The
Nature of Thomism
Dornach, 23 May 1920
What I especially tried to stress yesterday
was that in that spiritual development of the West which found
its expression in scholasticism not only that happens which one
can grasp in abstractions and which took place in a development
of abstractions, but that behind it a real development of the
impulses of western humanity exists. I think that one can look
at that at first, as one does mostly in the history of
philosophy, which one finds with the single philosophers. One
can pursue, how the ideas, which one finds with a personality
of the sixth, seventh, eighth, ninth centuries, are continued
by personalities of the tenth, eleventh, twelfth, thirteenth
centuries, and one can get the impression by such a
consideration that one thinker took over certain ideas from the
other and that a certain evolution of ideas is
there.
One has to leave this historical
consideration of the spiritual life gradually. Since that which
manifests from the single human souls are only symptoms of
deeper events which are behind the scene of the outer
processes. These events which happened already a few centuries
before Christianity was founded until the time of scholasticism
is a quite organic process in the development of western
humanity. Without looking at this process, it is equally
impossible to get information about that development, we say
from the twelfth until the twentieth years of a human being
unless one considers the important impact in this age that is
associated with sexual maturity and all forces that work their
way up from the subsoil of the human being. Thus, something
works its way up from the depths of this big organism of
European humanity that one can just characterise saying: those
old poets spoke very honestly and sincerely who began their
epic poems as Homer did: sing to me, goddess, on the rage of
the Peleid Achilles —, or: sing to me,
muse, on the actions of the widely wandered man.
— These
men wanted to say no commonplace phrase, they felt as inner
fact of their consciousness that not a single individual ego
wants to express itself there but a higher spiritual-mental
that intervenes in the usual state of human
consciousness.
Again — I said it already
yesterday —
Klopstock was sincere and figured this fact
out in a way, even if maybe only instinctively, when he began
his Messiah; now not:
sing, muse, or: sing, goddess, on the redemption of the human
beings -, but he said: sing, immortal soul -, that means: sing,
individual being that lives in the single person as an
individuality. —
When Klopstock wrote his
Messiah, this individual feeling had already advanced far in the
single souls. However, this inner desire to stress
individuality originated especially in the age of the
foundation of Christianity until High Scholasticism. In that
which the philosophers thought one can notice the uppermost,
which goes up to the extreme surface of that which takes place
in the depths of humanity: the individualisation of the
European consciousness. An essential moment of the propagation
of Christianity in these centuries is the fact that the
missionaries had to speak to people who more and more strove
for feeling the inner individuality.
Only from this viewpoint, you can
understand the conflicts that took place in the souls of such
human beings who wanted to deal with Christianity on one side
and with philosophy on the other side as Albert the Great and
Thomas Aquinas did. Today the common histories of philosophy
describe the soul conflicts too little, which found their end
in Albert and Thomas. There many things intervened in the soul
life of Albert and Thomas.
Seen from without it seems, as if Albert
the Great who lived from the twelfth to the thirteenth century
and Thomas who lived in the thirteenth century wanted to
combine Augustinism and Aristotelianism only dialectically on
one side. The one of them was the bearer of the ecclesiastical
ideas; the other was the bearer of the cultivated philosophical
ideas. You can pursue their searching for the harmony of both
views everywhere in their writings. Nevertheless, in everything
that is fixed there in thoughts endlessly much lives that did
not pass to that age which extends from the middle of the
fifteenth century until our days, and from which we take our
common ideas for all sciences and also for the whole public
life.
It appears to the modern human, actually,
only as something paradox: the fact that Augustine really
thought that a part of the human beings is destined from the
start to receive the divine grace without merit
— for they
all would have to perish because of the original sin
— and to
be saved mental-spiritually. The other part of humanity
must perish mental-spiritually, whatever it undertakes. —
For the modern human being this seems paradox, maybe even
pointless. Someone who can empathise in the age of Augustine in
which he received those ideas and sensations that I have
characterised yesterday will feel different. He will feel that
one can understand that Augustine wanted still to adhere to the
ideas that not yet cared about the single person that just
cared about the general-human influenced by such ideas as those
of Plotinism. However, on the other side, the drive for
individuality stirred in the soul of Augustine. Hence, these
ideas get such a succinct form, hence, they are fulfilled with
human experience, and thereby just Augustine makes such a deep
impression if we look back at the centuries, which preceded
scholasticism.
