Sketch of a Perspective of an Anthroposophy
(Opening pages of the last chapter of Rudolf Steiner's Riddles of
Philosophy, 1914)
Whoever studies the development of philosophical world views up to the
present day can discover in the seeking and striving of some thinkers
undercurrents that in a certain way do not break through into consciousness
but rather live on instinctively. Powers are at work in these undercurrents
that determine the direction and often the form as well of
the ideas of these thinkers; these thinkers do not want to turn their
searching spiritual gaze directly upon these powers, however. What they say
often seems motivated by hidden forces, which they do not want to
investigate, and from which they even recoil in fear. Such forces live in
the thought-worlds of Dilthey, of Eucken, and of Cohen. The beliefs
presented in these thought-worlds are the expression of cognitive powers
that govern these philosophers unconsciously, but that are not consciously
elaborated in their thought-systems.
Sureness and certainty in knowing are sought in many systems of thought.
The direction followed takes its point of departure more or less from
Kant's way of picturing things. The natural-scientific mode of thinking has
a definitive influence, consciously or unconsciously, upon the way one
shapes one's thoughts. But many people sense that it is within the
soul that is conscious of itself that the source is to be
sought from which knowledge must draw in order also to gain enlightenment
about the world outside the human soul. And almost all of them are
dominated by the question: How does the self-conscious soul arrive at the
point of seeing what it experiences within itself as being the
manifestation of a true reality? The everyday sensory world has become an
illusion because, in the course of philosophical development,
the self-conscious I has more and more found itself in its
inner experience to be isolated within itself. It has arrived at the point
of regarding even sense perceptions as mere inner experiences that reveal
no power within themselves able to guarantee their existence and permanence
within reality. One feels how much depends upon finding, in the
self-conscious I, a point of support for knowledge. In the
course of investigations motivated by this feeling, however, one arrives at
views that do not afford a means of penetrating with the I into
a world that can carry existence in a satisfactory way.
Whoever seeks the explanation for this state of affairs can find it in the
position toward outer reality taken by man's soul being, which has been
detached from this outer reality of the world by the development philosophy
has undergone. Man's soul being feels itself surrounded by a world that
reveals itself to him first of all through the senses. But the soul has
become attentive also to its own activity, to its inner, creative
experiencing. The soul feels it to be an irrefutable truth that no light,
no color can be revealed without an eye sensitive to light and color. Thus
it feels something creative already in the activity of the eye. But if the
eye itself creatively brings forth the color which is what one must
think according to this philosophy where can I then find something
that exists in itself, that does not owe its existence merely to my own
creative power? If now even the revelations of the senses are only
expressions of the soul's own power, must it not then to an even greater
extent be thinking that wants to gain a picture of true reality? Is
this thinking, however, not condemned to create pictures that are rooted in
the character of man's soul life but that can never bear within themselves
anything able to provide certainty in pressing forward to the sources of
existence? Such questions are surfacing everywhere in the recent
development of philosophy.
As long as one cherishes the belief that the world revealed to our senses
represents something complete and self-sustaining, which one must
investigate in order to know its inner being, one will not be able to
escape the confusion caused by the above question. The human soul can
produce its knowledge within itself only through its own
creativity. That is a conviction which justifiably grows out of the
presuppositions described in the chapter of this book on The World as
Illusion and in the presentation of Hamerling's thoughts. But then,
having arrived at this conviction, one will not surmount a certain obstacle
to knowledge as long as one still has the following picture: that the world
of the senses contains the true foundations of its existence within
itself; and that, with what man himself creates within his soul, he must
somehow copy something that lies outside the soul.
Only that knowledge will be able to surmount this obstacle which grasps
with the spiritual eye the fact that everything perceived by the senses
does not represent, through its own being, a finished, self-contained
reality, but rather something incomplete, a half reality, as it
were.
As soon as one assumes that the perceptions of the sense world present us
with a complete reality, one will never arrive at an answer to the
question: What do the soul's own creative productions have to add to this
reality in the act of knowing? One will have to remain at the Kantian
belief that the human being must regard his knowledge as the product of his
own soul organization and not as something that reveals itself to him as a
true reality. If reality, in its actual form and nature, lies
outside the soul, then the soul cannot bring forth what corresponds
to this reality, but only something that flows out of the soul's own
organization.
