10
From
Monolithic to Threefold Unity
WHEN,
some three years ago, at the request of a group of friends who were
disturbed by the social aftermath of the Great War, I published my book
The Threefold Commonwealth,
the immediate result, from my
point of view, was the profound misunderstanding it met
with on every side. This was because it was promptly classed
among the writings that have attempted, in a more or less
Utopian manner, to advocate institutions which their creators
envisaged as a sort of nostrum against the chaotic social
conditions thrown up in the course of man's recent
development. My book was intended not as a call
for reflection about possible institutions, but as a direct
appeal to human nature. It could not have been otherwise, given
the fundamentals of spiritual science, as will be apparent from
the whole tone of my lectures so far.
In
many cases, for example, what I included solely to illustrate
the central argument was taken to be my main point. In order to
demonstrate how mankind could achieve social thinking and
feeling and a social will, I gave as an example the way the
circulation of capital might be transformed so that it
would no longer be felt by many people to be oppressive, as
frequently happens at present. I had to say one or two things
about the price mechanism, the value of labour, and so on. All
this solely by way of illustration. Anyone who seeks to
influence human life as a whole must surely hearken to it
first, in order to derive from it the human remedies for its
aberrations, instead of extolling a few stereotyped
formulae and recommending their indiscriminate
application.
For
anyone who has reacted to the social life of Europe in the last
thirty or forty years, not with some preconceived attitude or
other but with an open mind, it is clear above all that what is
needed in the social sphere today is already prefigured in the
unconscious will of mankind in Europe. Everywhere we find these
unconscious tendencies. They exist already in men's souls, and
all that is needed is to put them into words.
That is what made me give in to my friends and write the book I
have mentioned. My purpose was to attempt, out of the sense of
reality which — in all modesty we can say this —
spiritual science instils in man, to observe what has been
going on in Europe in recent years, beneath the surface of
events and institutions, among all ranks and classes of
society. What I wanted to say was not: I think that this or
that is correct, but rather: This or that is secretly desired
by the unconscious, and all that is required is for us to
become conscious of the direction in which mankind is really
trying to go. The reason for many of our social abuses today is
precisely that this unconscious movement contradicts in
part what mankind has worked out intellectually and embodied in
institutions. Our institutions, in fact, run counter to what
men today desire in the depths of their hearts.
There is another reason why I do not believe there is any real
point today in simply advocating some particular Utopian
institution. In the historical development of mankind in
the civilized world we have entered a phase where any judgment
about relationships among and between men, however
shrewd, can be of no significance unless men accept it —
unless it is something towards which they are themselves
impelled, though for the most part unconsciously.
If
we wish to reflect at all upon these things at the present
time, therefore, I believe we must reckon with the democratic
mood which has emerged in the course of man's history, and
which now exists in the depths of men's souls — the
democratic feeling that something is really valuable in the
social sphere only if it aims, not at saying democratic things,
but at enabling men to express their own opinions and put them
over. My main concern was thus to answer the question:
Under what conditions are men really in a position to give
expression to their opinions and their will in social
matters?
When we consider the world around us from a social
standpoint, we cannot help concluding that, although it
would be easy to point to a great deal that should be
different, the obstacles to change are legion, so that what we
may know perfectly well and be perfectly willing to put into
practice, cannot be realized! There are differences of rank and
class, and the gulfs between classes. These gulfs cannot be
bridged simply by having a theory of how to bridge them; they
result from the fact that — as I stressed so much
yesterday — the will, which is the true centre of man's
nature, is involved in the way we have grown into our rank or
class or any other social grouping. And again, if you look for
the obstacles which, in recent times, with their
complicated economic conditions, have ranged themselves
alongside the prejudices, feelings and impulses of class
consciousness, you will find them in economic institutions
themselves. We are born into particular economic institutions
and cannot escape from them. And there also exists, I would
say, a third kind of obstacle to true social co-operation among
men; for those who might perhaps, as leaders, be in a
position to exert that profound influence of which I have been
speaking, have other limitations — limitations that
derive from certain dogmatic teachings and feelings about life.
While many men cannot escape from economic limitations and
limitations of class, many others cannot rise above their
conceptual and intellectual limitations. All this is already
widespread in life and results in a great deal of
confusion.
If,
however, we now attempt to reach a clear understanding of
everything which, through these obstacles and gulfs, has
affected the unconscious depths of men's souls in recent
decades, we become aware that in fact the essentials of the
social problem are not by any means located where they
are usually looked for.
