XVIII
Goethe's World View in his
Aphorisms in Prose
The human
being is not content with what nature willingly offers to his
observing spirit. He feels that nature, in order to bring forth the
manifoldness of its creations, needs driving forces that it at first
conceals from the observer. Nature does not itself utter its final
word. Our experience shows us what nature can create, but does not
tell us how this creating occurs. Within the human spirit itself
there lies the means for bringing the driving forces of nature to
light. Up out of the human spirit the ideas arise that bring
clarification as to how nature brings about its creations. What the
phenomena of the outer world conceal becomes revealed within the
inner being of man. What the human spirit thinks up in the way of
natural laws is not invented and added to nature; it is nature's own
essential being, and the human spirit is only the stage upon which
nature allows the secrets of its workings to become visible. What we
observe about the things is only one part of the things. What
wells up within our spirit when it confronts the things is the other
part. It is the same things that speak to us from outside and that
speak within us. Only when we hold the language of the outer world
together with that of our inner being, do we have full reality. What
have the true philosophers in every age wanted to do? Nothing other
than to make known the essential being of things that the things
themselves express when the human spirit offers itself to them as
their organ of speech.
When man allows his inner being to speak about nature, he recognizes
that nature falls short of what, by virtue of its driving forces, it
could accomplish. The human spirit sees what experience contains, in
its more perfect form. It finds that nature with its creations does
not achieve its aims. The human spirit feels itself called upon to
present these aims in their perfected form. It creates shapes in
which it shows: This is what nature wanted to do but could only
accomplish to a certain degree. These shapes are the works of art. In
them, the human being creates in a perfected way what nature
manifests in an imperfect form.
The philosopher and the artist have the same goal. They seek to give
shape to the perfected element that their spirit beholds when it
allows nature to work upon it. But they have different media at their
command for achieving this goal. For the philosopher, a thought,
an idea, lights up within him when he confronts a process in
nature. This he expresses. For the artist, a picture of this
process arises within him that manifests this process more perfectly
than can be observed in the outer world. The philosopher and the
artist develop the observation further in different ways. The artist
does not need to know the driving forces of nature in the form in
which they reveal themselves to the philosopher. When the artist
perceives a thing or an occurrence, there arises directly in his
spirit a picture in which the laws of nature are expressed in a more
perfect form than in the corresponding thing or occurrence in the
outer world. These laws do not need to enter his spirit in the form
of thoughts. Knowledge and art, however, are inwardly related. They
show the potentialities of nature that do not come to full
development in merely outer nature.
When now within the spirit of a genuine artist, not only the
perfected pictures of things express themselves, but also the driving
forces of nature in the form of thoughts, then the common source of
philosophy and art appears with particular clarity before our eyes.
Goethe is such an artist. He reveals the same secrets to us in the
form of his works of art and in the form of thoughts. What he gave
shape to in his poetic works, this he expresses in his essays on
natural science and art and in his
Aphorisms in Prose
[ 83 ]
in the form of thoughts. The deep satisfaction that emanates
from these essays and aphorisms stems from the fact that one sees the
harmony of art and knowledge realized in one personality. There is
something elevating in the feeling, which arises with every Goethean
thought, that here someone is speaking who at the same time can
behold in a picture the perfected element that he expresses in ideas.
The power of such a thought is strengthened by this feeling. That
which stems from the highest needs of one personality must
inwardly belong together. Goethe's teachings of wisdom answers the
question: What kind of philosophy is in accordance with genuine art?
I will try to sketch in context this philosophy that is born out of
the spirit of a genuine artist.
* * *
The
content of thought that springs from the human spirit when it
confronts the outer world is truth. The human being cannot demand any
other kind of knowledge than one he brings forth himself. Whoever
seeks something in addition behind the things that is supposed to
signify their actual being has not brought to consciousness the fact
that all questions about the essential being of things spring only
from a human need: the need, namely, also to penetrate with thought
what one perceives. The things speak to us, and our inner being
speaks when we observe the things. These two languages stem from the
same primal being, and man is called upon to effect their reciprocal
understanding. It is in this that what one calls knowledge consists.
And it is this and nothing else that a person seeks who understands
the needs of human nature. For someone who has not arrived at this
understanding, the things of the outer world remain foreign. He does
not hear the essential being of things speaking within his inner
life. Therefore he supposes that this essential being is hidden
behind the things. He believes in yet another outer world in
addition, behind the perceptual world. But things are outer things
only so long as one merely observes them. When one thinks about them,
they cease to be outside of us. One fuses with their inner being. For
man, opposition between objective outer perception and subjective
inner thought-world exists only as long as he does not recognize that
these worlds belong together. Man's inner world is the inner being of
nature.
