
true that we are limited by our own conception, but the element that
reaches us from outer reality is of purely spiritual nature, and is not
dependent upon the transmission of material atoms. What passes over into
the subject is not of material but of spiritual nature, as truly as the
name Miller passes into the wax. This must be the starting-point of a sound
theory and investigation of knowledge, and it will soon become apparent to
what extent Materialism has gained a footing even in philosophical thought.
An unbiased review of the state of affairs leaves us no alternative but to
conclude that Kant could only conceive the “thing-in-itself” as
matter, however grotesque this may seem at first sight. For the sake of a
complete survey of the subject we must new touch upon another point. We
have explained how Aristotle distinguished between “form” and
“matter” in all things within our range of experience. Now if
the process of cognition allows us to approach the “form” in
the manner indicated above, the question arises to what extent is a similar
approach possible in the direction of “matter.” It must be
noted that, for Aristotle, matter was not synonymous with material
substance, but comprised the spiritual element underlying the world, of
physical reality. It is therefore possible not only to comprehend the
spiritual element that reaches us from external things,* but also to seek
immediate access to the things and identify ourselves with matter. This
question is also of importance for the theory of knowledge, and can be
answered only by one who has gone deeply into the nature of thought, that
is, of pure thought. The concept of “pure thought” is one which
we must be at pains to acquire. Following Aristotle, we may look upon pure
thought as an actual process. It is pure form and, in its initial mode of
existence, void of content as far as the single, individual things of the
external physical world are concerned. Why? Let us make it clear how pure
conception comes into being in contradistinction to perception through the
senses. Let us imagine we wish to form the conception of a circle. We can,
for this purpose, put out to sea until we see nothing but water around:
this perception can provide the conception of a circle. There is another
way, however, of arriving at the conception of a circle without appealing
to the senses. I can construct, in thought, the sum of all places which are
equidistant from one particular spot. No appeal to the senses is necessary
for this exclusively internal thought-process; it is unquestionably pure
thought in the Aristotelian sense; pure actuality.
And now a
further significant fact presents itself. Pure thought thus conceived
harmonizes with experience; it is indispensable for the comprehension of
experience. Imagine Kepler evolving, by means of pure constructive thought,
a system in which the elliptical courses of the planets are shown, with the
sun in the focus, and then observation, by means of the telescope,
subsequently confirming an effort of pure thought conceived in advance of
experience. Pure thought is thus shown to possess significance for reality
— for it harmonizes therewith. Kepler's method affords a practical
illustration of the theories which Aristotelianism founded upon the science
of knowledge. The universalia post rem are grasped, and, upon nearer
approach, it is found that they became united with the things in a previous
form, as universalia ante rem. Now if these universals are not perverted in
the sense of a false theory of knowledge, if they are not made to appear as
subjective notions, but are found to exist objectively in the things, it
follows that they must first have become united with that
“form” conceived by Aristotle as the underlying foundation of
the world.
Thus the
discovery is made that the apparently most subjective activity (when
something is determined independently of all experience) provides the very
means for attaining reality in the most objective manner possible.
Now what
is the reason why human thought, in so far as it is subjective, cannot at
first find free access to the world? The reason is that it finds its way
obstructed by the “thing-in-itself.” When we construct a circle
we live in the process itself, if only formally to begin with. Now the next
question is: To what extent can subjective thought lead to the attainment
of any permanent reality? As we have pointed out, subjective thought is, in
the first place, expressly constructed by ourselves; it is of merely formal
nature and, as far as the objective world is concerned, has the appearance
of an extraneous addition. We are indeed justified in claiming that it is a
matter of complete indifference to any existing circle or sphere whether
our thought concerns itself therewith or not. My thought is brought
externally to bear upon reality, and is of no concern to the world of
experience around me. The latter exists in its own accord irrespective of
my thought. It can therefore follow that our thought may possess
objectivity for ourselves, yet be of no moment for the things. What is the
solution of this apparent contradiction? Where is the other pole to which
we must now have recourse? Can a way be found, within pure thought to
create not only form, but together with form its material reality? As soon
as the possibility is given of a simultaneous creation of form and matter a
point of security is reached upon which the theory of knowledge may
build.
