II
The Fundamental Desire for
Knowledge
Two souls
alas! are dwelling in my breast;
And each is
fain to leave its brother.
The one, fast
clinging, to the world adheres
With
clutching organs, in love's sturdy lust;
The other
strongly lifts itself from dust
To yonder
high ancestral spheres.
Faust
I, Sc. 2
(Priest translation)
With these words Goethe expresses a
characteristic deeply founded in human nature. Man is not whole in the
organization of his being. He demands always more than the world gives him of
its own accord. Nature has given us needs; among these are such whose
satisfaction it has left to our own activity. Abundant are the gifts
apportioned us, but still more abundant is our desiring. We seem born to be
discontented. One particular instance of this discontent is our urge to know.
We look twice at a tree. The one time we see it branches at rest, the other
time in motion. We do not content ourselves with this observation. Why does
the tree present itself to us the one time at rest, the other time in motion?
We ask about things in this way. Every look into nature produced a number of
questions in us. With every phenomenon that comes our way a task is set us
along with it. Every experience becomes a riddle for us. We see emerge from
the egg a being that resembles the mother animal; we ask for the reason for
this resemblance. We observe in a living being growth and development to a
particular level of perfection; we seek the determining factors of this
experience. Nowhere are we content with what nature spreads out before our
senses. We seek everywhere what we call explanation of the facts.
The fact that what we seek in
things exceeds what is directly given us in them, splits our entire being in
two parts; we become conscious of our polar opposition to the world. We
confront the world as independent beings. The universe appears to us in the
polarity: I and the world.
We erect this wall of separation
between us and the world as soon as consciousness lights up within us. But
never do we lose the feeling that we belong even so to the world, that a bond
endures that joins us to it, that we are not beings outside, but
rather inside the universe.
This feeling creates the striving
to bridge the polarity. And the entire spiritual striving of mankind
ultimately consists in the bridging of this polarity. The history of our
spiritual life is a continuous searching for the unity between us and the
world. Religion, art, and science all pursue this goal. The religious
believer seeks, within the revelation which God allots to him, the solution
to the world riddle that his “I,” not content with the world of
mere phenomena, poses him. The artist seeks to fashion into matter the ideas
of his “I,” in order to reconcile what lives in his inner being
with the outer world. He too feels himself unsatisfied by the world of mere
phenomena and seeks to mold into it that something more which his
“I,” transcending the world of phenomena, contains. The thinker
searches for the laws of phenomena; he strives, thinking, to penetrate what
he experiences observing. Only when we have made the world content
into our thought content, only then do we find again the connection
from which we ourselves have detached ourselves. We will see later on that
this goal will only be attained if the task of the scientific researcher is
in fact grasped much more deeply than is often done. The whole relationship I
have presented here confronts us in a world-historical manifestation: in the
polarity of the one-word view or monism, to the two-world theory or
dualism. Dualism directs its gaze only upon the separation between
“I” and world brought about by the consciousness of man. Its
whole striving is an ineffectual struggle to reconcile this polarity, which it
sometimes calls spirit and matter, sometimes subject and
object, sometimes thinking and phenomenon. It has a
feeling that there must be a bridge between the two worlds, but it is not
capable of finding it. In that the human being experiences himself as
“I,” he cannot but think of this “I” as being on the
side of the spirit; and in that he sets the world over against this
“I,” he must reckon to this world, the world of perception given
to the senses, the material world. Man places himself thereby into the
polarity of spirit and matter. He must do this all the more since his own
body belongs to the material world. The “I” belongs in this way
to the spiritual as a part of it; the material things and processes
that are perceived by the senses belong to the “world,” All the
riddles relating to spirit and matter must be found again by man within the
fundamental riddle of his own being. Monism directs its gaze upon the
unity alone and seeks to deny or obliterate the polarities actually present.
Neither of the two views can satisfy, for they do not do justice to the
facts. Dualism sees spirit (“I”) and matter (world) as two
fundamentally different entities, and therefore cannot grasp how the two can
interact with each other. How should the spirit know what is going on in
matter, if matter's essential nature is entirely alien to it? Or how
should the spirit under these circumstances work upon matter in such a way
that its intentions transform themselves into deeds? The most ingenious and
most contradictory hypotheses were set up in order to solve these questions.
Up to the present, however, monism is not in a much better position. It has
sought help up till now in three ways: either it denies the spirit and
becomes materialism; or it denies matter, in order to seek its salvation in
spiritualism; or, it maintains that matter and spirit are already inseparably
joined even in the most simple entity in the world, for which reason one need
not be surprised if these two kinds of existence, which after all are nowhere
separated, appear within the human being.
Materialism can never
provide a satisfactory explanation of the world. For every attempt at an
explanation must begin with one's forming thoughts for oneself
about the phenomena of the world.