These thoughts are not refuted by the fact that different people make
different mental pictures of things for themselves. Nor by the fact
that people's organizations are different so that one does not know
whether one and the same colour is seen by different people in
exactly the same way. For, the point is not whether people form
exactly the same judgment about one and the same thing, but whether
the language that the inner being of a person speaks is in fact the
language that expresses the essential being of things. Individual
judgments differ according to the organization of the person and
according to the standpoint from which one observes things; but all
judgments spring from the same element and lead into the essential
being of things. This can come to expression in different nuances of
thought; but it is, nevertheless, still the essential being of
things.
The human being is the organ by which nature reveals its secrets.
Within the subjective personality the deepest content of the world
appears. “When the healthy nature of man works as a whole, when
he feels himself in the world as though in a great, beautiful,
worthy, and precious whole, when his harmonious sense of well-being
imparts to him a pure, free delight, then the universe, if it could
experience itself, would, as having achieved its goal, exult with
joy and marvel at the pinnacle of its own becoming and being.”
(Goethe, Winckelmann) The goal of the universe and of the essential
being of existence does not lie in what the outer world provides, but
rather in what lives within the human spirit and goes forth from it.
Goethe therefore considers it to be a mistake for the natural
scientist to want to penetrate into the inner being of nature through
instruments and objective experiments, for “man in himself,
insofar as he uses his healthy senses, is the greatest and most
accurate physical apparatus that there can be, and that is precisely
what is of the greatest harm to modern physics, that one has, as it
were, separated experiments from man; one wants to know nature merely
through what manmade instruments show, yes, wants to limit and prove
thereby what nature can do.” “But man stands at such a
high level precisely through the fact that what otherwise could not
manifest itself does manifest itself in him. For what is a string and
all its mechanical divisions compared to the ear of the musician?
Yes, one can say, what are the elemental phenomena of nature
themselves compared to man who must first tame and modify them all in
order to be able to assimilate them to some extent?”
Man must allow the things to speak out of his spirit if he wants to
know their essential being. Everything he has to say about this
essential being is derived from the spiritual experiences of his
inner life. The human being can judge the world only from out of
himself. He must think anthropomorphically. One brings
anthropomorphism into the simplest phenomenon, into the impact of two
bodies, for example, when one says something about it. The judgment
that “one body strikes another” is already
anthropomorphic. For if one wants to go beyond the mere observation
of the process, one must bring to it the experience our own body has
when it sets a body in the outer world into motion. All physical
explanations are hidden anthropomorphisms. One humanizes nature when
one explains it; one puts into it the inner experiences of the human
being. But these subjective experiences are the inner being of
things. And one cannot therefore say that, because man can make only
subjective mental pictures for himself about nature, he does not know
the objective truth, the “in-itself” of things.
[ 84 ]
There can absolutely be no question of anything other than a
subjective human truth. For, truth consists in putting our subjective
experiences into the objective interrelationships of phenomena. These
subjective experiences can even assume a completely individual
character. They are, nevertheless, the expression of the inner being
of things. One can put into the things only what one has experienced
within oneself. Thus, each person, in accordance with his individual
experiences, will also put something different, in a certain sense,
into things. The way I interpret certain processes of nature for
myself is not entirely comprehensible for someone else who has not
inwardly experienced the same thing. It is not at all a matter,
however, of all men having the same thoughts about things, but rather
only of their living within the element of truth when they think
about things. One cannot therefore observe the thoughts of another
person as such and accept or reject them, but rather one should
regard them as the proclaimers of his individuality. “Those who
contradict and dispute should reflect now and then that not every
language is comprehensible to everyone.” A philosophy can never
provide a universally valid truth, but rather describes the inner
experiences of the philosopher by which he interprets the outer
phenomena.