Beyond Augustine that remained for many
human beings what the single human being of the West as a
Christian held together with his church — but only in the
ideas of Augustine. However, these ideas were just not suitable
for the western humanity that did not endure the idea to take
the whole humanity as a whole and to feel in it like a member,
which probably belongs to that part of humanity, which is
doomed. Hence, the church needed a way out.
Augustine still combated Pelagius
(~360-418) intensely, that man who was completely penetrated
with the impulse of individuality. He was a contemporary of
Augustine; individualism appears in him as usually only the
human beings of the later centuries had it. Hence, he could not
but say, it can be no talk that the human being must remain
quite passive in his destiny in the sensory world. From the
human individuality even the power has to originate by which
the soul finds the connection to that which raises it from the
chains of sensuousness to the pure spiritual regions where it
can find its redemption and return to freedom and
immortality. —
The opponents of Augustine asserted that
the single human being must find the power to overcome the
original sin.
The church stood between both opponents,
and it looked for a way out. This way out was often discussed.
One talked as it were back and forth, and one decided for the
middle. I would like to leave it to you whether it is the
golden mean. This middle was the Semipelagianism. One found a
formula which announced: indeed, it is in such a way as
Augustine said, but, nevertheless, it is not completely in such
a way as Augustine said; it is also not completely in such a
way as Pelagius said, but it is in a certain sense in such a
way as he said. Thus, one can say that, indeed, not by God's
everlasting wise decision the ones are destined to sin, the
others to grace; but the matter would be in such a way that,
indeed, there is no divine predetermination but a divine
foreknowledge. God knows in advance whether the one is a sinner
or the other is someone who is filled with grace.
Besides, we do not take into account when
this dogma was spread that it did not at all concern
foreknowledge, but that it concerned taking
plainly position whether now the single individual human being
can combine with the forces in his individual soul life which
can cancel his separation from the divine-spiritual being.
Thus, the question remains unsolved for dogmatism, and I would
like to say, Albert and Thomas were on one side forced to look
at the contents of the dogmas of the church, on the other side,
however, they were fulfilled with the deepest admiration of the
greatness of Augustine. They faced that what was western
spiritual development within the Christian current.
Nevertheless, still something played a role from former times.
It lived on in such a way that one sees it being active on the
bottom of their souls, but one also realises that they are not
quite aware of it that it has impact in their thoughts that
they cannot bring it, however, to an exact version.
One must consider this more for this time
of High Scholasticism of Albert and Thomas than one would have
to consider a similar phenomenon, for example, in our time. I
have already emphasised the why and wherefore in my
Worldviews and Approaches to Life in the
Nineteenth Century. I would only
like to note that this book was extended to The Riddles of Philosophy where the concerning passage could not return because
the task of the book had changed. We experience that from this
struggle of individuality the thinkers who developed this
struggle of individuality philosophically reach the zenith of
the logical faculty of judgement.
One may rail against scholasticism from
this or that party viewpoint — all this railing is
fulfilled with little expertise as a rule. Since someone who
has sense for the way in which the astuteness of thoughts comes
about with something that is explained scientifically or
different, who has sense to recognise how connections are
intellectually combined which must be combined intellectually
if life should get sense — who has sense for
all that and for some other things already recognises that so
exactly, so conscientiously logically one never thought before
and after High Scholasticism. Just these are the essentials
that the pure thinking proceeds with mathematical security from
idea to idea, from judgement to judgement, from conclusion to
conclusion in such a way that these thinkers always account to
themselves for the smallest step.
One has only to mind that this thinking
took place in a silent monastic cell or far from the activities
of the world. This thinking could still develop the pure
technique of thinking by other circumstances. Today it is
difficult to develop this pure thinking. Since if one tries
anyhow to present such activity to the general public which
wants nothing but to string together thoughts, then the biased
people, the illogical people come who take up all sorts of
things and allege their crude biased opinions. Because one is
just a human being among human beings, one has to deal with
these things that often are not at all concerned with that
which it concerns, actually. One loses that inner quietness
very soon to which thinkers of the twelfth and thirteenth
centuries could dedicate themselves who did not think much of
the contradiction of unprepared people in their social
life.
This and still some other things caused
that wonderful sculptural, on one side, but also in fine
contours proceeding activity of thinking which is
characteristic for scholasticism and at which Albert and Thomas
aimed exceptionally consciously.