They reside in the fact that there has
arisen in the recent development of civilized man, alongside
the technology which is so complicating life, a faith in the
supreme power of the monolithic state. This faith became
stronger and stronger as the nineteenth century wore on. It
became so strong and so fixed that it has never been shaken
even in the face of the many shattering verdicts on the
organization of society that multitudes of people have
reached.
With this dogmatic faith that thus takes hold of men,
something else is associated. Through their faith, people
seek to cling to the proposition that the object of their faith
represents a kind of sovereign remedy, enabling them to decide
which is the best political system, and also — I will not
say to conjure up paradise, but at least to believe that they
are creating the best institutions conceivable.
This attitude, however, leaves out of account something that
obtrudes itself particularly on those who observe life
realistically, as it has been observed here in the last
few days. Anyone who, just because he is compelled to mould his
ideas to the spiritual world, acquires a true sense of reality,
will discover that the best institutions that can be devised
for a particular period never remain valid beyond that period
and that what is true of man's natural organism is also true of
the social organism.
I
am not going to play the boring game of analogies, but by way
of illustration I should like to indicate what can be
discovered about society from a study of the human
organism. We can never say that the human organism — or,
for that matter, the animal or plant — will display only
an upward development. If organisms are to flourish and to
develop their powers from within themselves, they must also be
capable of ageing and of dying off. Anyone who studies the
human organism in detail finds that this atrophying is going on
at every moment. Forces of ascent, growth and maturation are
present continuously; but so too are the forces of
decomposition. And man owes a great deal to them. To overcome
materialism completely, he must direct his attention to just
these forces of decomposition in the human organism. He must
seek, everywhere in the human organ, ism, the points at which
matter is disintegrating as a result of the process of
organization. And he will find that the development of
man's spiritual life is closely linked to the disintegration of
matter. We can only understand the human organism by
perceiving, side by side with the forces of ascent,
growth and maturation, the continuous process of decay.
I
have given this simply by way of illustration, but it really
does illustrate what the impartial observer will
discover in the social organism too. It is true that the social
organism does not die, and to this extent it differs from the
human organism; but it changes, and forces of
advancement and decline are inherent in it. You can only
comprehend the social organism when you know that, even if you
put into practice the wisest designs and establish, in a given
area of social life, something that has been learnt from
conditions as they really are, it will after a time reveal
moribund forces, forces of decline, because men with their
individual personalities are active in it. What is correct for
a given year will have changed so greatly, twenty years later,
that it will already contain the seeds of its own decline. This
sort of thing, it is true, is often appreciated, in an abstract
way. But in this age of intellectualism, people do not go
beyond abstractions, however much they may fancy themselves as
practical thinkers. People in general, we thus discover, may
admit that the social organism contains forces of dissolution
and decline, that it must always be in process of
transformation, and that forces of decline must always operate
alongside the constructive ones. Yet at the point where these
people affect the social order through their intentions and
volition, they do not recognize in practice what they have
admitted in theory.
Thus, in the social order that existed before the Great War,
you could see that, whenever capitalism formed part of an
upward development, it resulted in a certain satisfaction
even for the masses. When in any branch of life capitalism was
expanding, wages rose. As the process advanced further
and further, therefore, and capitalism was able to operate with
increasing freedom, you could see that wages and opportunities
for the employment of labour rose steadily. But it was less
noticed that this upward movement contained at the same time
other social factors, which move in a parallel direction and
involve the appearance of forces of decline. Thus with
rising wages, for instance, conditions of life would be
such that the rising wages themselves would gradually create a
situation in which the standard of life was in fact raised
relatively little. Such things were, of course, noticed, but
not with any lively and practical awareness of the social
currents involved.
Hence today, when we stand at a milestone in history, it is the
fundamentals, not the surface phenomena of social life that we
must consider. And so we are led to the distinct branches that
go to make up our social life.
One
of these is the spiritual life of mankind. This spiritual life
— though we cannot, of course, consider it in isolation
from the rest of social life — has its own determinants,
which are connected with human personalities. The
spiritual life draws its nourishment from the human individuals
active in any period, and all the rest of social life depends
on this. Consider the changes that have occurred in many social
spheres simply because someone or other has made some
invention or discovery. But when you ask: How did this
invention or discovery come about? then you have to look into
the depths of men's souls. You see how they have undergone a
certain development and have been led to find, in the stillness
of their rooms, so to speak, something that afterwards
transformed broad areas of social life. Ask yourselves what is
the significance, for social life as a whole, of the fact that
the differential and integral calculus was discovered by
Leibniz. If from this standpoint you consider
realistically the influence of spiritual life on social
life, you will come to see that, because spiritual life has its
own determinants, it represents a distinctive branch of social
life as a whole.