When we,
for instance, construct the circle, we may claim that whatever we assert
concerning this circle is objectively true; but the question whether our
assertions are applicable to the things will depend upon the things
themselves eventually showing us to what extent they are subject to the
laws which we construct and apply to them. When the totality of forms
resolves itself in pure thought, some residue (Aristotle's
“matter”) must remain, where it is not possible by the process
of pure thought to reach reality.
Fichte
may at this point supplement Aristotle. A formula along Aristotelian lines
may be reached to the effect that everything about us, including all things
belonging to the invisible worlds, necessarily call for a material reality
to correspond with form-reality. To Aristotle the idea of God is a pure
actuality, a pure act, that is, an act in which actuality (the formative
element) possesses the power to produce its own reality; it does not stand
apart from matter, but by reason of its own activity fully and immediately
coincides with reality.
The image
of this pure actuality is found in man himself, when by the process of pure
thought he attains to the idea of the “I.” Upon this level (in
the “I”) he is within the sphere of what Fichte calls
“deed-act.” He has inwardly arrived at something which not only
lives in actuality, but together with this actuality produces its own
“matter.” When we grasp the “I” in pure thought we
are in a centre where pure thought produces its own essential
“matter.” When we apprehend the “I” in thought, a
threefold “I” is at hand; a pure “I” belonging to
the universalia ante rem; an “I” wherein we ourselves are,
belonging to the universalia in re; and an “I” which we
comprehend and which belongs to the universalia post rem. But here we must
especially note that, in this case, when we rise to a true apprehension of
the “I,” the threefold “I” becomes merged into one.
The “I” lives within itself; it produces its own concept and
lives therein as a reality. The activity of pure thought is not immaterial
to the “I,” for pure thought is the creator of the
“I.” Here the “creative” and the
“material” coincide, and we must but acknowledge that, whereas
in other processes of cognition we strike against a boundary, this is not
the case with the “I” which we embrace in its inmost being when
we enfold it in pure thought.
The
following fundamental axiom may therefore be formulated in the sense of the
theory of cognition: “In pure thought a particular point is
attainable wherein the complete convergence of the 'real' and the
'subjective' is achieved, and man experiences reality.” If we now set
to work at this point, if we cultivate our thought so that it shall bear
fruit and issue from itself — we then grasp the things of the world
from within. In the “I,” therefore, grasped in pure thought and
thereby also created, something is given whereby we may break down the
barrier which, in the case of all other things, must be placed between
“form” and “matter.”
A
well-founded and thoroughgoing theory of cognition may thus advance to the
point of indicating a way into reality by means of pure thought. If this
path be pursued, it will be found that it must eventually lead to
Anthroposophy. Very few philosophers, however, have any understanding of
this path. They are mostly entangled in their self-made web of notions;
arid since they cannot but regard the concept as something merely abstract,
they are incapable of grasping the one and only point where it is a
creative archetype, and equally incapable of finding a bond of union with
the “thing-in-itself.”
For a
knowledge of the “I” as an instrument whereby the human soul's
immersion in the fullest reality may be clearly perceived, we are required
to distinguish most carefully between the real “I” and the
“I” of ordinary consciousness. A confusion of these might lead
us to assert, with the philosopher Descartes: “I think, therefore I
am”; in this case, however, reality would refute us during every
sleep, when we “are” though we do not “think.”
Thought does not vouch for the reality of the “I.” On the other
hand, it is equally true that an experience of the true “I” is
not possible except by means of pure thought. As far as ordinary human
consciousness is concerned, the true “I” extends into pure
thought, and into pure thought alone. Mere thinking only leads us to a
thought (conception) of the “I”; experience of all that may be
experienced within pure thought provides our consciousness with a content
of reality in which “form” and “matter” coincide.
Apart from this “I,” ordinary consciousness can know of nothing
which carries both “'form” and “matter” into
thought. All other thoughts do not image full reality. Yet by acquiring
experience of the true “I” in pure thought we become acquainted
with full reality; moreover, we may advance from this experience to other
regions of true reality.