* * *
When a
thing expresses its essential being through the organ of the human
spirit, then full reality comes about only through the flowing
together of the outer objective and the inner subjective. It is
neither through one-sided observation nor through one-sided thinking
that the human being knows reality. Reality is not present in the
objective world as something finished, but rather is only first
brought forth by the human spirit in connection with the things. The
objective things are only a part of reality. To someone who extols
sense experience exclusively, one must reply like Goethe “that
experience is only half of experience.” “Everything
factual is already theory”; that means, an ideal element
reveals itself in the human spirit when he observes something
factual. This way of apprehending the world, which knows the
essential being of things in ideas and which apprehends knowledge to
be a living into the essential being of things, is not mysticism. But
it does have in common with mysticism the characteristic that it does
not regard objective truth as something that is present in the outer
world, but rather as something that can really be grasped within the
inner being of man. The opposite world view transfers the ground of
things to behind the phenomena, into a region lying beyond human
experience. This view can then either give itself over to a blind
faith in this ground that receives its content from a positive
religion of revelation, or it can set up intellectual hypotheses and
theories as to how this realm of reality in the beyond is
constituted. The mystic, as well as the adherent of the Goethean
world view, rejects both this faith in some “beyond” and
all hypotheses about any such region, and holds fast to the really
spiritual element that expresses itself within man himself. Goethe
writes to Jacobi: “God has punished you with metaphysics
and set a thorn in your flesh, but has blessed me, on the
other hand, with physics. ... I hold more and more firmly to
the reverence for God of the atheist (Spinoza) ... and leave to you
everything you call, and would have to call, religion ... When you
say that one can only believe in God ... then I say to you
that I set a lot of store in seeing.” What Goethe wants
to see is the essential being of things that expresses itself within
his world of ideas. The mystic also wants to know the essential being
of things by immersing himself in his own inner being; but he rejects
precisely that innately clear and transparent world of ideas as
unsuitable for attaining higher knowledge. He believes he must
develop, not his capacity for ideas, but rather other powers of his
inner being, in order to see the primal ground of things. Usually it
is unclear feelings and emotions in which the mystic wants to grasp
the essential being of things. But feelings and emotions belong only
to the subjective being of man. In them nothing is expressed about
the things. Only in ideas do the things themselves speak. Mysticism
is a superficial world view, in spite of the fact that the mystics
are very proud of their “profundity” compared to men of
reason. The mystics know nothing about the nature of feelings,
otherwise they would not consider them to be expressions of the
essential being of the world; and they know nothing about the nature
of ideas, otherwise they would not consider them shallow and
rationalistic. They have no inkling of what people who really have
ideas experience in them. But for many people, ideas are in fact mere
words. They cannot acquire for themselves the unending fullness of
their content. No wonder they feel their own word husks, which are
devoid of ideas, to be empty.
* * *
Whoever seeks the essential content of the objective world within his
own inner being can also regard the essential being of the moral
world order as lying only within human nature itself. Whoever
believes in the existence of a reality in the beyond, behind human
reality, must also seek the source of morality there. For, what is
moral in a higher sense can come only from the essential being of
things. The believer in the beyond therefore assumes moral
commandments to which man must submit himself. These commandments
reach him either via revelation, or they enter as such into his
consciousness, as is the case with Kant's categorical imperative. As
to how this imperative comes into our consciousness from out of the
“in-itselfness” of things in the beyond, about this
nothing is said. It is simply there, and one must submit oneself to
it. The philosopher of experience, who looks for his salvation in
pure sense observation, sees in what is moral, only the working of
human drives and instincts. Out of the study of these, norms are
supposed to result that are decisive for moral action.
Goethe sees what is moral as arising out of man's world of ideas. It
is not objective norms and also not the mere world of drives that
directs moral action, but rather it is ideas, clear within
themselves, by which man gives himself his own direction. He does not
follow them out of duty as he would have to follow objective moral
norms. And also not out of compulsion, as one follows one's drives
and instincts. But rather he serves them out of love. He loves them
the way one loves a child. He wants to realize them, and steps in on
their behalf, because they are a part of his own essential being. The
idea is the guideline and love is the driving power in
Goethean ethics. For him duty is “where one loves what one
commands oneself to do.”
Action, in the sense of Goethean ethics, is a free action.
For, the human being is dependent upon nothing other than his own
ideas. And he is responsible to no one other than himself. In my
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
I have already refuted the feeble
objection that a moral world order in which each person obeys only
himself would have to lead to a general disorder and disharmony in
human action. Whoever makes this objection overlooks the fact that
human beings are essentially alike in nature and that they will
therefore never produce moral ideas which, through their essential
differentness would cause discord.
[ 85 ]
* * *
If the
human being did not have the ability to bring forth creations that
are fashioned in exactly the same sense as the works of nature and
only bring this sense to view in a more perfect way than nature can,
there would be no art in Goethe's sense. What the artist creates are
nature objects on a higher level of perfection. Art is the extension
of nature, “for inasmuch as man is placed at the pinnacle of
nature, he then regards himself again as an entire nature, which yet
again has to bring forth within itself a pinnacle. To this end he
enhances himself, by imbuing himself with every perfection and
virtue, summons choice, order, harmony, and meaning, and finally
lifts himself to the production of works of art.” After
seeing Greek works of art in Italy, Goethe writes: “These great
works of art have at the same time been brought forth by human beings
according to true and natural laws, as the greatest works of nature”
(Italian Journey, September 6, 1787).
For the merely
sense-perceptible reality of experience, works of art are a beautiful
semblance; for someone who is able to see more deeply, they are “a
manifestation of hidden laws of nature which without them would never
be revealed.”
It is not the substance the artist takes from nature that constitutes
the work of art; but only what the artist puts into the work of art
from out of his inner being. The highest work of art is one that
makes you forget that a natural substance underlies it, and that
awakens our interest solely through what the artist has made out of
this substance. The artist forms things naturally; but he does not
form things the way nature itself does. These statements to me
express the main thoughts that Goethe set down in his aphorisms on
art.
|