|
|
|
Rudolf Steiner e.Lib
|
|
Man as a Being of Sense and Perception
Rudolf Steiner e.Lib Document
|
|
Man as a Being of Sense and Perception
Development of Human Soul Life since the Fourth Century B.C.
Schmidt Number: S-4548
On-line since: 27th June, 2002
YESTERDAY I tried to draw the line between those sensory experiences
which belong to the upper man, constituting man's essential
soul life, and those which are more connected with the lower
man, the content of which stands in much the same relationship to
human consciousness as external experiences proper, only that these
experiences take place within man. We have seen that the ego-sense,
the sense of thought, the word-sense, the sense of hearing, the sense
of warmth and the sense of sight are all experiences of the former
kind, and that we then plunge into two regions in which man's inner
experiences resemble external experiences so far as his consciousness
is concerned; these two regions are, first, the senses of taste and
smell, and then the other four, the inner senses proper.
You see at once how difficult it is to make do with the rough and
ready terms which are suitable enough for descriptions of the external
world, but quite inadequate directly one comes to consider the being
of man and the structure of the world within him.
But at all events, if we are quite clear about this distinction
between the upper and the lower man, both of which in a certain way
are representative of the world-process, we shall also be well aware
that there is a cleavage in our experience, that our relationship to
the one pole of our experience is utterly different from our
relationship to the other. Unless we grasp this division of the human
being thoroughly we shall never reach full clarity about the most
important problem of the present and of the near future, the problem
of the relationship of the moral world, within which we live with our
higher nature, within which we have responsibility, to that other
world with which we are also connected, the world of natural
necessity.
We know that in recent centuries, since the middle of the fifteenth
century, human progress has consisted predominantly in the development
of ideas about natural necessity. Humanity has paid less attention in
recent centuries to the other pole of human experience. Anyone who is
at all able to read the signs of the times, anyone who knows how to
recognise the task of the times, is quite clear that there is a deep
cleft between what is called moral necessity and what is called
natural necessity.
This cleavage has arisen primarily because a great many of those who
believe themselves to represent the spiritual life of to-day
distinguish between a certain sphere of experience that can be grasped
by science, by knowledge, and another sphere that is said to be
grasped only by faith. And you know that in certain quarters only what
can be brought under strict natural law is acknowledged to be really
scientific; and another kind of certitude is postulated for all that
falls within the sphere of the moral life, a certitude which only
claims to be the certitude of faith. There are circumstantial theories
as to the necessary distinction that has to be made between real
scientific certainty and the certitude of belief.
All these distinctions, these theories, have come about because to-day
we have very little historical consciousness; we pay very little
attention to the conditions under which our present soul-content came
into being. I have often given the classic example of this. I have
often told you that to-day, when philosophers speak of the distinction
between body and soul, they think they are using a concept which
derives from original observation, whereas what they think about body
and soul is merely the result of the decision of the eighth
Æcumenical Council of 869, which raised to the status of dogma
the doctrine that man must not be regarded as consisting of body, soul
and spirit but of body and soul only, although some spiritual
characteristics may be ascribed to the soul.
In the centuries that followed, this dogma became more and more firmly
established. The Schoolmen in particular were steeped in it. And when
modern philosophy developed out of Scholasticism, people thought that
now they were forming their judgments from experience. But they were
only judging according to their usual habits, through the
centuries-old custom of assuming man to consist of body and soul.
This is the classic example of many situations in which present-day
humanity believes that it forms an unprejudiced judgment, whereas the
judgment it utters is nothing but the result of an historical event.
One comes to a really sound judgment and then not without
difficulty only by the survey of ever wider and wider
historical epochs.
