Introduction
On August
18, 1787, Goethe wrote to Knebel from Italy: “To judge by the
plants and fish I have seen in Naples and Sicily, I would, if I were
ten years younger, be very tempted to make a trip to India, not in
order to discover something new, but in order to contemplate in my
own way what has already been discovered.” In these words
is to be found the point of view from which we have to look at
Goethe's scientific works. With him it is never a matter of
discovering new facts, but rather of opening up a new point of
view, of looking at nature in a particular way. It is true that
Goethe made a number of great single discoveries, such as the
intermaxillary bone, the vertebral theory of the skull in osteology,
the common identity of all plant organs with the leaf in botany, etc.
But we have to regard as the life and soul of all these individual
cases the magnificent view of nature by which they are carried; in
the study of organisms we have to fix our attention above all on a
magnificent discovery that overshadows everything else: that of
[the being or nature of] the organism itself. Goethe has set forth
the principle by which an organism is what it presents itself to be;
he sets forth the causes whose results appear to us in the manifestations
of life; he sets forth, in fact, everything we can ask about the
manifestations of life from a point of view concerned with principles
[ 1 ].
From the beginning, this is the goal of all his striving with respect
to the organic natural sciences; in his pursuit of this goal, those
particular discoveries arose for him as though of themselves. He had
to find them if he did not want to be hindered in his further
striving. Natural science before him — which, did not know the
essential being of life phenomena, and which simply investigated
organisms as compositions of parts, according to outer
characteristics, just as one does with inorganic things — often
had, along its way, to give these particulars an incorrect
interpretation, to present them in a false light. One cannot of
course see any such error in the particulars themselves. But we will
recognize this only after we have first understood the organism,
since the particulars in themselves, considered separately, do not
bear within themselves the principle that explains them. They can be
explained only by the nature of the whole, because it is the whole
that gives them being and significance. Only after Goethe had
discovered precisely this nature of the whole did these erroneous
interpretations become evident to him; they could not be reconciled
with his theory of living beings; they contradicted it. If he wanted
to go further on his way, he would have to clear away such
preconceptions. This was the case with the intermaxillary bone.
Certain facts that are of value and interest only if one possesses
just such a theory as that of the vertebral nature of the skull bone
were unknown to that older natural science. All these hindrances had
to be cleared away by means of individual discoveries. These,
therefore, never appear in Goethe's case as ends in themselves; they
must always be made in order to confirm a great thought, to confirm
that central discovery. The fact cannot be denied that
Goethe's contemporaries came to the same observations sooner or
later, and that all of them would perhaps be known today even without
Goethe's efforts; but even less can the fact be denied that no one
until now has expressed his great discovery, encompassing all organic
nature, independently of him in such an exemplary way
[ 2 ]
— in fact, we still lack an even partially satisfactory appreciation
of his discovery. Basically it does not matter whether Goethe was the
first to discover a certain fact or only rediscovered it; the fact
first gains its true significance through the way he fits it into his
view of nature. This is what has been overlooked until now. The
particular facts have been overly emphasized and this has led to
polemics. One has indeed often pointed to Goethe's conviction about
the consistency of nature, but one did not recognize that the main
thing, in organic science for example, is to show what the nature is
of that which maintains this consistency. If one calls it the typus,
then one must say in what the being of the typus consists in
Goethe's sense of the word.
The significance of Goethe's view about plant metamorphosis does not
lie, for example, in the discovery of the individual fact that leaf,
calyx, corolla, etc., are identical organs, but rather in the
magnificent building up in thought of a living whole of mutually
interacting formative laws; this building up proceeds from his view
of plant metamorphosis, and determines out of itself the individual
details and the individual stages of plant development. The greatness
of this idea, which Goethe then sought to extend to the animal world
also, dawns upon one only when one tries to make it alive in one's
spirit, when one undertakes to rethink it. One then becomes aware
that this thought is the very nature of the plant itself translated
into the idea and living in our spirit just as it lives in the
object; one observes also that one makes an organism alive for
oneself right into its smallest parts, that one pictures it not as a
dead, finished object, but rather as something evolving, becoming, as
something never at rest within itself.
As we now attempt, in what follows, to present more thoroughly
everything we have indicated here, there will become clear to us at
the same time the true relationship of the Goethean view of nature to
that of our own age, and especially to the theory of evolution in its
modern form.
|