Anthroposophy attempts this advance. It does not remain stationary on the
level of the experiences of ordinary consciousness, but strives to achieve
an investigation of reality through the agency of a transformed
consciousness. With the exception of the “I” experienced in
pure thought, ordinary consciousness is excluded for the purpose of this
investigation.
A new
consciousness takes its place, whose activity in its widest range is
commensurate with the activity of ordinary consciousness at such moments
when the latter can rise to the experience of the “I” in pure
thought. To achieve this purpose, our soul most acquire the strength to
withdraw from the apprehension of all external things and from all
conceptions with which we are inwardly so familiar that we can recall them
in our memory. Most seekers after the knowledge of reality deny the
possibility of the above; they deny it without trial. Indeed, the only
method of trial is the accomplishment of those inner processes which lead
to the above-mentioned transformation of consciousness. (A detailed
description of these processes will be found in my book, among others,
Knowledge of the Higher Worlds and Its Attainment.)
An attitude of denial
in this matter effectively hinders the attainment of true reality. Only the
main points in connection with these processes can here be given; the
subject is treated in detail in the author's above-mentioned and other
books. The soul forces which in ordinary life and science are devoted to
the perception of things and to the activity of such thought as can be
recalled in memory — these forces can be applied to the perception
and experience of a supersensible world. Our initial experience in this way
is the perception of our supersensible being. The reason why we cannot
attain this supersensible being if we remain within the limits of ordinary
consciousness becomes conspicuous to us. (Though we attain it at that one
point of the true “I,” as explained above, we are unable
immediately to recognize it in its state of isolation.) Ordinary
consciousness is produced when man's physical, bodily nature, as it were,
engulfs his spiritual being and acts in its place. In the ordinary
apprehension of the physical world we have an activity of the human
organism which is maintained by the transformation of man's supersensible
being into a sensible (physical) being. The activity of ordinary thought
originates in the same way, with the difference that apprehension is
ensured by the reciprocal relation of the human organism to the outer
world, whereas thought evolves within the organism itself.
An
insight into these facts is conditional to all true knowledge of reality.
The seeker after knowledge must make the attainment of this insight the
object of inner, spiritual exertion. The habits of thought prevalent in our
day tend to a confusion of this spiritual exercise with all manner of
nebulous, mystical amateurishness. Nothing can be more irrelevant. The
effort is entirely in the direction of the fullest clarity of soul.
Strictly logical thought is both the point of departure and the standard of
exercise, to the exclusion of all experiences deficient in such inner
clarity. But this purely logical thought is related to the inner exercise
in question, as a shadow to the object which casts it. The exercise of the
inner faculties strengthens the soul to such an extent that the struggle
towards knowledge becomes fraught with more than the experience of mere
abstract thought; the experience of spiritual realities is achieved.
Knowledge is kindled in the soul, of which a non-transformed consciousness
can have no conception. This development of consciousness has nothing to do
with any form of visionary or other diseased condition of soul. These are
inseparable from a debasement of the soul below the sphere in which clear,
logical thought is active; anthroposophical research, however, transcends
this sphere and leads into the spiritual. In the above-mentioned conditions
of soul the physical body is always implicated; anthroposophical research
strengthens the soul to such an extent that activity in the spiritual
sphere is possible independently of the physical body. The attainment of
this strengthened condition of soul requires, to begin with, exercise in
“pictorial thought.” Consciousness is made to centre upon such
clear and pregnant conceptions as are otherwise only formed under the
influence of external apprehension. An inner activity is thus experienced
of such intensity as only external tone or colour or another
sense-perception can otherwise evoke. In this case, however, the activity
is purely the result of strong inner effort. It is of the nature of
thought; not such thought as accompanies sense-perception with abstract
concepts, but thought which becomes intensified to the point of (inner)
visibility such as ordinarily is only evident in the imagery of
sense-perception. The importance does not lie in “what” we
think but in the consciousness of an activity not undertaken in ordinary
consciousness. We thus learn to experience ourselves in the supersensible
being of our “I” which, in ordinary life, is concealed by the
manifestations of the physical, bodily organization. A consciousness thus
transformed becomes the instrument for the perception of supersensible
reality. For this purpose, however, further exercise in respect of feeling
and willing is necessary, in addition to the above-mentioned exercise,
which is only concerned with the transformed faculties of perceiving and
conceiving.
