There are two conflicting views in respect to
the Social Question. The one regards the causes of the good and bad
in social life as lying rather in men themselves; the other as lying
mainly in the conditions under which men live. People who represent
the first of these opinions will, in all their efforts for human
progress, aim chiefly at raising men's spiritual and physical
fitness, together with their moral susceptibilities; whereas those
who incline more to the second view will direct their attention first
and foremost to raising the standard of living; they say to
themselves that if once people have the means of living decently, the
level of their general fitness and moral sense will rise of itself.
It will hardly be denied that this latter view is held in many
circles to be the mark of a very old-fashioned turn of mind. A
person, we are told, whose life from early morning till late at night
is one bitter struggle with dire necessity, has no possibility of
properly developing his spiritual and moral powers. First give him
his daily bread before you talk to him of spiritual
things.
In this first declaration there is apt to be a
sting of reproach, especially when it is leveled at a movement such
as the anthroposophical one. Nor are they the worst people of our
times, from whom such reproaches come. They are inclined to say:
“Your out-and-out occultist is very loathe to leave the planes
of Devachan and Kama, and come down to common earth. He would rather
know half-a-dozen Sanskrit words than condescend to learn what
‘ground-rent' is.” These very words may be read in
European Civilization and the Revival of Modern Occultism, an
interesting book by G. L. Dankmar, which has recently
appeared.
It is not far-fetched to couch the reproach in
the following form: People will point out, that in our modern age
there are not infrequently families of eight persons, all huddled
together in a single garret, lacking both light and air and obliged
to send their children to school in such a weak and half-starved
condition that they can scarcely keep body and soul together. Should
not those then — they ask — who have at heart the
progress and improvement of the masses, concentrate their whole
endeavors on abolishing such a state of things? Instead of pondering
over the principles of higher spiritual worlds, they should turn
their minds to the question: What can be done to relieve the existing
social distress? “Let Anthroposophy come down out of its frosty
insularity amongst human beings, amongst the common people. Let it
place at the forefront of its program, the ethical claim of universal
brotherhood, and act accordingly, regardless of consequences. Let it
turn what Christ says about loving our neighbor into a social fact
and Anthroposophy will become for all time a precious and
indestructible human asset.” This is pretty much what the book
goes on to say.
Those people mean well who make such an
objection to Anthroposophy. Indeed, we may admit that they are right,
as against many of those who devote themselves to anthroposophical
studies. There are undoubtedly, amongst these latter, many persons
who only have their own spiritual needs at heart, who only want to
know something about “the higher life”, about the fate of
the soul after death, and so forth. Neither, most certainly, are
people wrong in saying that at the present day it seems more needful
to exercise oneself in acts of common welfare, in the virtues of
neighborly love and human usefulness, rather than to sit aloof,
nursing in one's soul the latent seeds of some higher faculty.
Those with whom this is the foremost object may well be deemed
persons of a subtilized selfishness, who let the well-being of their
own soul rank before the common human
virtues.
Again another remark, often to be heard, is
that a spiritual movement like the anthroposophical one can, after
all, only have an interest for people who are “well-off”
and have “spare time” for such things; but that, when
people have to keep their hands busy from morning till night for a
miserable pittance, what is the use of trying to feed them up with
fine talk about the common unity of man, the higher life, and the
like.
There has been a good deal of sinning in this
respect undoubtedly, and by zealous disciples of Anthroposophy too.
And yet it is none the less true that the anthroposophic life, lived
with true understanding, cannot but lead men to the virtues of
self-sacrificing work for the common interest. At any rate there is
nothing in Anthroposophy to hinder anyone from being every whit as
good a human being as others who have no knowledge of Anthroposophy,
or will have none.
But, as regards the Social Question, none of
this touches the point. To arrive at the root of the matter requires
very much more than the opponents of the anthroposophic movement are
willing to admit. It shall be conceded to them forthwith that much
can be done by means of the measures proposed on various sides for
the betterment of men's social conditions. One party aims at
one thing; another, at another. In all such party claims there is a
great deal that any clear thinker soon discovers to be mere
brain-spinning; but there is much too, undoubtedly, which, at core,
is excellent.
Robert Owen (1775–1858), incontestably
one of the noblest of social reformers, over and over again insists
that a man is determined by the surroundings in which he grows up;
that the formation of a man's character is not due to himself,
but to the conditions of his life being such as he can thrive in.