Everything changes as soon as one recognizes that the organization of the
human soul with what it produces creatively itself in the activity
of knowledge does not move away from reality; rather, in the life it
unfolds before all knowing activity, it conjures up a world that is not the
real one. The human soul is placed into the world in such a way that,
because of the soul's own nature, it makes things different than they
really are. In a certain sense what Hamerling expresses in the following
passage is justified: Certain stimuli produce odors in our sense of
smell. The rose, therefore, has no fragrance if no one smells it ... If
that is not obvious to you, dear reader, and if your understanding shys
away from this fact like a skittish horse, then read no further; leave this
and every other book on philosophical matters unread; for you lack the
necessary ability to grasp a fact without bias and to retain it in
thought. The way the sense world appears when man
confronts it immediately does depend, without any doubt, upon the being and
nature of his soul. But does it not follow from this that his soul
in fact causes the world to appear as it does? Now an unbiased study shows
how the unreal character of the sense-perceptible outer world stems from
the fact that man, in his immediate confrontation with things, suppresses
something in himself which in truth belongs to them. If then, out of his
own creativity, he unfolds his inner life, if he allows what slumbers in
the depths of his soul to rise up out of these depths, then, to what he
beheld with his senses, he adds something more that makes the half reality
into a full reality in the act of knowledge. It lies in the nature of the
soul to extinguish, with its first look at things, something that
belongs to their reality. Thus, for the senses, things are not as they are
in reality but rather as the soul has made them. But their semblance (or
their mere appearance) is due to the fact that the soul has first taken
away from them something that belongs to them. By not stopping short at his
first look at things, man, in his activity of knowing, then adds to them
that which first reveals their full reality. In its activity of knowing,
the soul does not add something to things that is an unreal element with
respect to them; rather, before its activity of knowing, the soul
has taken something from things that belongs to their true reality. It will
be philosophy's task to realize that the world revealed to man is an
illusion until he confronts it in knowing activity, but
that the path of knowledge indicates the direction toward full reality.
What man produces out of his own creativity in knowing appears to be an
inner revelation of the soul only because man, before he has the cognitive
experience, must close himself off from the essential being of things. He
cannot yet see this essential being in things when he at first only
confronts them. In knowing, he discovers for himself, through his own
activity, what at first was hidden. Now if man regards as a reality what he
has only perceived, then what is produced in the activity of knowing will
appear to him as something he has added onto this reality. When he realizes
that what he had only seemingly produced himself must be sought in the
things, and that he had only kept this at a distance when he first looked
at the things, then he will sense how his activity of knowing is a process
of reality by which the soul progressively grows into world existence and
broadens its inner, isolated experience into world-experience.
In a little book,
Truth and Science,
published in 1892, the author
of the present book attempted to give a philosophical foundation to what
has just been briefly indicated. He speaks there about perspectives that
modern philosophy must open up if it is to surmount the obstacle that has
resulted quite naturally from its own recent development. A certain
philosophical viewpoint is presented in that book in the following words:
It is not the first form in which reality approaches the
I that is its true one; its true form is the final one, which
the I makes out of the first. That first form has no
significance at all for the objective world and has that form only as a
basis for the cognitive process. Therefore, it is not the form of the world
given it by knowledge that is subjective; but rather the first form
given to the I that is so. The author's later
philosophical attempt,
The Philosophy of Spiritual Activity,
(see Note #1)
published in 1894, is a further elaboration of this viewpoint. His effort
there is to establish a philosophical basis for a view indicated in that
book in the following way: It is not due to the objects that they are
given to us at first without their corresponding concepts, but rather it is
due to our spiritual organization. Our total being functions in such a
way that, for each thing within reality, the pertinent elements flow to us
from two sides: from the sides of perceiving and of thinking.