However, please remember that there are
demands of life, on one side, which appear as dogmas which were
similarly ambiguous in numerous cases as the characterised
Semipelagianism, and that one wanted to maintain the dogmas of
the church with the most astute thinking. Imagine only what it
means to consider Augustinism just with the most astute
thinking. One has to look into the inside of the scholastic
striving and not only to characterise the course from the
Fathers of the Church to the scholastics along the concepts
that one has picked up.
Just many semi-conscious things had impact
on these spirits of High Scholasticism. You cope with it only
if you look beyond that what I have characterised already
yesterday and if you still envisage such a figure that entered
mysteriously under the name of Dionysius the Areopagite into
the European spiritual life from the sixth century on. Today I
cannot defer to all disputes about whether his writings were
written in the sixth century or whether the other view is right
that at least leads back the traditional of these writings to
much earlier periods. All that does not matter, but that is the
point that the thinkers of the seventh, eighth centuries and
still those like Thomas Aquinas studied the views of Dionysius
the Areopagite, and that these writings contained that in a
special form which I have characterised yesterday as Plotinism,
but absolutely with a Christian nuance. That became significant
for the Christian thinkers up to High Scholasticism how the
writer of Dionysius' writings related to the ascent of the
human soul to a view of the divine.
One asserts normally that Dionysius had two
ways to the divine. Yes, he did have two. One way is that he
asks, if the human being wants to ascend from the outside
things to the divine, he must find out the essentials of all
things which are there, he has to try to go back to the most
perfect ones, he must be able to name the most perfect so that
he has contents for this most perfect divine which can now pour
itself out again as it were and create the single things of the
world from itself by individuation and differentiation. — Hence, one would
like to say, God is that being to Dionysius that one has to
call with many names that one has to give as most
distinguishing predicates which one can find out of all
perfections of the world. Take any perfection that strikes you
in the things of the world, and then call God with it, then you
get an idea of God. —
This is one way that Dionysius
suggests.
He says about the other way, you never
reach God if you even give him one single name because your
endeavour to find the perfections in the things, the essentials
of the things, to summarise them to characterise God with. You
have to free yourself from everything that you have recognised
in the things. You have to purify your consciousness completely
from everything that you have found out in the things. You must
know nothing of that which the world says to you. You must
forget all names that you have given the things and you have to
put yourself in a soul condition where you know nothing of the
whole world. If you can experience this, you experience the
unnamed one who is misjudged immediately if you give him any
name; then you recognise God, the super-God in his
super-beautifulness. However, already these names would
interfere. They can serve only to make you aware of that which
you have to experience as unnamed.
How does one cope with a personality who
gives not one theology but two theologies, a positive one and a
negative one, a rationalistic and a mystic theology? Someone
who can just project his thoughts in the spirituality of the
periods from which Christianity is born can cope with it quite
well. If one describes, however, the course of human
development during the first Christian centuries in such a way
as modern materialists do, then the writings of the Areopagite
appear more or less folly. Then one simply rejects them as a
rule. If you can project your thoughts, however, in that which
one experienced and felt at that time, then you understand what
a person like the Areopagite only wanted to express, actually,
at which countless human beings aimed. For them God was a being
that one could not recognise at all if one took one way to Him
only. For the Areopagite God was a being that one had to
approach on rational way by naming and name finding. However,
if you go this way only, you lose the path, and then you lose
yourself in cosmic space void of God. Then you do not find your
way to God. Nevertheless, one must take this way, for without
taking this way you cannot reach God. However, one has still to
take a second way. This is just that which aims at the unnamed.
However, if you take one way only, you find God just as little;
if you take both, they cross, and you find God at the crossing
point. It is not enough to argue whether one way or the other
way is right. Both together are right; but every single one
leads to nothing. One has to take both ways and the human soul
finds that at the crossing point at which it aimed.
I can understand that some people of the
present shrink from that what the Areopagite demands here.
However, this lived with the persons who were the spiritual
leaders during the first Christian centuries, then it lived on
traditionally in the Christian-philosophical current of the
West, and it lived up to Albert the Great and Thomas Aquinas.
It lived, for example, in that personality whose name I have
called already yesterday, in Scotus Eriugena. As I have told
yesterday, Vinzenz Knauer and Franz Brentano who were usually
meek flew into a rage if Plotinus came up for discussion. Those
who are more or less, even if astute and witty, rationalists
will already rail if they come in contact with that which
originated from the Areopagite, and whose last significant
manifestation Eriugena was.
A legend tells that Eriugena was a
Benedictine prior in England in his last years. However, his
own monks stabbed him repeatedly with their styluses
— I do not
say that it is literally true, but if it is not quite true, it
is approximately true —
until he was dead because he had still
brought Plotinism into the ninth century.