There can be no question of disputing the glaring truth that is
contained in such maxims; still less, any desire to shrug it away
contemptuously, as being more or less self-evident. On the contrary,
let it be admitted at once that many things may become much better,
if people will be guided in public life by the recognition of these
truths. Neither will Anthroposophy, therefore, withhold anyone from
taking part in such practical schemes for human progress as may aim,
in the light of such truths, at bettering the lot of the depressed,
poverty-stricken classes of mankind.
But — Anthroposophy must go deeper. For a
thorough, radical progress can never possibly be affected by any such
means as these. Anyone who disputes this has never become clear in
his own mind whence those conditions of life originate, in which men
find themselves placed. For, in truth, so far as a man's life
is dependent on such conditions, these conditions themselves have
been created by men. Who else, then, made the institutions under
which one man is poor, and another rich? Other men, surely. And it
really does not affect the question that these other men for the most
part lived before those who are now flourishing, or not flourishing,
under the conditions. The suffering which Nature, of herself alone,
inflicts upon Man are, for the social state of affairs, only of
indirect consideration. These natural sufferings are just what must
be mitigated, if not totally removed, by human action. And if this
does not happen, if what is needed in this respect is not done, then
the fault lies after all with the human institutions. If we study
these things to the bottom, we find that all evils which can
correctly speaking be called social evils, originate also in human
deeds. In this respect certainly, not the individual, but mankind as
a whole, is most assuredly the “Forger of its own
Fate.”
Undeniable as this is, it is no less true that,
taken on a large scale, no considerable section of mankind, no one
caste or class, has deliberately, with evil intentions, brought about
the suffering of any other section. All the assertions that are made
of this kind are based simply on lack of discernment. And although
this too is really a self-obvious truth, yet it is a truth that
requires stating. For although such things are obvious enough to the
understanding, yet in the practice of life people are apt to take a
different attitude. Every exploiter of his fellow men would naturally
much prefer it, if the victims of his exploitations did not have to
suffer; and it would go a long way, if people not merely took this as
mentally obvious, but also adjusted their feelings
accordingly.
“Well, but when you have said this, what does it
all lead to?” — so many a social reformer will no doubt
protest. “Do you expect the exploited to look on the exploiter
with feelings of unmixed benevolence? Isn't it only too
understandable that he should detest him, and that his detestation
should lead him to adopt a party attitude? And what is more”
— they will urge — “it would truly be but a poor
remedy to prescribe the oppressed brotherly-love for his oppressor,
taking for text perhaps the maxim of the great Buddha: ‘Hate is
not overcome by Hate, but by Love
alone.”
And yet, for all that, we touch here upon
something, the recognition of which can alone lead to any real
“social thinking.” And this is where the anthroposophic
attitude of mind comes in. For the anthroposophic attitude of mind
cannot rest content with a surface understanding; it must go to the
depths. And so it cannot stop at demonstrating that such and such
conditions produce social misery; but must go further, and know what
it is that created these conditions, and still continues to create
them, which, after all, is the only knowledge that can bear any
fruit. And in the face of these deeper problems most of the social
theories prove indeed very “barren theories,” not to say
mere shibboleths.
So long as one's thinking only skims the
surface of things, one ascribes a quite fictitious power to
circumstances, indeed to externals generally. For these circumstances
are simply the outer expression of an inner life. Just as a person
only understands the human body when he knows that it is the outer
expression of the soul, so he alone can form a right judgment of the
external institutions of life who sees that they are nothing but the
creations of human souls, who embody in these institutions their
sentiments, their habits of mind, their thoughts. The conditions
under which we live are made by our fellow-men; and we shall never
ourselves make better ones, unless we set out from other thoughts,
other habits of mind and other sentiments than those of the former
makers.
When considering such things it is well to take
particular instances. On face of it, someone may very likely appear
to be an oppressor because he is able to keep a smart establishment,
travel first class on the railway, and so forth. And the oppressed
will be he who is obliged to wear a shabby coat and travel third. But
without being a “hidebound individualist”, or a
“retrograde Tory”, or anything of the sort, simple plain
thinking may lead one to see this fact, namely: That no one is
oppressed or exploited through my wearing one sort of coat or
another; but simply from the fact of my paying the workman who makes
the coat too low a wage in return. The poor workman who buys his
cheap coat at a low price is, in this respect, in exactly the same
position towards his fellow-men as the rich man, who has his better
coat made for him. Whether I be poor or rich, I am equally an
exploiter when I purchase things which are underpaid. As a matter of
fact no one in these days has the right to call anyone else an
oppressor; for he has only to look at himself. If he scrupulously
examines his own case, he will not be long in discovering the
oppressor there too. Is the work that goes to the well-to-do class
the only badly-paid work I do? Why, the very man sitting next to me,
and complaining with me of oppression, procures the labor of my hands
on precisely the same terms as the well-to-do whom we are both
attacking. Think this thoroughly out, and one finds other landmarks
for one's social thinking than those in customary
use.
