First
Appendix
(Addendum
to the Revised Edition of 1918)
Certain objections raised from
philosophical quarters immediately after the appearance of this book move me
to add the following brief comments to this new edition. I can very well
imagine that there are readers interested in the content of this book who
will nevertheless regard the following as a superfluous, remote, and abstract
spinning out of concepts. They can leave this brief presentation unread.
However, within the philosophical way of looking at the world, problems arise
which have their origin more in certain preconceptions of thinkers than in
the natural course of general human thinking. What is otherwise taken upon in
this book seems tome to be a task which concerns every person who is
struggling for clarity with respect to the being of man and his relationship
to the world. What follows, however, is more a problem that certain
philosophers demand be taken up when the things presented in this boo are
discussed, because, through their way of picturing things, these philosophers
have created for themselves certain difficulties not generally present. If
one completely bypasses such problems, then certain personalities are quick
at hand with the reproach of dilettantism and the like. And there arises an
opinion as though the author of a presentation like the one given in this
book had not come to terms with views which he does not discuss within the
book itself.
The problem to which I refer is
this; there are thinkers who are of the opinion that a particular difficulty
arises when one wants to grasp how another human soul life could affect
one's own (the observer's). They say that my conscious world is
enclosed within me; and the other conscious world likewise within itself. I
cannot see into the world of consciousness of another. How do I arrive at
knowing myself to be in a common world with him? That world view which
regards it as possible to infer, from the conscious world, an unconscious one
that can never become conscious attempts to solve this difficulty in the
following fashion. It says that the world which I have in my consciousness is
a representation in me of a world of reality not consciously attainable by
me. In this world of reality lie the unknown causes of my world of
consciousness. In it lies also my real being, of which I likewise have only a
representation in my consciousness. In it lies also my real being, of which I
likewise have only a representation in my consciousness. In it lies also,
however, the being of the other person who approaches me. Now what is
experienced in the consciousness of this other person has its corresponding
reality, independent of his consciousness, within his being This reality
works in the realm that cannot become conscious upon my essential unconscious
being, and through this a representation is created in my consciousness for
that which is present in a consciousness that is completely independent of my
conscious experience. One can see that here, in addition to the world
accessible to my consciousness, a world is hypothetically constructed which
cannot be experienced by this consciousness, because otherwise one believes
oneself forced to maintain that all the outer word which I believe I have
before me is only my word of consciousness, and that would result in the
solipsistic absurdity that other people also live only within my
consciousness.
Clarity can also be gained
on this question, raised by many epistemological tendencies of our day, if
one undertakes to look at the matter from the point of view of observation in
accordance with the spirit taken in the presentation of this book. What do I
have before me then to begin with when I confront another personality? I look
at what is most immediate. This is the bodily manifestation of the other
person given to me as perception; then in addition perhaps the audible
perception of what he says, and so on. I do not merely stare at all this, but
rather it sets my thinking activity in motion. Inasmuch as I stand, thinking,
before the other personality, the perception reveals to me its characteristic
of being in a certain way transparent to the soul. I am obliged, in grasping
the perception in thinking, to say to myself that it is not at all that which
it appears to be to the outer senses. The physical manifestation reveals,
within what it is directly, something else which it is indirectly. Its
placing itself before me is at the same time its extinguishing as a merely
physical manifestation. But what it brings to manifestation in this
extinguishing compels me as a thinking being to extinguish my thinking during
the time of its working and to set in the place of my thinking, its
thinking. Its thinking, however, I grasp within my thinking as an
experience like my own. I have really perceived the thinking of the other
person. For the direct perception which extinguishes itself as a physical
manifestation is grasped by my thinking, and this is an occurrence lying
completely within my consciousness, an occurrence which consists in
the fact that the other thinking takes the place of my thinking. Through the
physical manifestation's extinguishing itself, the separation between
the two spheres of consciousness is actually removed. This represents itself
within my consciousness through the fact that, in experiencing the other
content of consciousness, I experience my own consciousness just as little as
I experience it in dreamless sleep. Just as in dreamless sleep my day
consciousness is excluded, so in perceiving the other content of
consciousness my own content is excluded. What keeps me from recognizing this
is only the fact that, firstly, when I perceive the other person,
unconsciousness does not enter the place where the content of my own
consciousness is extinguished as in sleep, but rather the other content of
consciousness enters, and secondly, that the alternating states of the
extinguishing and lighting up again of my consciousness of myself succeed one
another too quickly to be usually noticed. — The whole problem lying
before us here is not to be solved by artificial constructs of concepts which
infer something conscious-in-itself that can never become conscious, but
rather by true experiencing of what results from the joining of thinking and
perception. This is the case with very many of the questions which appear in
philosophical literature. Thinkers should seek the way to unprejudiced
observation in accordance with the spirit; instead of this they thrust an
artificial construct of concepts in front of reality.