For example, the man who knows nothing but the scientific thought of
the present time quite naturally thinks it the only valid kind of
thought, and is incapable of thinking that there could be any other
kind of knowledge. The man who, as well as being familiar with the
scientific opinion of the present time which has hardened
somewhat since the middle of the fifteenth century also knows a
little of what was accepted in the early Middle Ages, right back to
the fourth century, will form his judgments about the relations of man
with the world somewhat as the Neo-Scholastics do. But at most he will
be able to form opinions about man's relation to intellectuality; he
will not be able to form any opinion about his relation to
spirituality. For he does not know that if we go back earlier than,
say, Aristotle, who died in 322 B.C., we have to see ourselves
in a very different spiritual configuration from the one at present
prevailing, in order to get any sort of understanding as to how the
men of that time thought. To try to understand Plato or Heraclitus or
Thales with a constitution of soul such as we have at the present day
is an utter impossibility. We do not even understand Aristotle. And
anyone who is at all familiar with the discussions that have taken
place in modern times about the Aristotelian philosophy knows that
amidst all the waging of wordy warfare which still goes on in
connection with Aristotle countless misconceptions have arisen, simply
because men have not reckoned with the fact that the moment we go back
to Plato, for example, who was Aristotle's teacher, we need an
entirely different spiritual constitution. For if one approaches
Aristotle in a forward direction, from the direction of Plato, one
judges his logic differently from the way one does if one merely looks
back upon it with the spiritual make-up resulting from present-day
culture.
Even when Aristotle was compiling his logic, which is certainly pretty
abstract, very much intellectualised, he still had at least an
external knowledge, even if not personal vision there was
certainly very little of that left in Aristotle but he was
still clearly aware that at one time it had been possible to see into
the spiritual world, even if only in an instinctive way. And for him
the rules of logic were the last utterance from above, from the
spiritual world, if I may put it so. For Aristotle, accordingly, what
he established as the laws or principles of logic were, so to say,
shadows which had been cast down from the spiritual world the
world that was still a world of experience, a fact of consciousness,
for Plato.
The enormous differences that obtain between different epochs of
humanity is a thing that is usually overlooked. Let us take the years
from the death of Aristotle, 322 B.C., to the Council of Nicea, A.D.
325; there you have a period which it is very difficult to get to
know, because the Church took care to destroy all documents that might
have given a more or less accurate picture of the state of soul of
those three pre-Christian and three post-Christian centuries.
You have only to recall how often reference is made to-day to the
Gnosis. But how do people know about the Gnosis? They know it through
the writings of its opponents. Except for a very few texts, and those
very far from representative ones, the whole of the Gnostic literature
has been wiped out, and all we have are quotations from it in the
works of its opponents, in works which are intended to refute it. We
know about as much of the Gnosis as we should know of Anthroposophy if
we were to make its acquaintance through the writings of Pius X.
Nevertheless, out of this superficial knowledge people do hold forth
about the Gnosis.
But the Gnosis was an essential element in the spiritual life of the
centuries that I have just mentioned, To-day, of course, we cannot go
back to it. But at that particular period it was an extremely
important element in European development.
How can one really describe it? You see, one could not have spoken of
it five hundred years earlier in the way it was spoken of in the
fourth century A.D. For at that time there was still an instinctive
clairvoyance, an ancient clairvoyance, there was knowledge of a
super-sensible world, and one had to speak in a descriptive way out of
this knowledge. The real spiritual world was always present in
consciousness and was always behind such portrayals of it. Then that
condition ceased.
It is a marked feature of Aristotle, for example, that this
super-sensible world was for him only a tradition. He may have known
something of it, but, as I have already said, in the main it was
tradition for him. But the concepts which he received from the
spiritual world still carried the impress of that world, an impress
which was lost only in the third and fourth centuries A.D.
In Augustine we find no trace of the Gnosis; by his time it had quite
disappeared. Thus we may say that the Gnosis is in its essence the
abstract residuum of an earlier spiritual knowledge; it consists of
naked concepts. What lived in it was a body of abstractions. We can
see this already in Philo. And one can see abstractions in the ideas
of the real Gnostics, too, but their teachings were abstractions of a
spiritual world that had once been seen. By the fourth century A.D.
things had come to the point when men no longer knew what to make of
the ideas that formed the content of the Gnosis. Hence arose the
dispute between Arius and Athanasius, which cannot really be reduced
to a formula. The argument as to whether the Son is of the same nature
and being as the Father, or of a different nature and being, is
carried on in a realm in which the real content of the old ideas has
been lost. The argument takes its course no longer with ideas, but
merely with words.