If
asked to define its special quality, we would say: Everything
that is really to flourish in the spiritual life of mankind
must spring from man's innermost productive power. And we
inevitably find that the elements that develop freely in the
depths of the human soul are what is most favourable for social
life as a whole.
We
are, however, also affected by another factor, one that has
become increasingly apparent in recent decades. It is the
impulse — subsequently absorbed into a faith in the
omnipotence of political life — for civilized humanity,
out of the depths of its being, to become more and more
democratic. In other words, aspirations are present in the
masses of humanity for every human being to have a voice in
determining human institutions. This democratic trend may be
sympathetic or unsympathetic to us — that is not a matter
of primary importance. What matters is that the trend has shown
itself to be a real force in the history of modern man. But in
looking at this democratic trend, we are particularly struck,
if our thinking is realistic, by the way in which, out of an
inner pressure, out of the spiritual life of Middle Europe
ideas evolved, in the noblest minds, about the political
community of men.
I
do not mean to suggest that today we must still attach any
special value to the “closed commercial state” put
forward by one of the noblest of Germans. We need pay attention
less to the content of Fichte's thought than to his noble
purpose. I should, however, like to emphasize the emergence in
a very popular form, at the end of the eighteenth and beginning
of the nineteenth century, of what we may call the search
for concepts of natural law. At that time, certain
eminent and high-minded men devoted themselves to the question:
What is the relation of man to man? And what in general is
man's innermost essence, socially speaking? They believed that,
by a right understanding of man, they would also be able to
find what is the law for men. They called this “the law
of reason” or “natural law.” They believed
that they could work out rationally which are the best legal
institutions, the ones under which men can best prosper. You
need only look at Rotteck's work to see how the idea of natural
law still operated for many writers in the first half of the
nineteenth century.
In
opposition to this, however, there emerged in the first half of
the nineteenth century in Europe the historical school
of law. This was inspired by the conviction that you cannot
determine the law among men by a process of reason.
Yet
this historical school of law failed to notice what it is that
really makes any excogitation of a rational law unfruitful;
they failed to see that, under the influence of the age of
intellectualism, a certain sterility had invaded the spiritual
life of mankind. Instead, the opponents of natural law
concluded that men are not competent to discover, from within
their souls, anything about law, and that therefore law must be
studied historically. You must look, they said, at man's
historical development, and see how, from customs and
instinctive relationships, systems of law have resulted.
The
historical study of law? Against such a study Nietzsche's
independent spirit rebelled in
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life.
He believed that, if we are always
looking solely at what has exercised mankind historically, we
cannot be productive and evolve fruitful ideas for the
present; the elemental forces that live in man must revolt
against the historical sense, in order that, from these forces,
there may develop a constitution of social relationships.
Among leading personalities there developed in the nineteenth
century, at the height of intellectualism, a battle over the
real foundations of law. And this also involved a battle over
the foundations of the state. At least, it was generally
assumed so at the time. For the state is, ultimately, no more
than the sum total of the individual institutions in which the
forces of law reside. The fact that the ability to detect the
foundations of law had been lost also meant, therefore, that it
was no longer possible to attain clarity about the real
nature of the state. That is why we find — not simply in
theory, but in real life as well — that, during the
nineteenth century, the essence of the state became, for
countless people, including the masses, a problem that they had
to solve.
Yet
this applied more particularly, I would say, to the upper and
more conscious reaches of civilized humanity. From
underground, the democratic attitude I have described was
tunnelling its way towards the surface. Its appearance, if
properly understood, leads us to conceive the problem of
the nature of law in a way that is much deeper and much closer
to reality than is usual today. There are many people today who
think it self-evident that, from within the individual, you can
somehow arrive at what is actually the law in a given sphere.
Modern jurists, it is true, soon lose sight of the ground when
they attempt to do so; and what they find, when they
philosophize in this way or indeed think they are reflecting in
a practical way upon life, is that law loses its content for
them and becomes an empty form. And then they say: This empty
form must be given a content; the economic element must
be decanted into it.
On
the one hand, then, there exists a definite sense of man's
powerlessness to reach a concept or feeling of law from within
himself. On the other hand, we do continually attempt to derive
the nature of law from man himself. And yet the democratic
attitude jibs at any such attempt. What it says is that there
is no such thing as a general abstract determination of law;
there is only the possibility that the members of a particular
community may reach an understanding and say to one
another: “You want this from me, I want that from
you,” and that they will then come to some agreement
about their resulting relations. Here, law springs
exclusively from the reality of what men desire from one
another. There cannot therefore be any such thing as a law of
reason; and the “historical law” that has come into
being can always do so again if only we find the right
foundation for it. On this foundation, men can enter into a
relationship in which, through mutual understanding, they
can evolve a realistic law. “I want to have my say when
law is being made” — so speaks the democratic
attitude. Anyone, then, who wishes to write theoretically about
the nature of law cannot spin it out of himself; he just has to
look at the law that appears among men, and record it. In
natural science too, our view of the phenomenal world does not
allow us to fashion the laws of nature out of our head; we
allow things to speak to us and shape natural laws accordingly.