However, his ideas that further developed
at the same time survived him. His writings had disappeared
more or less; nevertheless, they were delivered to posterity.
In the twelfth century, one considered Scotus Eriugena as a
heretic. However, this did yet not have such a meaning as later
and today. Nevertheless, the ideas of Scotus Erigena deeply
influenced Albert the Great and Thomas Aquinas.
We realise this heritage of former times on
the bottom of the souls, if we want to speak of the nature of
Thomism. Something else is considered. In Plotinism, you can
realise a very significant feature that arose from a
sensory-extrasensory vision of the human being. One gets great
respect for these things, actually, when one finds them
spiritual-scientifically again. There one would like to confess
the following. There one says, if one reads anything
unpreparedly like Plotinus or that which is delivered from him,
then it appears quite chaotic. However, if one discovers the
corresponding truths again, these views take on a different
complexion even if they were pronounced different at that time.
Thus, you can find a view with Plotinus that I would like to
characterise possibly in the following way.
Plotinus looks at the human being with his
bodily-mental-spiritual peculiarities from two viewpoints at
first. He looks at them first from the viewpoint of the work of
the soul on the body. If I wanted to speak in modern way, I
would have to say the following. Plotinus says to himself at
first, if one looks at a child growing up, then one realises
that that still is developed which develops from
spiritual-mental as a human body.
For Plotinus is everything that appears
material in particular in the human being — please be not irked
by the expression —
an exudate of the spiritual-mental, a crust
of the spiritual-mental as it were. We can interpret everything
bodily as a crust of the spiritual-mental. However, when the
human being has grown up to a certain degree, the
spiritual-mental forces stop working on the bodily.
One could say, at first, we have to deal
with such an activity of the spiritual-mental in the bodily
that this bodily is organised from the spiritual-mental. The
spiritual-mental works out the human organisation. If anything
in the organic activity attains a certain level of maturity, we
say, for example, for that activity to which the forces are
used which appear later as the forces of memory, just these
forces which have once worked on the body appear in a
spiritual-mental metamorphosis. What has worked first
materially from the spiritual-mental, gets free from it if it
is ready with its work, and appears as an independent being, as
a soul mirror if one wants to speak in the sense of
Plotinus.
It is exceptionally difficult to
characterise these things with our concepts. One comes close to
them if one imagines the following. The human being can
remember from a certain level of maturity of his memory. He is
not able to do this as a little child. Where are the forces
with which he remembers? They develop the organism at first.
After they have worked on the organism, they emancipate
themselves and still work on the organism as something
spiritual-mental. Then only the real core, the ego lives again
in this soul mirror. In an exceptionally pictorial way this
double work of the soul, this division of the soul into an
active part which builds up, actually, the body and into a
passive part is portrayed by that ancient worldview. It found
its last expression in Plotinus and devolved then upon
Augustine and his successors.
We find this view in a rationalised form,
in more physical concepts with Aristotle. However, Aristotle
had this view from Plato and from that on which Plato rested.
If you read Aristotle, it is in such a way, as if you have to
say, Aristotle himself strives for conceptualising all old
views abstractly. Thus, we recognise in the Aristotelian system
that also continued the rationalistic form of that which
Plotinus gave in another form, we recognise a rationalised
mysticism in Aristotelianism continued until
Albert and Thomas Aquinas, a rationalistic portrayal of the
spiritual secret of the human being.
Albert and Thomas knew that Aristotle had
brought down that by abstractions what the others had in
visions. Therefore, they do not at all face Aristotle in such a
way as modern philosophers and philologists do who quarrel over
two concepts that come from Aristotle. However, because the
Aristotelian writings have not come completely to posterity,
one finds these concepts or ideas without being related to each
other. Aristotle considered the human being as a unity that
encloses the vegetative, lower principle and the higher
principle, the nous, —
the scholastics call it intellectus agens.
However, Aristotle distinguishes the nous poietikos and the
nous pathetikos, an active and a passive human mind. What does
he mean with them?
You do not understand what he means if you
do not go back to the origin of these concepts. Even like the
other soul forces these two kinds of mind are active in the
construction of the human soul: the mind, in so far as it is
still active in the construction of the human being which does
not stop, however, like the memory once and emancipates itself
as memory but is active the whole life through. It is the nous
poietikos. This builds up and individualises the body from the
universe for itself in the sense of Aristotle. It is the same
as the soul constructing the human body of Plotinus. That what
emancipates itself then what is destined only to take up the
outer world and to process the impressions of the outer world
dialectically is the nous pathetikos, the intellectus possibilis. What
faces us as astute dialectic, as exact logic in scholasticism
goes back to these old traditions. You do not cope with that
what happened in the souls of the scholastics if you do not
take into consideration this impact of ancient
traditions.