All this formed the transition to the pure intellectualism which was
to develop more and more, reaching western humanity just in the middle
of the fifteenth century. By the time this intellectualism emerged,
logic was something quite different from what it had been for
Aristotle. For him, logic was, so to say, the residue of spiritual
knowledge. He had made a compilation of what in earlier times had been
experienced out of the spiritual world. By the middle of the fifteenth
century the last scrap of consciousness of this spiritual world had
vanished, and only the intellectual element remained; but now this
intellectual element appears not as the residue of a spiritual world,
but as an abstraction from the sense-world. What for Aristotle was a
gift from the world above, was now taken to be an abstraction from the
world below. And it was in essentials with
this element that men such as Galileo, Copernicus, Kepler now went
forward (though Kepler, it is true, still had some intuitions),
seeking to apply an intellectualism, the spiritual origin of which had
been lost, to the external world, the purely natural world. So that
one can say that during its development from the fourth to the
fifteenth century civilised humanity is, as it were, in labour with
the intellectualism that only comes from below an
intellectualism which is fully born only in the fifteenth century, and
thereafter establishes itself firmly, applying reason ever more and
more to the observation of external nature, until in the nineteenth
century it reaches its high-water mark in this respect.
If you take what I said yesterday about the ego-sense, the
thought-sense, the word-sense and so on, you will come to the
conclusion that in what we now experience through these senses in our
ordinary human consciousness we are actually only dealing with
pictures; otherwise there could not be those perpetual discussions
which result inevitably from the characteristics of the present time.
Indeed, a real understanding of the essential soul-life has for the
time being been lost. An example of this is the way in which
Brentano's attempt to write a psychology, a theory of the soul, failed
... something which he tried to do in all sincerity. Other people of
course write psychologies, because they are less honest, less candid
... but he wanted in perfect candour to write a psychology that would
be worth while, and he achieved nothing of any intrinsic value,
because this could only have come from spiritual science, which he
repudiated. Hence his psychology remained truncated, since he achieved
so little of what he was really striving for. This failure of
Brentano's psychology is an historic fact of profound significance.
For the jugglery with all sorts of concepts and ideas that our
psychological science pursues to-day was of course for Brentano
something quite empty.
But now what we have here (see
diagram)
as the soul-life which is the outcome of the six upper senses, from
the ego-sense to the sense of sight, all this was at one time filled
with spiritual life. If we turn our gaze back to ancient times in
Europe, back as far as Plato, all that afterwards became more and more
devoid of spirituality, more and more intellectualised, was then
filled with spirituality. We find there all that had been given to
humanity in its evolution in a still more ancient time, in the time
when the Orient had taken the lead as regards human civilisation; then
men possessed a civilisation which was devoted to this
soul-life, this true soul-life. So that we can say:
All these senses furnish experiences which nourish the spiritual life,
when spiritual life is present in the soul. And what humanity
developed in this respect was developed within the ancient eastern
culture. And you understand that culture best when you understand it
in the light of what I have just told you.
But all this has, so to say, receded into the background of evolution.
The life of the soul then lost its spirituality, it became
intellectualised, and that, as I said, began in the fourth century
B.C. Aristotle's compilation of abstract logic was the first milestone
on the path of this despiritualisation of human soul-life, and the
development of the Gnosis brought about its complete descent.
Now we still have the other man:
And now a civilisation began that was based essentially upon the
senses just enumerated. Even if you do not at first admit it,
nevertheless it is so. For take the scientific spirit that emerged,
the scientific spirit that tries to apply mathematics to everything.