We assume that what we try to encompass in the laws of
nature is already created, but that what exists in the legal
sphere has to be created among men. This is a different stage
of life. In this realm, man stands in the position of creator
— but as a social being, alongside other men — so
that a life may come about that shall infuse the meaning of
human evolution into the social order. This is precisely the
democratic spirit.
The
third thing that presents itself to people today and calls for
social reorganization is the complicated economic pattern which
has developed in recent times, and which I need not describe,
since it has been accurately described by many people. We can
only say: This economic pattern certainly results from factors
quite different from those controlling the other two fields of
the social organism — spiritual life, where all that is
fruitful in the social order must spring from the individual
human personality (only the creativity of the individual can
make the right contribution here to the social order as a
whole), and the sphere of law, where law, and with it the body
politic, can only derive from an understanding between men.
Both factors — the one applicable to spiritual life and
the other to political and legal life — are absent from
economic life.
In
economic life, what may come about cannot be determined by the
individual. In the nineteenth century, when intellectualism
enjoyed such a vogue among men, we can see how various
important people — I do not say this ironically —
people in the most varied walks of life, gave their opinion
about one thing and another — people who were well placed
in economic life, and whose judgment one would have expected to
trust. When they came to express an opinion about something
outside their own speciality, something that affected
legislation, you often found that what they said, about the
practical effect of the gold standard for example, was
significant and sensible. If you follow what went on in the
various economic associations during the period when certain
countries were going over to the gold standard, you will be
astonished at the amount of common sense that was generated.
But when you go further and examine how the things that had
been prophesied then developed, you will see, for
instance, that some very important person or other
considered that, under the influence of the gold standard,
customs barriers would disappear! The exact opposite
occurred!
The
fact is that, in the economic sphere, common sense, which can
help one a very great deal in the spiritual sphere, is not
always a safe guide. You gradually discover that, as far as
economic life is concerned, the individual cannot reach
valid judgments at all. Judgments here can only be arrived at
collectively, through the co-operation of many people in
very different walks of life. It is not just theory, but
something that will have to become practical wisdom, that truly
valid judgments here can arise only from the consonance of many
voices.
The
whole of social life thus falls into three distinct fields. In
that of spiritual life, it is for the individual to speak. In
the democratic sphere of law, it is for all men to speak, since
what matters here is the relationship of man to man on a basis
of simple humanity — where any human being can express a
view. In the sphere of economic life, neither the judgment of
the individual, nor that which flows from the un-sifted
judgments of all men, is possible. In this sphere, the
individual contributes, to the whole, expert knowledge and
experience in his own particular field; and then, from
associations, a collective judgment can emerge in the proper
manner. It can do so only if the legitimate judgments of
individuals can rub shoulders with one another. For this,
however, the associations must be so constituted as to contain
views that can rub shoulders and then produce a
collective judgment. — The whole of social life,
therefore, falls into these three regions. This is not deduced
from some Utopian notion, but from a realistic observation of
life.
At
the same time, however — and this must be emphasized over
and over again — the social organism, whether small or
large, contains within itself, together with constructive
forces, also the forces of decline. Thus everything that we
feed into social life also contains its own destructive forces.
A constant curative process is needed in the social
organism.
When we look at spiritual life from this standpoint, we can
even say, on the lines of the observations put forward here in
the last few days: in Oriental society, the life of the spirit
was universally predominant. All individual phenomena —
even those in political and in economic life — derived
from the impulses of spiritual life, in the way I have been
describing. If now you consider the functioning of society, you
find that for a given period — every period is different
— there flow forth from the life of the spirit impulses
that inform the social structures; economic associations come
into being on the basis of ideas from spiritual life, and the
state founds institutions out of spiritual life. But you can
also see that spiritual life has a constant tendency to develop
forces of decline, or forces from which such forces of decline
can arise. If we could see spiritual life in its all-powerful
ramifications, we should perceive how it constantly impels men
to separate into ranks and classes. And if you study the
reasons for the powerful hold of the caste system in the
Orient, you will find that it is regarded as a necessary
concomitant of the fact that society sprang from spiritual
impulses. Thus we see that Plato still stresses how, in the
ideal state, humanity must be divided into the producer class,
the scholar class and the warrior class — must be
divided, that is, into classes. If you analyse the reasons for
this, you will find that differences of rank and class follow
from the gradation which is implicit in the supreme power of
spiritual life. Within the classes, there then appears once
more the sense of human personality, which experiences them as
prejudicial to the social system. There thus always exist,
within spiritual life, opportunities for the appearance of
gulfs between classes, ranks, even castes.