Because all that had an impact on the
scholastics, the big question arose to them that one normally
regards as the real problem of scholasticism. In that time when
humanity had still a vision that produced such things like
Platonism or its rationalistic filtrate,
Aristotelianism, in which, however, still the individual feeling
had not reached the climax, the scholastic problems were not
yet there. Since that which we call intellect and which has its
origin in the scholastic terminology on one side is just an
outflow of the individual human being. If we all think in the
same way, it is only because we all are organised equally
individually and that the mind is attached to the individual
that is the same in all human beings. They think different, as
far as they are differentiated. However, these nuances have
nothing to do with real logic. However, the real logical
and dialectic thinking is an outflow of the general human but
individually differentiated organisation.
Thus, the human being stands there as an
individuality and says to himself, in me the thoughts emerge by
which the outside world is represented internally; there the
thoughts which should give a picture of the world are arranged
from the inside. There, on one side, work mental pictures
inside of the human being that are attached to single
individual things, like to a single wolf or to a single human
being, we say to Augustine. Then, however, the human being gets
to other inner experiences, like to his dreams for which he
does not find such an outer representative at first. There he
gets to those experiences, which he forms for himself, which
are chimaeras as already the centaur was a chimaera to
scholasticism.
Then, however, are on the other side those
concepts and ideas that shimmer, actually, to both sides: the
humanity, the type or genus of lion, the type or genus of wolf,
and so on. The scholastics called these general concepts
universals (universalia). When the human beings still rose to
these universals in such a way as I have described it
yesterday, they felt them as the lowest border of the spiritual
world. To experience in such a way, it was not yet necessary to
have that individual feeling which prevailed then during the
later centuries. With individualised feeling, one said to
himself, you rise from the sensory things up to that border
where the more or less abstract, but experienced things are,
the universals humanity, lion, wolf and so on.
Scholasticism understood this very well
that one could not say just like that, these are only summaries
of the outer world, but this became a problem for it with which
it struggled. We have to develop such general concepts, such
universal concepts from our individuality. If we look out,
however, at the world, we do not have the humanity, but single
human beings, not the type wolf, but single wolves. However, on
the other side, we cannot regard that what we study as the wolf
type or the lamb type, the material that is contained in these
summaries as the only real. We cannot accept this just like
that, because then we would have to suppose that a wolf becomes
a lamb if one feeds it with lambs only long enough. Matter does
not do it; the wolf remains wolf. Nevertheless, the wolf type
is something that one cannot only equate with the material just
like that.
Today it is often a problem, which people
do not at all take seriously. Scholasticism struggled intensely
with this problem, just in its period of bloom. This problem
was directly connected with the ecclesiastical interests. We
can get an idea of it if we take into consideration the
following.
Before Albert the Great and Thomas Aquinas
appeared with their special elaboration of philosophy, already
some people had appeared like Roscelin (R. of Compiègne,
~1050-1120, French theologian and philosopher), for example,
who asserted and were absolutely of the opinion that these
general concepts, these universalia were nothing but that what
we summarise from the outer individual things. They are,
actually, mere words, mere names. — This nominalism
regarded the general things, the universalia, only as words.
However, Roscelin was dogmatically serious about nominalism,
applied it to the Trinity, and said, if — what he considered
right — this summary is only a word, the Trinity is only a
word, and the individuals are the only real: the Father, the
Son, and the Holy Spirit. Then the human mind summarises this
three: Father, Son, and Holy Spirit with a name only.
— Medieval
spirits expanded such things to the last consequences. The
church was compelled to declare this view of Roscelin a partial
polytheism and the doctrine heretic on the synod of Soissons
(1092). So one was in a certain calamity compared with
nominalism. A dogmatic interest united with a philosophical
one.
In contrast to today, one felt it as
something very real in that time, and just with the
relationship of the universalia to the individual things Thomas
and Albertus struggled spiritually; it is the most important
problem for them. Everything else is only a result as far as
everything else got a certain nuance by the way how they
positioned themselves to this problem. However, just in how
Albertus and Thomas positioned themselves to this problem, all
forces are involved which had remained as tradition of the
Areopagite, of Plotinus, Augustine, Eriugena and many others.