Mathematics, as I explained to you yesterday, comes from the senses of
movement and of balance. Thus even the most spiritual things
discovered by modern science come from the lower man. But modern
scientists work above all with the sense of touch. You can make
interesting studies to-day if you go into the sphere of physiology.
Of course, people talk about seeing, or about the eye, or about the
sense of sight; but one who sees through these things knows that all
the concepts that are used are somehow conjured from the sense of
touch to the sense of sight. People work with things that are
borrowed, smuggled in, from the sense of touch. People do not notice
it, but in describing the sense of sight they make use of categories,
of ideas, with which one grasps the sense of touch. What to-day is
called sight in scientific circles is really only a somewhat
complicated touching; and categories, concepts such as tasting or
smelling, are sometimes brought in to help. We can see everywhere at
work the way of grasping external phenomena which lies behind modern
ideas. For modern anatomy and physiology have already discovered
or at any rate have a well-founded hypothesis that
modern thinking really has its roots in the sense of smell, in that
thinking is bound up with the brain thus not at all with the
higher senses, but with a metamorphosis of the sense of smell. This
characteristic attitude of ours in our grasp of the outer world is
quite different from the relationship that Plato had. It is not a
product of the higher senses, it is a product of the sense of smell,
if I may put it so. I mean that to-day our perfection as man does not
come from our having developed the higher senses, but from our having
created for ourselves a modified, metamorphosed dog's muzzle.
This peculiar way of relating ourselves to the outer world is quite
different from the way which befits a spiritual epoch. Now if we have
to designate as oriental culture what was first revealed through the
higher senses in ancient times, then what I have just depicted, in the
midst of which we are now living, must be called the essence of
western culture. This western culture is in essentials derived from
the lower man.
I must again and again emphasise that there is no question of
appraisal in what I am now saying; it is merely a statement of the
course of history. I am certainly not trying to point out that the
upper man is estimable and the lower man less estimable. The one is an
absorption into the world, the other is not. And it does not help to
introduce sympathy and antipathy, for then one does not reach
objective knowledge. Anyone who wishes to understand what is contained
in the Veda culture, the Yoga culture, must start from an
understanding of these things, and must take this direction (see
diagram,
upper man). And whoever wishes to understand what is really to be
found in its first beginnings, what has to be more and more developed
for certain kinds of human relationships, what indeed in the
nineteenth century has already reached a certain climax, has to know
that it is particularly the lower man that is trying to emerge there,
and that this emergence of the lower man is especially characteristic
of the Anglo-American nature, of western culture.
A spirit specially representative of the rise of this culture is Lord
Bacon of Verulam. In his Novum Organum, for instance, he makes
statements statements very easily misunderstood that at
bottom can have meaning only for superficial people. And yet what he
says is extraordinarily characteristic. Bacon is in a certain respect
both ill-informed and foolish, for as soon as he begins to speak of
ancient cultures he talks nonsense; he knows nothing about them. That
he is superficial can be demonstrated from his own writings. For
instance, where he speaks about warmth he is an empiricist
he gathers together everything that can be said about warmth,
but one sees that he gets it all from notes of experiments. What he
has to say about warmth, he did not find out for himself, but it has
been pieced together by a clerk, a copyist, for it is a frightfully
careless piece of work. Nevertheless Bacon is a milestone in modern
evolution. One may dismiss his personality as of no interest, but yet
through all his ineptitude and through all the rubbish that he again
and again gives out, something continually gets through that is
characteristic of the emergence of a culture that corresponds with
what I have described here (see
diagram,
lower man). And humanity will not be able to emerge from the poverty
of soul in which it is now living if it does not grasp that for
reasons which previous lectures will have made sufficiently clear
it was possible to live with the culture of the upper man, but
it will not be possible to live with the culture of the lower man. For
after all, man brings his soul with him into each new incarnation, a
soul which has unconscious memories of earlier lives on earth. Man is
ever and again urged towards what he has outlived. To-day he often
does not know what it is that he is being driven towards. This urge
consists in a vague longing; it is sometimes quite indefinable, but it
is there. And it is there above all because one comes gradually to
regard what belongs to this sphere (see
diagram,
lower man) as something objective, since it can be grasped in terms of
laws. All that exists of a more traditional nature, and belongs to
this sphere (see
diagram,
upper man) has, as regards its real nature, faded away into belief.