How I am organized to grasp things has nothing to do with their nature. The
split between perceiving and thinking is first present the moment I, the
observer, approach the things. And in the last chapter of the book:
The perception is the part of reality that is given objectively; the
concept is the part given subjectively (through intuition). Our spiritual
organization tears reality apart into these two factors. The one factor
appears to perception; the other to intuition. Only the union of both, the
perception incorporating itself lawfully into the universe, is full
reality. If we look at mere perception by itself, we then have no reality,
but rather a disconnected chaos; if we look at the lawfulness of our
perceptions by itself, we then have to do merely with abstract concepts.
The abstract concept does not contain reality; but the thinking observation
does indeed do so that considers neither concept nor perception one-sidedly
by itself, but rather the union of both.
For someone who can make this point of view his own it is then possible to
regard fruitful reality as being united with his soul life within the
self-conscious I. This is the view toward which the evolution
of philosophy has been striving since Greek times and which has revealed
its first clearly recognizable traces in Goethe's world view.
It is becoming recognized that this self-conscious I does not
experience itself as isolated within itself nor as being outside of the
objective world; rather, the Is separation from this
world is only a phenomenon of human consciousness and can be overcome by
the insight that, as a human being in a certain stage of development, man
has assumed a temporary form for the I by expelling from
consciousness the forces that unite the soul with the world. If these
forces worked continuously in human consciousness, one would not then
attain a powerful, self-contained consciousness of oneself. One could not
experience oneself as an I conscious of itself. The development
of self-consciousness therefore depends precisely upon the soul's being
given the possibility of perceiving the world without that part of reality
which the self-conscious I extinguishes at a certain stage
at the stage that precedes knowledge.
Thus, the cosmic forces in this part of reality work upon the being of the
soul in such a way that they withdraw and conceal themselves in order to
allow the self-conscious I to shine forth powerfully. The
I, accordingly, must recognize that it owes its knowledge of
itself to a factor that casts a veil over its knowledge of the world. It
follows necessarily from this that everything which brings the soul to a
powerful, energetic experience of the I renders invisible the
deeper ground in which this I has its roots. But now all the
knowledge that our ordinary consciousness has is of the kind that makes the
self-conscious I powerful. The human being feels himself to be
a self-conscious I through the fact that he perceives an outer
world with his senses, through the fact that he experiences himself as
outside of this outer world, and through the fact that he stands in a kind
of relationship to this outer world that, at a certain stage of scientific
investigation, makes the world seem like an illusion. If all
this were not the case, the self-conscious I would not come to
manifestation. If, therefore, in one's activity of knowing, one strives
only to make a copy of what was already observed before one's
knowing activity, then one gains no true experience of full reality,
but only a copy of half reality.
If one acknowledges that this is how matters stand, one cannot then seek
the answer to the riddles of philosophy within the experiences of the soul
that present themselves to ordinary consciousness. This consciousness is
called upon to strengthen the self-conscious I; striving to
this end, it must veil our vision of the relationship between the
I and the objective world; it cannot therefore show how the
soul relates to the true world.
This explains why a cognitive striving that wishes to progress
philosophically by using the approach of natural science or something
similar must always arrive at a point where what it is striving for in the
activity of knowing falls apart. This book has had to point to this falling
apart in the case of many modern thinkers, for, basically, all scientific
endeavor of modern times works with those scientific, cognitive means that
serve to detach the self-conscious I from true reality. And the
strength and greatness of modern science, especially of natural science, are
founded upon the unrestrained application of these cognitive means.
Individual philosophers like Dilthey, Eucken, and others direct their
philosophical studies toward the soul's observation of itself. But what
they study are those experiences of the soul which provide the basis for
the self-conscious I. Therefore they do not penetrate into
those wellsprings of the world where the soul's experiences well forth from
true reality. These wellsprings cannot lie where the soul at first
confronts and observes itself with its ordinary consciousness. If the soul
wants to arrive at these wellsprings, it must get out of this ordinary
consciousness. It must experience something in itself that this
consciousness cannot give it. To our ordinary knowledge such an experience
seems at first sheer nonsense. The soul is supposed to experience itself
knowingly in some element without bringing its consciousness along
with it into this element?! One is supposed to skip over consciousness and
still remain conscious at the same time?! And yet: in philosophical
endeavors one will either continue to arrive at impossibilities, or one
will have to entertain the prospect that the sheer nonsense
just indicated only seems to be so, and that precisely it points the way to
where help must be sought in solving the riddles of philosophy.