One still knew that there were human beings who beheld beyond
the concepts into the spiritual world, into the intellectual
world, in that world about which also Thomas speaks as about a
reality in which he realises the intellectual beings free of
matter that he calls angels. These are not mere abstractions
but real beings that have no bodies only. Thomas placed these
beings into the tenth sphere. While he imagines the earth
circled by the sphere of the moon, then of Mercury, Venus, and
sun and so on, he comes via the eighth and the ninth spheres to
the Empyrean, to the tenth sphere. He imagines all that
absolutely interspersed with intelligences, and the
intelligences to which he refers back at first send down what
they have as their lowest border as it were in such a way that
the human soul can experience it. However, in such a way as I
have pronounced it now, in this form which is more based on
Plotinism it does not appear from the mere individual feeling
to which just scholasticism had brought itself, but it remained
belief for Albert and Thomas that there is the manifestation of
these abstractions above these abstractions. For them, the
question originated, which reality do these abstractions
have?
Albert and Thomas still had an idea of the
work of the mental-spiritual on the bodily and its subsequent
mirroring if it has worked enough on the bodily. They had
images of all that. They had images also of that which the
human being becomes in his single individual life what he takes
up as impressions of the outside world and processes it with
them. Thus, the idea developed that we have the world round
ourselves, but this world is a manifestation of the spiritual.
While we look at the world, while we see the single minerals,
plants, and animals, we suspect that that is behind them, which
manifests from higher spiritual worlds.
If we consider the realms of nature with
logical decomposition and with the greatest possible mental
capacity, we get to that which the spiritual world has put into
the realms of nature. Then, however, we have to understand the
fact that we are in contact with the world by our senses. Then
we turn away from the world. We keep that as memory, which we
have taken up from the world. We look back remembering. There
only the universal like “humanity” appears to us in
its inner conceptual figure. So that Albert and Thomas say, if
you look back if your soul reflects that to you, which it has
experienced in the outside world, then the universalia live in
your soul. Then you have universalia. You develop from all
human beings whom you have met the concept of humanity. You
could live generally only in earthly names if you remembered
individual things only. While you do not at all live only in
earthly names, you must experience universalia. There you have
universalia post res, universals that live after the things in
the soul. While the human being turns his soul to the things,
he does not have the same in his soul what he has after if he
remembers it, but he is related to the things. He experiences
the spiritual in the things; he translates it to himself only
into the form of the universalia post res.
While Albert and Thomas suppose that the
human being is related to something real when he is related to
his surroundings by his intellectual capacity, so not only to
that what the wolf is because the eye sees it, the ear hears it
and so on, but because the human being can think about it, the
type “wolf” develops. He experiences something that
he grasps intellectually abstractly in the things that is also
not completely absorbed in the sensory entities. He experiences
the universalia in rebus, the universals in the
things.
One cannot distinguish this easily because
one normally thinks that that which one has in his soul at last
as a reflection is also the same in the things. No, it is not
the same in the sense of Thomas Aquinas. What the human being
experiences as an idea in his soul and explains with his mind
to himself is that by which he experiences the real, the
universal. So that the form of the universals
after the
things is different from that of the universals
in the
things, which then remain in the soul; but internally they are
the same.
There you have one of the scholastic
concepts whose clearness one normally does not consider. The
universals in the things and the universals after the things in
the soul are as regards content the same, different only after
their form.
Then, however, something else is added.
That which lives in the things individualised points to the
intellectual world again. The contents are the same, which are
in the things and after the things in the human soul, but they
have different form. Again in other form, but with the same
contents: are the universalia ante res, the universals
before the things. These are the universals as they are
included in the divine mind and in the mind of the divine
servants, the angels.
Thus, the immediate
spiritual-sensory-extrasensory view of ancient time changes
into the views which were illustrated only just with sensory
pictures because one cannot even name that which one beholds in
extrasensory way after the Areopagite if one wants to deal with
it in its true figure. One can only point to it and say, it is
not all that which the outer things are. - Thus, that which
presented itself as reality in the spiritual world to the
ancient people becomes something for scholasticism about which
just that astuteness of thinking has to decide. One had brought
down the problem that was once solved by beholding into the
sphere of thinking, of the ratio. This is the nature of the
view of Thomas and Albert, of High Scholasticism. It realises
above all that in its time the feeling of the human
individuality culminates. It realises all problems in their
rational logical figure.