We
now turn to the field of politics, and it is here
especially that we must look for what I have been calling
the subjection of labour, in the course of man's
development, to the unitary social organism. It is precisely
because theocracy, coming from Asia, developed into a political
system that is now dominated by concepts of law, that the
problem of labour arises. In so far as each individual was to
attain his rights, there developed a demand for labour to
be properly integrated into society. Yet as law cast off its
links with religion and moved further and further towards
democracy, there insinuated itself more and more into men's
lives a certain formalized element of social thinking.
Law
developed in fact from what one individual has to say to
another. It cannot be spun out of a man's own reasoning
faculty. Yet from the mutual intercourse of men's reasoning
faculties — if I may so put it — a true life of law
arises. Law is inclined, therefore, towards logic and
formalized thought. But humanity, on its way down the ages,
goes through phases of one-sided development. It went through
the one-sided phase we call theocracy, and similarly, later on,
it goes through the one we call the state. When it does so, the
logical element of social life is cultivated — the
element of excogitation. Just think how much human
ratiocination has been expended on law in the course of
history!
In
consequence of this, however, mankind also proceeds
towards the capacity for abstraction. You can sense how
human thinking, under the influence of the principle of law,
becomes increasingly abstract. What mankind acquires in one
sphere, however, is extended at certain periods to the whole of
human life. In this way, I would say, even religion was, as I
have indicated earlier, absorbed into the juridical
current. The God of the Orient, universal legislator and giver
of Grace to men, became a God of judgment. Universal law in the
cosmos became universal justice. We see this especially
in the Middle Ages. As a result, however, there was imported
into men's habits of thought and feeling a kind of abstraction.
People tried increasingly to run their lives by means of
abstractions.
In
this way, abstraction came to extend to religion and spiritual
life, on the one hand, and economic life, on the other. Men
began to trust more and more in the omnipotence of the state,
with its abstract administrative and constitutional activity.
Increasingly, men regarded it as progressive for spiritual
life, in the shape of education, to be absorbed completely into
the sphere of the state. Here, however, it could not avoid
being caught up in abstract relationships, such as are
associated with the law. Economic activity, too, was absorbed
into something that was felt to be appropriate when the state
is in control. And at the time when the modern concept of the
economy was formed, it was the general opinion that the state
should be the power above all which determined the proper
organization of economic activity. In this way, however, we
subject the other branches of life to the rule of abstraction.
This statement itself may sound abstract, but in fact it is
realistic. Let me demonstrate this with regard to
education.
In
our age, where common sense is so commonplace, men can come
together in a committee, in order to work out the best
pedagogic procedures. When they meet together in this way and
work out how education should be organized and just what should
be covered by this class or the other in the timetable, they
will — and I say this without irony — work out
first-rate things. I am convinced that, so long as they are
fairly sensible — and most people are nowadays —
they will draw up ideal programmes. We live — or
did live at least, for some attempt is being made to escape
— in the age of planning. There is certainly no shortage
of programmes, of guiding principles in any given area of life!
Society after society is founded and draws up its
programme: a thing is to be done in this way or that. I
have no objection to these programmes, and indeed I am
convinced that no one who criticizes them could draw up better
ones. But that is not the point. What we work out, we can
impose on reality; only reality will not then be suitable for
men to live in. And that is what really matters.
And
so we have reached a kind of dead end in the matter of
programmes. We have seen recently how, with the best and
noblest of intentions for the development of mankind, a man
drew up one of these programmes for the entire civilized world,
in fourteen admirable points. It was shattered immediately it
came into contact with reality. From the fate of Wilson's
fourteen abstract points — which were the product
of shrewd intellects, but were not in accordance with
reality, not quarried from life itself — an enormous
amount can be learnt.
In
education and teaching, it is not programmes that matter, for
they after all are only a product of politics and law. You can,
with the best of intentions, issue a directive that this or
that must be done; in reality, however, we are dealing with a
staff composed of teachers with a particular set of capacities.
You have to take these capacities into account in a vital way.
You cannot realize a programme. Only what springs from the
individual personalities of the teachers can be realized.
You must have a feeling for these personalities. You will need
to decide afresh, each day, out of the immediate life of the
individual, what is to happen. You will not be able to set up a
comprehensive programme: this remains an abstraction.