In an essay by Eduard von
Hartmann on “The Ultimate Questions of Epistemology and
Metaphysics” (in the Journal of Philosophy and Philosophical Criticism,
Vol. 108, p. 55ff.)* my
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
is included
in that philosophical discussion of thought which wishes to base itself upon
an “epistemological monism.” Such a standpoint is rejected by
Eduard von Hartmann as an impossible one. He does this for the following
reasons. According to the way of picturing things brought to expression in
his essay, there are only three possible epistemological standpoints. Either
a person remains at the naive standpoint, which takes the manifestations it
perceives to be real things outside of human consciousness. Then one would
lack critical knowledge. One would not see that one is, with one's content
of consciousness, still only within one's own consciousness. One would
not recognize that one does not have to do with a
“table-in-itself,” but rather only with an object of one's
own consciousness. Whoever remains at this standpoint or returns to it again
through some consideration or other, is a naive realist. But this standpoint
is impossible, however, for it overlooks the fact that consciousness has only
its own objects of consciousness. Or one recognizes this state of affairs and
admits it to oneself fully. Then one becomes at first a transcendental
idealist. But then one would have to reject the possibility that anything of
a “thing-in-itself” could ever appear within human consciousness.
Through this, however, one cannot escape absolute illusionism, if one is only
consistent enough about it. For the world which one confronts transforms
itself for one into a mere sum total of objects of consciousness, and in fact
only of objects of one's own consciousness. One is then compelled
— and this absurd — to think that even other people as objects
are present only in one's own content of consciousness alone. Only the
third standpoint, transcendental realism, is a possible one. It assumes that
there are “things-in-themselves,” but that consciousness cannot
in any way have anything to do with them in immediate experience. Beyond
human consciousness, in a way that does not enter consciousness, they bring
it about that within consciousness the objects of consciousness appear. One
can come to these “things-in-themselves” only through inferences
drawn from the content of one's consciousness which alone is
experienced but which in fact is merely one's mental pictures. Now
Eduard von Hartmann maintains, in the essay mentioned above, that an
“epistemological monism,” which he considers my standpoint to be,
would have to espouse one of the three standpoints; it does not do so only
because it does not draw the actual conclusions lying within its
presuppositions. And then in the essay it is said, “If one wants to
find out which epistemological standpoint a supposed epistemological monist
belongs, then one needs only to lay a few questions before him and to compel
him to answer them. For of himself no such monist will ever venture any
utterance on these points, and he will even seek in every way to evade
answering direct questions, because every answer invalidates the claim of
epistemological monism as to its being a different standpoint than the other
three. These questions are the following: 1. Are things continuous or
intermittent in their existence? If the answer is that they are
continuous, then one has to do with naive realism in one form or anther. If
the answer is that they are intermittent, then it is a case of transcendental
idealism. But if the answer is that they are on the one hand (as content of
the absolute consciousness, or as unconscious mental pictures or as
perceptual possibilities) continuous, and on the other hand (as content of
our limited consciousness) intermittent, then transcendental realism is
established. 2. If three people are sitting at a table, how many specimens
of the table are present? Whoever answers ‘one,’ is a naive
realist; whoever answers ‘three’ is a transcendental idealist,
but whoever answers ‘four,’ he is a transcendental realist. It
is, to be sure, assumed in this, that one is allowed to draw together into
one common appellation ‘specimens of the table,’ such unlike
things as the table as thing-in-itself, and the three tables as objects of
perception within the three consciousnesses. If this seems too great a
liberty to anyone, he will have to give the answer ‘one and
three’ instead of ‘four.’ 3. If two people are alone
together in a room, how many specimens of these people are present?