The scholastic thinking struggles with this
figure of the world problems. With this struggle and thinking,
scholasticism stands in the middle of the ecclesiastical life.
On the one side, is that of which one could believe in the
thirteenth, in the twelfth centuries that one has to gain it
with the thinking, with the astute logic; on the other side
were the traditional ecclesiastical dogmas, the religious
contents.
Let us take an example how Thomas Aquinas
bears a relation to both things. There he asks, can anyone
prove the existence of God by logic? Yes, one can do it.
— He gives
a range of proofs. One of them is, for example, that he says,
we can only gain knowledge at first, while we approach the
universalia in rebus and look into the things. We cannot
penetrate by beholding — this is a simply
personal experience of this age — into the spiritual
world. We can thereby only penetrate with human forces into the
spiritual world that we become engrossed in the things, get out
the universalia in rebus. Then one is able to conclude what is
about these universalia ante res before, he says. We see the
world moved; a thing always moves the other because it itself
is moved. Thus, we come from one moved thing to another moved
thing, from this to another moved thing. This cannot go on
endlessly, but we must come to the prime mover. If he were
moved, however, we would have to look for another prime mover.
We must come to an unmoved prime mover. — With it, Thomas just
reached — and Albert concluded in the same way
— the
Aristotelian unmoved mover, the first cause. The logic thinking
is able to acknowledge God as an inevitably first being as the
inevitably unmoved prime mover.
No such line of thought leads to Trinity.
However, it is traditional. One can reach with the human
thinking only so far that one tries whether the Trinity is
preposterous. There one finds: It is not preposterous, but one
cannot prove It, one must believe It, one must accept It as
contents up to which human intellectuality cannot
rise.
Thus, scholasticism faces the so important
question at that time, how far can one reach with the human
intellect? However, by the development of time it was placed
still in quite special way in this problem, because other
thinkers preceded. They had accepted something apparently quite
absurd. They had said, something could be theologically true
and philosophically wrong. One can say flatly, it can
absolutely be that things were handed down dogmatically, as for
example the Trinity; if one contemplates then about the same
question, one comes to the contrary result. It is possible that
the intellect leads to other results than the religious
contents. —
This the other problem that the scholastics
faced: the doctrine of double truth. Both thinkers Albert and
Thomas made a point harmonising the religious contents and the
intellectual contents, searching no contradiction between that
what the intellect can think, indeed, only up to a certain
limit, and the religious contents. However, what the intellect
can think must not be contradictory to the religious contents;
the religious contents must not be contradictory to the
intellect.
This was radical in those days because the
majority of the leading church authorities adhered to the
doctrine of double truth: that — on one side
— the
human being must simply think something reasonable, as regards
content in one figure, and the religious contents can give him
it in another figure. He has to live with these two figures of
truth. — I believe that one could get a feeling for historical
development if one thought that people were with all their soul
forces in such problems few centuries ago. Since these things
still echo in our times. We still live in these problems.
Tomorrow we want to discuss how we live in these problems.
Today I wanted to characterise the nature of Thomism generally
in such a way as it lived at that time.
The main problem to Albert and Thomas was
how do the intellectual contents of the human being relate to
the religious contents? First, how can one understand what the
church specifies as faith, secondly how can one defend it
against that which is opposite to it? Albert and Thomas were
very much concerned with it. Since in Europe that did not live
exclusively which I have characterised, but there were still
other views. With the propagation of Islam, other views still
asserted themselves in Europe. Something of Manichaean views
had remained in Europe.
However, there was also the doctrine of
Averroes (Ibn Rushed, 1126-1198, Andalusian polymath) who said
there, what the human being thinks with his pure intellect does
not belong to him especially; it belongs to the whole
humanity. —
Averroes says, we do not have the intellect
for ourselves; we have a body for ourselves, but not everybody
has an intellect for himself. The person A has an own body, but
his intellect is the same as that of person B and again as that
of person C. —
One could say, to Averroes a uniform
intelligence of humanity exists, in which all individuals
submerge. They live with their heads in it as it were. When
they die, the body withdraws from this universal intelligence.
Immortality does not exist in the sense of an everlasting
individual existence after death. What lasts there is only the
universal intelligence, is only that which is common to all
human beings.