Only out of life itself can something be created. Let us
imagine an extreme case: In some subject or other, there are
available only teachers of mediocre ability. If, at a time when
they were free of teaching and had nothing to do but think,
these teachers were to work out pedagogic aims and issue
regulations, even they would no doubt come up with something
extremely sensible. But the actual business of teaching is
another thing altogether; all that matters there is their
capabilities as whole men. It is one thing to reckon with what
derives solely from the intellect, and quite another to reckon
with life itself. For the intellect has the property of
overreaching; fundamentally, it is always seeking to encompass
the boundless nature of the world. In real life, it should
remain a tool in a specific concrete activity.
Now
if we reflect particularly on the fact that what takes place
between human beings, when they confront each other as equals,
can turn into law — then we must say: The things humanity
develops are all right when they are the outcome of
contemporary abstraction; for that is how men do feel. Men
establish legal relations with one another, based on certain
abstract concepts of man, and they arrive at these legal
relations through the circumstance that they stand together on
democratic ground. Yet it will never be possible in this way to
create for the whole of humanity something that springs
directly from the life of the individual; but only what is
common to the whole of humanity. In other words: to be quite
honest, there cannot well up, from a democratic foundation,
what ought to spring from the individuality of man within
spiritual life.
We
must, of course, realize that a belief in the predominance of
law and politics was a historical phenomenon, and that it was
historically legitimate for modern states, at the time when
they came into being, to take over responsibility for the
schools, since they had to take them away from other
authorities who were no longer administering them properly. You
should not try to correct history retrospectively. Yet we must
also perceive clearly that in recent years there has developed
a movement to shape the life of the spirit once again as
something independent, so that it contains within itself its
own social structure and its own administration; and also that
what takes place in individual classes can stem from the vital
life of the teacher and not from adherence to some regulation
or other. Despite the fact that it has been regarded as a step
forward to hand over spiritual life, and with it schools, to
the state, we must make up our minds to reverse this trend.
Only then will it be possible for the free human personality to
achieve expression within spiritual life, including the sphere
of education. Nor need anyone be afraid that authority would
suffer in consequence! Where a productive influence is
exercised by the human personality, the individuals concerned
yearn for a natural authority. We can see this at work in the
Waldorf School. Everyone there is pleased when one person or
the other can be his authority, because he needs what the
individual talents of that person have to offer.
It
then remains possible for politics and law to function on a
democratic basis.
Here again, however, the fact is that, simply through its
tendency to abstractness, the state contains within
itself the germ of what are later to become forces of decline.
Anyone who studies how, by virtue of the existence of this
tendency, what men do in the political and legal sphere cannot
help becoming increasingly cut off from any concrete interest
in a particular aspect of life, will also realize that it is
precisely political life which provides the basis for the
abstractness that has become increasingly apparent in
connection with the circulation of capital. The formation of
capital nowadays is much criticized by the masses. But the
campaign against it, as conducted at present, reveals an
ignorance of the true situation. Anyone who wanted to abolish
capital or capitalism would have to abolish modern economic and
social life as a whole, because this social life cannot survive
without the division of labour, and this in turn implies the
formation of capital. In recent times, this has been
demonstrated particularly by the fact that a large part of
capital is represented by the means of production. The
essential point, however, is that in the first place capitalism
is a necessary feature of modern life, while on the other hand,
precisely when it becomes nationalized, it leads to the
divorce of money from specific concrete activities. In the
nineteenth century, this was carried so far that now what
actually circulates in social life is as completely divorced
from specific concrete activities, as the bloodless ideas of a
thinker who lives only in abstractions are divorced from real
life. The economic element that is thus divorced from specific
activities is money. When I have a certain sum in my pocket,
this sum can represent any given object in the economy or even
in spiritual life. This element stands in the same relation to
specific concrete activities as a wholly general concept does
to specific experiences. That is why crises must inevitably
arise within the social order.
These crises have been extensively studied. A theory of crises
is prominent in Marxism, for example. The mistake lies in
attributing the crises to a single chain of causes, whereas in
fact they are due to two underlying trends. There may be too
much capital, in which case the excess that is circulating
gives rise to crises. It may also happen, however, that too
little capital is available, and this also leads to crises.
These are two different types of crisis. Such things are not
examined objectively, even by political economists today. The
fact is that, in the real world, a single phenomenon may have
very varied causes.