And although people are at a loss how to attribute real existence to
this moral content of the soul, and turn to faith as the only support
for knowing anything about it, nevertheless they try to cling to it.
But, my dear friends, it is not possible for humanity nowadays to go
on living with this cleavage in the soul. One can still argue that the
evangelical antithesis, the opposition between faith and knowledge
which has been elaborated particularly in the evangelical
denominations, can be maintained as a theory; but it cannot be applied
to life, one cannot live by it. Life itself gives the lie to such an
antithesis. The way must be found to assimilate morality with that to
which we ascribe real being, otherwise we shall always come to the
point of saying: Natural necessity provides us with ideas about the
beginning and the end of the earth; but when the end decreed by the
scientists has arrived, what is to become of everything to which we
ascribe human worth, of all that man attains inwardly, morally ... as
to what is to become of that, how it is to be rescued from the
perishing earth, all this has to be left to faith!
And it is interesting to note that it is just from this standpoint
that Anthroposophy is attacked. Perhaps at this point I may be allowed
to mention this attack, because it is typical; it does not emanate
from one person, but from a number of people. They find that
Anthroposophy claims to have a content of knowledge, and thus can be
treated like scientific knowledge. Simpletons say of course that its
content cannot be compared with scientific knowledge, that it is
something else well, that is self-evident, there is no need to
mention it; but it can be treated in the same way as natural
scientific knowledge. Many people also say that one cannot prove it.
Those people have never made themselves acquainted with the nature of
logical proof. But the main point is that people say that the things
of which Anthroposophy treats ought not to be the objects of
knowledge, for this would deprive them of their essential character.
They must be objects of faith. For it is only in the fact that we know
nothing of God, of eternal life, but only believe in these things,
that their true value lies. And indeed such knowledge is assailed on
the ground that it will undermine the religious character of these
truths; for their sacredness is said to lie in the very fact that in
them we believe something about which we know nothing. The very
expression of our trust lies in our ignorance. I should very much like
to know how men would get on with such a concept of trust in everyday
life, if they had to have the same trust in those about whom they knew
nothing as in those of whom they knew something ... at that rate one
should no longer trust the divine spiritual powers when one gets to
know them! Thus the essence of religion is supposed to consist in the
fact that one does not know it, for the holiness of religious truths
suffers injury when one converts those truths into knowledge.
That is what it comes to. If one pays any attention to the worthless
scribbling that goes on, then every week one sees in print things that
are reduced to nonsense if one analyses them into their original
elementary constituents. To-day one must not ignore these things. I
must again and again stress this, and I do not hesitate to repeat
myself. For instance, when a respectable newspaper in Wurttemburg
publishes an essay on Anthroposophy by a university lecturer who
writes, This Anthroposophy maintains that there is a spiritual
world in which the spiritual beings move about like tables and chairs
in physical space, when a university don to-day is able to write
such a sentence, we must leave no stone unturned to discredit him; he
is impossible: nonsense in responsible quarters must not be allowed to
pass. It is only when anyone is drunk that he sees tables and chairs
move, and then only subjectively. And since Professor T. would neither
admit that he was drunk when he wrote his authoritative article, nor
that he was a spiritualist for tables and chairs do move for
spiritualists, even if not of themselves then one is justified
in saying that here we have an example of the most thoughtless
nonsense. And by having written such nonsense, the Professor
undermines confidence in all his knowledge.