Thomas had to count on this universality of
the intellect. However, he had to position himself on the
viewpoint that the universal intellect not only combines
intimately with the individual memory in the single human
being, but that that which during life combines also with the
bodily forces form a whole that all formative, vegetative and
animal forces, as the forces of memory are attracted by the
universal intellect. Thomas imagines that the human being
attracts the universal and then draws that into the spiritual
world, which his universal has attracted so that he brings it
into the spiritual world. Hence, to Thomas and Albert not
pre-existence but post-existence can be as Aristotle had
assumed. In this respect, these thinkers continue
Aristotelianism, too.
Thus, the big logical questions of the
universals combine with the questions that concern the world
destiny of the single human beings. In the end, the general
logic nature of Thomism had an impact on all that
— even if
I wanted to characterise the cosmology of Thomas and the
enormous natural history of Albert. This logical nature
consisted of the following: we can penetrate everything with
keen logic and dialectic up to a certain border, and then we
must penetrate into the religious contents. Thus, both thinkers
faced these two things without being contradictory: what we
grasp with our intellect and what is revealed by the religious
contents can exist side by side.
What was, actually, the nature of Thomism
in history? For Thomas it is typical and important to prove
God, while he strains the intellect and at the same time, he
has to concede that one comes to an idea of God as one had it
as Jahveh rightly in the Old Testament. — That is, he gets to
that uniform God whom the Old Testament called the Jahveh God.
If one wants to get to Christ, one has to pass over to the
religious contents; one cannot get to it with that which the
human soul experiences as its own spiritual.
Something deeper was in the views of double
truth against which High Scholasticism simply had to oppose out
of the spirit of time, that one could not survey, however, in
the age in which one was surrounded everywhere by the pursuit
of rationalism, of logic. The following fact was behind
it: those who spoke of double truth did not take the view that
that which theology reveals and that which the intellect can
reach are two different things, but are two truths
provisionally, and that the human being gets to them because he
took part in the Fall of Man to the core of his soul.
This question lives as it were in the
depths of the souls until Albert and Thomas: did we not take up
the original sin also in our thinking? Does the intellect lead
us to believe other truth contents than the real truth because
the intellect has defected from spirituality?
— If we
take up Christ in our intellect, if we take up something in our
intellect that transforms this intellect, then only it consorts
with the truth, with the religious contents. The thinkers
before Thomas wanted to take the doctrine of the original sin
and the doctrine of the redemption seriously. They did not yet
have the power of thought, the logicality for that, but they
wanted to make this seriously. They presented the question to
themselves: how does Christ redeem the truth of the intellect
that is contradictory to the spiritually revealed truth in us?
How do we become Christians to the core? Since the original sin
lives in our intellect, hence, the intellect is contradictory
to the pure religious truth.
Then Albert and Thomas appeared and
supposed that it is wrong that we indulge in sinfulness of the
world if we delve purely logically into the universalia in
rebus if we take up that which is real in the things. The usual
intellect must not be sinful. The question of Christology is
contained in this question of High Scholasticism. High
Scholasticism could not solve the problem: how can the human
thinking be Christianised? How does Christ lead the human
thinking to the sphere where it can grow together with the
spiritual religious contents?
This question shook the souls of the
scholastics. Hence, it is, — although the most
perfect logical technique prevails in scholasticism
— above
all important that one does not take the results of
scholasticism, but that one looks through the answer at the big
questions which were put at that time. One had not yet advanced
so far with Christology that one could pursue the redemption
from the original sin up to the human thinking. Hence, Albert
and Thomas had to deny the intellect the right to cross the
steps over which it can enter into the spiritual world. High
Scholasticism left behind the question: how does the human
thinking evolve into a view of the spiritual world?
Even the most important result of High
Scholasticism is a question: how does one bring Christology
into thinking? How is thinking Christianised?
— Up to
his death in 1274, Thomas Aquinas could bring himself to this
question. One could answer it only suggestively in such a way
that one said, the human being penetrates into the spiritual
nature of the things to a certain degree. However, then the
religious contents have to come. Both must not be contradictory
to each other; they must be in concordance with each other. However,
the usual intellect cannot understand the contents of the
highest things on its own accord, as for example, Trinity, the
incarnation of Christ in the person Jesus and so on. The
intellect can understand only so far that it can say, the world
may have originated in time, but it may also exist from
eternity. However, the revelation says, it originated in time.
If you ask the intellect once again, you find the reasons, why
the origin in time is more reasonable.
More than one believes, that lives still in
modern science, in the whole public life, which was left of
scholasticism, indeed, in a special figure. Tomorrow we want to
speak about how alive scholasticism is still in us and which
view the modern human being has to take of that which has
survived as scholasticism.
|