We
can see, therefore, that, just as spiritual life tends to
develop forces of decline arising from differences of
class, rank and caste, so too the life that is moving towards
abstractions — and rightly so — includes a
tendency, on the one hand to develop the constructive forces
that are part of a legitimate formation of capital, but on the
other hand to give rise to crises because capitalism results in
abstract economic activity, in which a capital sum can be used
indifferently for one purpose or another.
When people realize this, they become social reformers and work
out something that is designed to produce a cure. But now you
come up against the fact that, although the individual does
shape economic life by contributing his experiences through the
appropriate associations, he cannot as a single
individual determine the shape of economic life. That
is why, when we go beyond the political and legal and the
spiritual spheres, I have posited the association as a
necessity of economic life.
In
this connection, I was struck by the fact that, when I was
speaking in Germany to a fairly small group of working-men
about associations, they said to me: We have heard of very many
things, but we don't really know what associations are; we
haven't really heard anything about them. An association is not
an organization and not a combination. It comes into being
through the conflux of the individuals within the economy. The
individual does not have to adopt something handed out from a
central body, but is able to contribute the knowledge and
ability he has in his own field. From a collaboration in which
each gives of his best, and where what is done springs from the
agreement of many — only from such associations does
economic life in general derive.
Associations of this kind will come into being. They are
certain to arise, I have no doubt of that. To anyone who
tells me this is Utopian, my reply is: I know that these
associations spring only from subconscious forces in man. We
can, however, foster them by the reason and make them arise
more quickly, or we can wait until they arise from necessity.
They will link together those engaged in production and
commerce, and the consumers. Only production,
distribution and consumption will have any part in them.
Labour will come more and more under the aegis of law.
On the question of labour, men must reach an understanding in a
democratic manner. In consequence, labour will be insulated
from the only force which can be effective in economic life
— that which is the resultant of a collective
judgment in associations linking producers and consumers,
together with distributors.
In
the sphere of economic life, therefore — in the
associations — goods alone will have a part to play. This
will, in turn, have an important consequence: we shall cease
entirely to have any fixed notions of the price and value of an
article. Instead, we shall say: the price and value of an
article is something that changes with the surrounding
circumstances. Price and value will be set by the collective
judgment of the associations. I cannot go into this at
length here; but you can follow it up in my book
The Threefold Commonwealth.
I
have been trying to outline how, from our observation, we
become aware that social life falls into three regions, shaped
by quite distinct and different factors: spiritual life, legal
and political life, and economic life. Within the recent
development of civilization, these three have been achieving
some degree of independence. To understand this independence,
and gradually to allocate to each field what belongs to it, so
that they may collaborate in an appropriate manner, is
the important task today.
Men
have reflected in very different ways on this tripartite
articulation of the social organism. And, as my
Threefold Commonwealth
began to attract attention here and
there, people pointed out various things in it that were
already foreshadowed by earlier writers. Now I do not wish to
raise the question of priority at all. What matters is not
whether it was a particular individual who discovered
something, but how it can become established in life. If a lot
of people were to hit on it, one would be only too pleased. One
point must be noted, however: when Montesquieu in France
outlines a sort of tripartite division of the social organism,
it is merely a division. He points out that the three sections
have quite different determinants, and that we must therefore
keep them separate. This is not the tenor of my book. I do not
try to distinguish spiritual life, legal life and economic
life, in the way that you would distinguish in man the nervous
system, the respiratory system and the metabolic system, if at
the same time you wanted to insist that they are three systems,
each separate from the other. In itself, such a division
leads nowhere; you can advance only by seeing how these three
different systems function together, and how they best combine
into a single whole by each operating on its own terms. The
same is true of the social organism. When we know how to
establish spiritual life, political and legal life, and
economic life on the terms that are native to each, and how to
let them run off their native sources of power, then the unity
of the social organism will also follow. And then you will find
that certain forces of decline are released within each of
these fields, but that they are countered through collaboration
with other fields. This suggests, not a tripartite
division of the social organism, as in Montesquieu, but
a threefold articulation of it, which yet comes together
in the unity of the social organism as a whole, by virtue of
the fact that, after all, every individual belongs to all three
regions. The human personality — and that is what is
all-important — inhabits this triform social organism in
such a way as to unite the three parts.
Especially in the light of what I have been saying, then, we
find that what we must aim at is not a division but an
articulation of the social organism, in order that a
satisfying unity may be attained. And in a more superficial
way, you can also see that, for over a century, mankind in
Europe has tended to seek such an articulation. It will come
about, even if men do not consciously desire it; unconsciously,
they will so conduct themselves, in the economic,
spiritual, and political and legal spheres, that it will come
about. It is demanded by the actual evolution of humanity.
And
we can also point to the fact that the impulses which
correspond to these three different aspects of life entered
European civilization at a particular moment in the shape
of three quintessential ideals, three maxims for social life.