To-day we must make it our bounden duty to treat such things with the
utmost severity. And we shall become more and more entangled in the
forces of decadence if we do not maintain this severity. We meet with
utterly incredible things to-day, and the most incredible things get
by, since we perpetually find excuse after excuse for the trickeries
that are committed in so-called authoritative circles. To-day it is
absolutely necessary to lay stress upon the importance of reaching
clear ideas, full of content, in every sphere. And if one does this,
then the doctrine of the separation between knowledge and faith cannot
be maintained, for then it would be reduced to what I have just now
pointed out.
But this distinction between knowledge and belief is something that
has been brought about only in the course of history. It has come
about partly for reasons which I have already mentioned, partly on
account of something else. Above all, the following must be taken into
consideration. To begin with, there is what came about in western
Christianity in the first Christian centuries through the fusing of
the Gnosis with the monotheistic Gospel teaching, and then there is
the fusing of Christianity with the Aristotelianism that arose in the
time of the Schoolmen certainly in a highly intelligent way,
but nevertheless merely as historical recollection. And this doctrine,
the doctrine of the uniform origin of both body and soul through birth
or conception, is a thoroughly Aristotelian doctrine. With the casting
off of the old spirituality, with the emergence of pure
intellectuality, Aristotle had already been divested of the notion of
pre-existence, the notion of the life of the human soul before birth,
before conception. This denial of the doctrine of pre-existence is not
Christian; it is Aristotelian. It first became a dogmatic fetter
through the introduction of Aristotelianism into Christian theology.
But at this point an important question arises a question which
can be answered to some extent from the substance of the lectures I
have given here in recent weeks. If you remember much of what I have
lately been saying, you will have come to the conclusion that the
materialism of the nineteenth century is in a certain sense not wholly
unjustified (I have repeatedly stressed this). Why! Because what
confronts us in the human being, in so far as he is a
physical-material being, is an image, a reproduction, of his spiritual
evolution since his last death. What develops here between birth and
death is not in fact the pure soul-spiritual; it is the soul-physical,
a copy. Out of man's experiences between birth and death there is no
possibility of acquiring a scientific conception of life after death.
There is nothing which offers a possible proof of immortality, if one
looks merely at the life between birth and death.
But traditional Christianity does look only at this life between birth
and death, for it regards the soul as well as the body as having been
created at the time of birth or conception. This viewpoint makes it
impossible to acquire knowledge about life after death. Unless one
accepts the existence of life before birth, knowledge of which can, as
you know, be acquired, one can never obtain knowledge of life after
death. Hence the cleavage between knowledge and belief as regards the
question of immortality arises from the dogma which denies the life
before birth. It was because men wanted to drop the knowledge of
pre-natal life that it became necessary to postulate a special
certitude of faith. For if, whilst denying pre-natal life, one still
wishes to speak of a life after death, then one cannot speak of it as
scientific knowledge.
You see how systematically ordered the dogmatic structure is. Its
purpose is to spread darkness among mankind about spiritual science.
How can that be done? On the one hand by attacking the doctrine of
life before birth ... then there can be no knowledge about life after
death, then men have to believe it on the basis of dogma. The fight
for belief in dogma is waged by fighting against knowledge of life
before birth.
The way dogma has developed since the fourth century A.D., and the way
modern scientific notions have developed without interruption out of
dogma it is all extraordinarily systematic! For all these
scientific ideas can be traced back to their origin in dogma, only
they are now applied to the observation of external nature, and it can
be shown how thereby the way has been paved for man's dependence upon
mere belief. Because man will have some relationship to
immortality, he is deprived of his knowledge for he has been
deprived of it and then he is open to dogmatic belief. Then
dogmatic belief can seek out its kingdom.
This is at the same time a social question, a question relevant to the
evolution of humanity, a question that has to be clearly faced to-day.
And it is the crucial test, not only of the value of modern culture,
but also of the value of the modern scientific spirit, and of
humanity's prospects of recovering the strength to rise, to climb up
again.
Last Modified: 02-Nov-2024
|
The Rudolf Steiner e.Lib is maintained by:
The e.Librarian:
elibrarian@elib.com
|
|
|
|
| |