In
ordinary life, feeling and willing are associated with beings or processes
external to the soul. To bring supersensible reality within the range of
cognition, the soul must give vent to the same activity which, in the case
of feeling and willing, is outwardly directed; this activity, however, must
now apprehend the inner life itself. For the purpose of and during
supersensible investigation, feeling and will must be entirely diverted
from the outer world; they must solely grasp what the transformed faculties
of perceiving and conceiving create within the soul. We “feel,”
and we permeate with “will” solely what we inwardly experience
as consciousness transformed through thought intensified to the point of
inner visibility. (A more detailed account of this transformation of
feeling and willing will be found in the books mentioned above.) The life
of the soul thus becomes completely transformed. It becomes the life of a
spiritual being (our own) experienced in a real supersensible, spiritual
world — as man, within ordinary consciousness, experiences his
“self” in a sensible, physical world through his senses and the
faculty of conceptual thought connected therewith. The knowledge of true
reality is the goal of human effort, and the first step towards its
realization consists of the insight that neither Natural Science nor
ordinary mystical experience can provide this knowledge; for between them
there yawns an abyss (as was shown at the outset) which must be bridged.
This is effected through the transformation of consciousness as outlined in
these pages. The knowledge of true reality can never be attained unless we
first realize that the usual instruments of knowledge are inadequate for
this purpose, and that the requisite instrument must first be developed.
Man feels that something more is slumbering within him than his own
consciousness can encompass in ordinary life and with ordinary science. He
instinctively yearns for a knowledge which is unattainable for this
consciousness. For the purpose of attaining this knowledge he must not
shrink from transforming the faculties which in ordinary consciousness are
directed towards the physical world, so that they shall apprehend a
supersensible world. Before true reality can be apprehended, a condition of
soul appropriate for the spiritual world must first be established! The
range of ordinary consciousness is dependent upon the human organization,
which is dissolved by death. Hence it is conceivable that the knowledge
resulting from this consciousness falls short of being knowledge of the
spiritual and eternal in man. Only the transformation of this consciousness
ensures a perception of that world in which man lives as a supersensible
being, that is, as a being which remains unaffected by the dissolution of
the physical organism.
The
acceptance of this transmutability of consciousness and, hence, of a
possible investigation of reality, is alien to the habits of thought of the
present day. More so, perhaps, than the physical system of Copernicus to
the men of his time. But as this system, in spite of all obstacles, found
its way to the human soul — so, too, anthroposophical Spiritual
Science will find its way. An understanding of anthroposophy is also
difficult for contemporary philosophy, for the latter derives its origin
from a mode of thought which failed to fructify the germs of an
unprejudiced technique of thought which were implanted in Aristotelianism.
This shortcoming, as was shown above, was followed by the seclusion of
thought and investigation, through an artificial web of concepts, from true
reality, which became a “thing-in-itself.” Owing to this
fundamental tendency, contemporary philosophy cannot but refuse to accept
anthroposophy. In the light of the philosophical conception of scientific
method, anthroposophy cannot but appear as dilettantism, and this reproach
is easily conceivable if the essentials of the question are kept in view.
The origin of this reproach has here been explained.
These
pages will possibly have made clear what must necessarily occur before the
philosophers can undertake to agree that anthroposophy is no dilettantism.
It is necessary that philosophy, with its conceptual system, should work
its way to an unprejudiced recognition of its own fundamental basis. It is
not the case that anthroposophy is at variance with sound philosophy, but
that a modern theory of knowledge, accepted by science, is itself at
variance with the deeper foundation of true philosophy.
This
theory of knowledge is wandering in false tracks and must relinquish these
if it would develop an understanding of anthroposophical
world-comprehension.