At the end of the eighteenth century in Western Europe, a
demand spread abroad for liberty, equality and fraternity. Is
there anyone who bears with the development that has taken
place in modern times, who would deny that these maxims contain
three quintessential human ideals? Yet on the other hand
it must be admitted that there were many people in the
nineteenth century who argued ingeniously against the view that
a unified social organism or state can exist if it has
to realize these three ideals all together. Several persuasive
books were written to demonstrate that liberty, equality
and fraternity cannot be completely and simultaneously combined
within the state. And one must admit that these ingenious
arguments do evoke a certain scepticism. In consequence,
people once again found themselves face to face with a
contradiction imposed by life itself.
Yet
it is not the nature of life to avoid contradictions; life is
contradictory at every point. It involves the repeated
reconciliation of the contradictions that are thrown up.
It is in the propagation and reconciliation of
contradictions that life consists. It is, therefore, absolutely
right that the three great ideals of liberty, equality and
fraternity should have been put forward. Because it was
believed in the nineteenth century, however, and right down to
our own times, that everything must be centrally organized,
people went off the rails. They failed to perceive that it is
of no importance to argue about the way in which the means of
production be employed, capitalism developed, etc. What matters
is to enable men to arrange their social system to accord with
the innermost impulses of their being. And in this connection
we must say: We need to comprehend, in a vital way, how liberty
should function in spiritual life, as the free and productive
development of the personality; how equality should function in
the political and legal sphere, where all, jointly and in a
democratic manner, must evolve what is due to each
individual; and how fraternity should function in the
associations, as we have called them. Only by viewing life in
this way do we see it in its true perspective.
When we do so, however, we perceive that the theoretical belief
that it is possible to accommodate all three ideals
uniformly in the monolithic state has led to a
contradiction within life. The three ideals of liberty,
equality and fraternity can be understood in a vital way only
when we realize that liberty has to prevail in spiritual life,
equality in the political and legal sphere, and fraternity in
the economic sphere. And this not in a sentimental manner, but
in a way that leads to social systems within which men can
experience their human dignity and their human worth. If we
understand that the unified organism can come into being only
when out of liberty spirit develops in a productive way, when
equality functions in the political and legal sphere and
fraternity in the economic one, in the associations, then
we shall rise above the worst social dilemmas of the
present.
For
man gains a spiritual life that is rooted in truth only out of
what can freely spring from him as an individual; and this
truth can only make its appearance if it flows directly from
men's hearts. The democratic tendency will not rest easy until
it has established equality in the political and legal sphere.
This can be achieved by rational processes; if not, we expose
ourselves to revolutions. And in the economic field, fraternity
must exist in the associations.
When this happens, the law — which is founded on a human
relationship in which like meets like — will be a vital
law. Any other kind of law turns into convention. True law must
spring from the meeting of men, otherwise it becomes
convention.
And
true fraternity can found a way of life only if this derives
from economic conditions themselves, through the medium of the
associations; otherwise, the collaboration of men within groups
will establish not a way of life, but a routine existence, such
as is almost invariably the case at the present time.
Only when we have learnt to perceive the chaotic nature of
social conditions that spring from the predominance of
catchwords instead of truth in the spiritual sphere,
convention instead of law in the political and legal sphere,
and routine instead of a way of life in the economic sphere,
shall we be seeing the problem clearly. And we shall then
be following the only path that affords a correct approach to
the social problem.
People will be rather shocked, perhaps, to find that I am not
going to approach the social problem in the way many people
think it ought to be approached. What I am saying now,
however, is based solely on what can be learnt from
reality itself with the aid of spiritual science, which is
everywhere orientated towards reality. And it turns out that
the fundamental questions of social life today are these:
How
can we, by a correct articulation of the social organism, move
from the all too prevalent catch-word (which is thrown up by
the human personality when its creative spirit is
subordinated to another) to truth, from convention to
law, and from a routine existence to a real way of life?
Only when we realize that a threefold social organism is
necessary for the creation of liberty, equality and fraternity,
shall we understand the social problem aright. We shall then be
able to link up the present time properly with the eighteenth
century. And Middle Europe will then be able, out of its
spiritual life, to reply, to the Western European demand for
liberty, equality, fraternity: Liberty in spiritual life,
equality in political and legal life, and fraternity in
economic life.
This will mean much for the solution of the social problem, and
we shall be able to form some idea of how the three spheres in
the social organism can collaborate, through liberty, equality
and fraternity, in our recovery from the chaotic situation
— spiritual, legal, and economic — which we are in
today.
THE
END
|