More especially, when this line of reflection
is pursued, it becomes evident that “rich” and
“exploiter” are two notions that must be kept entirely
distinct. Whether one is rich or poor today depends on one's
own energies, or the energies of one's ancestors, or on
something at any rate quite different. That one is an exploiter of
other people's labor-power has nothing whatever to do with
these things; or not directly at least. It has, however, very closely
to do with something else: namely, it has to do with the fact that
our institutions, or the conditions of our environment, are built up
on personal self-interest. One must keep a very clear mind here;
otherwise one will have quite a false idea of what is being actually
stated. If today I purchase a coat, it seems, under existing
conditions, perfectly natural that I should purchase it as cheaply as
possible; that is: I have myself only in view of the transaction. And
herewith is indicated the point of view from which the whole of our
life is carried on.
The reply will promptly be forthcoming:
“How about all the social movements? Is not the removal of this
particular evil the very object for which all the parties and leaders
of social reform are striving? Are they not exerting themselves for
the ‘protection’ of Labor? Are not the working-class and
their representatives demanding higher scales of wages and a
reduction of working hours?” As was said already: from the
standpoint of the present time, not the least objection is here being
urged against such demands and measures. Neither, of course, is any
plea hereby put forward for any one of the existing parties and
programs. In particular, from the point of view with which we are
here concerned no question comes in of siding with any party —
whether “for” or “against”. Anything of the
sort is of itself foreign to the anthroposophic way of viewing these
matters.
One may introduce any number of ameliorations
for the better protection of one particular class of labor, and
thereby do much no doubt to raise the standard of living amongst this
or that group of human beings. But the nature of the exploitation is
not thereby in its essence changed nor bettered. For it depends on
the fact that one man, from the aspect of self-interest, obtains for
himself the labor-products of another. Whether I have too much or too
little, that which I have I use to gratify my own self-interest; and
thereby the other man is of necessity exploited. And though, whilst
continuing to maintain this aspect, I protect his labor, yet nothing
is thereby changed, save in appearances. If I pay more for his work,
then he will have to pay the more for mine; unless the one's
being better off is to make the other worse
off.
To give another instance, by way of
illustration: If I purchase a factory in order to make as much as
possible for myself out of it, then I shall take care to get the
necessary labor as cheaply as possible. Everything that is done will
be done from the view of my personal self-interest. If, on the other
hand, I purchase the factory with the view of making the best
possible provision for two hundred human beings, then everything I do
will take a different coloring. Practically, in the present day,
there will probably be no such very great difference between the
second case and the first; but that is solely because one single
selfless person is powerless to accomplish very much inside a whole
community built up on self-interest. Matters would stand very
differently if non-self-interested labor were the general
rule.
Some “practical” person will no
doubt opine that mere good intentions will not go far towards
enabling anyone to improve the wage-earning possibilities of his
workers. Good will, after all, will not increase the returns on his
manufactured articles, and, without that, it is not possible to make
better terms for his workmen. Now here is just the important point:
namely, to see that this argument is altogether erroneous. All
interests, and therewith all the conditions of life, become different
when a thing is procured not with an eye to oneself, but with an eye
to the other people. What must any person look to, who is powerless
to serve anything but his own private welfare? To making as much as
he can for himself, when all is said and done. How others are obliged
to labor, in order to satisfy his private needs, is a matter which he
cannot take into consideration. And thus he is compelled to expend
his powers in the fight for existence. If I start an undertaking
which is to bring in as much as possible for myself, I do not enquire
as to how the labor-power is set in motion that does my work. But if
I myself do not come into question at all, and the only point of view
is: How does my labor serve the others? — then the whole thing
is changed. Nothing then compels me to undertake anything which may
be of detriment to someone else. Then I place my powers not at the
service of myself, but at the service of the other people. And, as a
consequence, men's powers and abilities take quite a different
form of expression.
How this alters the conditions of life in actual practice shall be left
to the next chapter.
|