Whoever answers ‘two’ is a naive realist; whoever answers
‘four’ (namely, in each of the two consciousnesses, one ego and
one other), he is a transcendental idealist; but whoever answers
‘six’ (namely, two people as things-in-themselves, and four
mental pictures of people within the two consciousnesses), he is a
transcendental realist. Whoever wanted to show that epistemological monism is
a different standpoint than these three, would have to give to each of these
three questions some different answer; I wouldn't know, however, what
they could be.” The answers of the
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
would have to be: 1. Whoever grasps only the perceptual content
of things and considers this to be reality is a naive realist, and he does
not make it clear to himself that he should actually regard this
perceptual content as existing only for as long as he is looking at the
things, that therefore he would have to think of what he has before him as
intermittent. As soon as he becomes clear about the fact, however, that
reality is present only when the perceptible is permeated with thought, will
he attain the insight that the content of perception, appearing as
intermittent, if permeated by what is worked out in thinking, reveals itself
to be continuous. We must therefore regard as continuous the perceptual
content grasped by a thinking which is experienced; the part of this content
that is only perceived would have to be thought of as intermittent, if
— which is not the case — it were real. — 2. If three
people are sitting at a table, how many specimens of the table are present?
There is only one table present; but as long as the three
people wanted to stop short at their perceptual pictures, they would have to
say that these perceptual pictures are definitely no reality. As soon
as they proceed to the table grasped in their thinking, the one
reality of the table reveals itself to them; they are united with their three
contents of consciousness within this reality. — 3. If two people are
alone together in a room, how many specimens of these people are present?
There are quite certainly not six — not even I the sense of the
transcendental realist — specimens present, but only two. Only, each of
the persons has at first, both of himself and of the other person, only his
unreal perceptual picture. Of these pictures there are four present,
through whose presence within the thinking activities of the two persons the
grasping of reality takes place. In this thinking activity each of the
persons reaches beyond his sphere of consciousness; the sphere of
consciousness, the other person's and his own, comes to life in this
activity. In the moment this comes to life the two people are enclosed just
as little within their consciousness as they are in sleep. But in the other
moments, the consciousness of this merging with the other consciousness
arises again, in such a way that, in thinking experience the consciousness of
each one of the two people grasps himself and the other. I know that the
transcendental realist will call this a relapse into naive realism. However,
I have already indicated in this book that naive realism still holds good for
thinking which is experienced. The transcendental realist does not enter at
all into the true state of affairs with respect to the cognitive process; he
closes himself off from this through a web of thoughts and entangles himself
in it. The monism which appears in
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
should also not be called “epistemological,” bur
rather, if one wishes a second name, thought-monism. All this was
misunderstood by Eduard von Hartmann. He did not enter into that which is
particular in what
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
presents, but rather asserted that I had made the attempt to combine Hegel's
universalistic panlogism with Hume's individualistic phenomenalism
(p. 71 of the Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 108, footnote),**
whereas in fact
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
as such has absolutely nothing to
do with these two standpoints which it is supposedly trying to unite. (This is
also the reason I could not be concerned about coming to terms, for example,
with the “epistemological monism” of Johannes Rehmke. The point
of view of
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
is, in fact, completely different from what Eduard von Hartmann and others
call epistemological monism.)
*“Die letzten Fragen der Erkenntnistheorie
und Metaphysik,” Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische
Kritik.
**Zeitschrift fur Philosophie
|