One will have to acknowledge that the path into the inner being of
the soul must be a completely different one than that chosen by many
a recent world view. As long as one takes soul experiences the way they are
presented to ordinary consciousness, one will not enter into the depths of
the soul. One will be limited to what these depths send up. Eucken's world
view is in this situation. One must strive downward, below the surface of
the soul. But one cannot do this with the means of ordinary soul
experience. Their strength lies precisely in the fact that they maintain
the soul in this ordinary consciousness.
Means of penetrating more deeply into the soul present themselves when one
directs one's gaze upon something that is, to be sure, also at work in
ordinary consciousness, but which, in its work, does not enter this
consciousness at all. When a person thinks, his consciousness is directed
toward his thoughts. He wants to picture something through his thoughts; he
wants to think correctly in the ordinary sense. But one can also focus
one's attention on something else. One can fix one's spiritual gaze upon
the activity of thinking as such. For example, one can place in the center
of one's consciousness a thought that does not relate to anything external,
that is thought as a kind of» symbol without any regard at all for the fact
that it might represent something external. One can now continue to hold
onto such a thought for a time. While one perseveres in this way, one can
live entirely into what the soul itself is doing inwardly. The important
thing here is not that one live in thoughts, but rather that one experience
the activity of thinking. In this way the soul breaks away from what it
accomplishes in its ordinary thinking. When the soul has continued this
inner practice long enough, it will recognize after a time that it has
become involved with experiences which detach it from that thinking and
picturing which are bound to the bodily organs. One can accomplish
something similar with the soul's activities of feeling and willing; yes,
even with its sensing and perceiving of outer things. One will achieve
something along this path only if one does not shrink from acknowledging
that one cannot undertake self-knowledge of the soul simply by looking at
the inner life that is usually present, but rather by looking at what must
first be disclosed by inner, soul work by soul work which, through
practice, arrives at such concentration upon the inner activity of
thinking, feeling, and willing that these experiences become in a certain
way spiritually densified within themselves (sich geistig in
sich verdichten). In this densified state they
then reveal their inner being, which cannot be perceived in ordinary
consciousness. Through such soul work one discovers that in order for
ordinary consciousness to arise, one's soul forces must become
rarefied (sich verdünnen) in this way and
that in this rarefied state they become unperceivable. The soul work meant
here consists in the unlimited enhancement of soul capacities known
also to ordinary consciousness but which this consciousness does not employ
in their enhanced state. These are the capacities for attentiveness
(Aufmerksamkeit) and for
loving devotion
to what is experienced by
the soul. In order to achieve the spiritual densification indicated
here, one must enhance these capacities to such a degree that they work as
entirely new powers of the soul.
By proceeding in this way, one grasps within the soul a real experience
whose actual being proves to be independent of the restrictions of the
bodily organs. This is a spiritual life that must not be confused
conceptually with what Dilthey and Eucken call the spiritual world, for
their spiritual world is experienced by the human being only when he is
connected with his bodily organs. What we mean here by spiritual life is
not present for the soul that is bound up with the body.
And a true knowledge of our ordinary soul life does present itself as one
of our first experiences when this new spiritual life has been attained. In
reality, even our ordinary spiritual life is not produced by the body, but
rather runs its course outside the body. When I see a color, when I hear a
sound, I do not experience the color or sound as resulting from my body;
rather, as a self-conscious I, I am connected outside of my
body with the color or sound. The task of the body is to function as a kind
of mirror. If, in my ordinary consciousness, I am connected with a
color only with my soul, then, because of the nature of this consciousness,
I can perceive nothing of the color. Similarly, I cannot see my own face
when I look forward, but if a mirror is in front of me, I perceive my face
as an objective body. If I do not stand in front of a mirror, I am
this body and experience myself as such. Standing in front of a mirror, I
perceive this body as a reflection. It is like this also with sense
perception (one must of course recognize the insufficiency of any
analogy). I live with the color outside of my body; through
the activity of my body (of my eye, of my nervous system) the color becomes
a conscious perception for me. The human body is not a producer of
perceptions nor of any soul life; rather, it is an apparatus for
reflecting what takes place in a soul-spiritual way outside of the body.
Such a view places epistemology upon a promising basis. One will ...
arrive epistemologically at a ... picture of the I not when one
pictures it (the I) as being within the bodily organization and
as receiving impressions from outside, but rather when one
regards this I as located within the lawfulness of the things
themselves and when one sees the bodily organization only as a kind of
mirror; by means of the organic processes of the body, the weaving of the
I within the true being of the world outside the body is
reflected back to the I. Thus in a lecture
entitled The Psychological Basis and Epistemological Position of
Spiritual Science prepared for the Philosophical Congress in Bologna
in 1911 did the author of this book seek to characterize the
perspective hovering before him of an epistemology.
During sleep the mirror-like relationship of the body to the soul is
interrupted; the I lives only within the weaving of what
is soul-spiritual. For ordinary consciousness, however, no experience of
the soul is present if the body does not mirror these experiences.
Therefore sleep runs its course unconsciously. The result of the soul
exercises indicated above and of others like them is that the soul unfolds
a different consciousness than its ordinary one. The soul attains thereby
the capacity not only for experiencing in a soul-spiritual way, but also
for strengthening in itself what is experienced, so that what is
experienced reflects itself in a certain way within itself without
the help of the body and thus arrives at spiritual perception. And
only in what is thus experienced can the soul first truly know itself and
consciously experience itself in its essential being.
Just as memory conjures up out of the depths of the soul physically
experienced facts from the past, so for a soul that has prepared
itself for this by the means indicated above there arise from the
soul's inner depths substantial experiences that do not belong to the world
of sense existence but rather to a world in which the soul has its
fundamental being.
It is only too obvious that the adherents of many modern points of view
will consign the world revealed here to the realm of mental aberration, of
illusion, of hallucination, of auto-suggestion, and the like. One can only
answer them that an earnest striving of the soul working in the way
just indicated finds, in the inner, spiritual state which it has
developed, the means to distinguish between illusion and spiritual reality;
and these means are just as sure as those used in ordinary life, in a
healthy state of soul, to distinguish between something imaginary
and something actually perceived. One will search in vain for theoretical
proof that the spiritual world characterized above is real; but such proof
of the reality of the perceptual world does not exist either. In both cases
it is the experience itself that determines how one is to judge.
What keeps many people from taking the step which, according to our
presentation, alone offers a prospect of solving the riddles of philosophy
is that they believe such a step will land them in a realm of nebulous
mysticism. But anyone who has no soul predisposition toward such nebulous
mysticism will, along the path just described, gain access to a world of
soul experience that is just as crystal clear in itself as the structures
of mathematical ideas. To be sure, if someone is inclined to seek the
spiritual in some dark unknown, in something that cannot
be explained, then he will not find his way on this path either as
knowledgeable adherent or as opponent.
It is also easy to understand that what is indicated here will be strongly
resisted by those who want to regard the natural-scientific approach to
knowing the sense world as the only true scientific way. Nevertheless,
whoever casts off such one-sidedness will be able to recognize that it is
precisely the genuine natural-scientific attitude that provides the
basis for undertaking what has been described here. The ideas described in
this book as constituting the modern natural-scientific approach provide
the best practice thoughts to which the soul can devote itself and upon
which it can dwell in order to free itself in its inner experiences from
its connectedness to the body. Whoever uses these natural-scientific ideas
and proceeds with them in the way described here will discover that,
through inner spiritual practice, thoughts that originally seem meant only
to portray natural processes, really free the soul from the body, and that
therefore the spiritual science referred to here must be seen as a
continuation of a natural-scientific way of thinking that is rightly
experienced by the soul.
Footnotes:
-
Anthroposophic Press, 1986
-
Hingabe: literally, a giving oneself over to something. -Ed.
|