Materialism therefore takes its start with
the thought of matter or of material processes. Thus it already has
two different realms of facts before it: the material world and thoughts
about it. It seeks to understand the latter by grasping them as a purely
material process. It believes that thinking takes place in the brain in about
the same way as digestion does in the animal organs. Just as it attributes to
matter mechanical and organic effects, so it also ascribes to it the
capability, under specific conditions, to think. It forgets that it has now
only transferred the problem to another place. It attributes the capability
of thinking not to itself but to matter. And in doing so it is back again at
its starting point. How does matter come to reflect upon its own being? Why
is it not simply satisfied with itself and accepting of its existence? The
materialist has turned his gaze away form the specific subject, from our own
“I,” and has arrived at an indefinite, hazy configuration. And
here the same riddle comes to meet him. The materialistic view is not able to
solve the problem, but only to shift it.
How do matters stand with the
spiritualistic view? The pure spiritualist denies matter in its
independent existence and apprehends it only as product of the spirit. If he
applies this world view to solving the riddle of his own human nature, he is,
in doing so, driven into a corner. Confronting the “I,” which can
be placed on the side of spirit, there stands, without intermediary, the
sensory world. Into this, no spiritual entry seems to open; this world
has to be perceived and experienced by the “I” through material
processes. The “I” does not find any such material processes
within itself, if it wants to be considered only as a spiritual entity. The
sense world is never present in what the “I” works through
spiritually for itself. It seems the “I” must admit that the
world would remain closed to it, if the “I” were not to put
itself into a relationship with it in an unspiritual way. In like manner, when
we come to act, we must transform our intentions into reality with the help
of the material substances and forces. We are, therefore, reliant on the
outer world. The most extreme spiritualist, or if you will, the thinker
presenting himself as extreme spiritualist through absolute idealism, is
Johann Gottlieb Fichte. He attempted to derive the whole edifice of the world
out of the “I.” What he actually achieved thereby is a
magnificent thought picture of the world, without any content of
experience. Just as little as it is possible for the materialist to banish
spirit by decree, it is possible for the spiritualist to banish the outer
material world by decree.
Because the human being, when he
directs his knowledge to the “I,” perceives to begin with the
working of this “I” within the thinking elaboration of the world
of ideas, the spiritualistically oriented world view can feel itself tempted,
by looking at its own human nature, to acknowledge of the spirit only this
world of ideas. Spiritualism becomes in this way one-sided idealism. It does
not come to the point, through the world of ideas, of seeking a
spiritual world; it sees in the world of ideas itself the spiritual
world. It is compelled thereby to remain as though spellbound within the
activity of the “I” itself.
A curious variant of idealism is
the view of Friedrich Albert Lange which he has presented in his widely read
History of Materialism.*
He supposes that materialism is totally right
when it explains all phenomena, including our thinking, as the product of
purely material processes; but conversely, matter and its processes
themselves are again a product of our thinking. “The senses give us
... effects of things, not accurate pictures, let alone the things
themselves. To these mere effects belong however also the senses themselves,
along with the brain and the movements of molecules thought to be in
it.” That means our thinking is produced by the material processes, and
these by the thinking of the “I.” Lange's philosophy is
thereby nothing other than the story, translated into concepts, of the
intrepid Münchhausen, who holds himself up freely in the air by his own
pigtail.
*Geschichte des
Matrialismus
The third form of monism is that
which sees within the simplest entity (atom) the two entities of matter and
spirit already united. But all that is achieved here is that the question,
which actually arises in our consciousness, is shifted to another arena. How
does the simple entity come to manifest itself in a twofold way, if it is an
undivided whole?
With respect to all these
standpoints we must note that the basic and original polarity comes to meet
us first of all within our own consciousness. It is we who detach ourselves
from the mother ground of nature, and place ourselves as “I” over
against the “world.” Goethe expresses this classically in his
essay, “Nature,” even though his approach may at first be
considered completely unscientific: “We live in the midst of her
(nature) and are foreign to her. She speaks unceasingly to us and does not
betray her secret.” But Goethe also knows the reverse side:
“Human beings are all within her and she within all human
beings.”
As true as it is that we have
estranged ourselves from nature, it is just as true that we feel that we are
within it and belong to it. It can only be its own working that also lives in
us.
We must find the way back to it
again. A simple consideration can show us this way. We have, it is true, torn
ourselves from nature; but we must nevertheless have taken something over
with us into our own being. We must seek out this being of nature within us,
and then we will also find the connection again. Dualism neglects to do this.
It considers the inner being of man to be a spiritual entity totally foreign
to nature and seeks to attach this entity onto nature. No wonder that it
cannot find the connecting link. We can find nature outside us only when we
first know it within us. What is akin to it in our own inner being
will be our guide. Our course is thereby sketched out for us. We do not want
to engage in any speculations about the interaction of nature and spirit. We
want, however, to descend into the depths of our own being, in order to find
there those elements which we have rescued in our flight from nature.
The exploration of our being must
bring us the solution to the riddle. We must come to the point where we can
say to ourselves: here we are no longer merely “I,” here lies
something that is more than “I.”
I am prepared for the objection
that many who have read this far will not find my expositions to be in
conformity with “the present-day position of scholarship.” I can
only reply that up till now I have not wanted to concern myself with
scholarship, but rather with the simple description of what everyone
experiences within his own consciousness. Individual sentences about attempts
of consciousness to reconcile itself with the world have also been included
only in order to make the actual facts clear. I have therefore also not
thought it important to use such single expressions as “I,”
“spirit,” “world,” “nature,” and so forth
in the precise way that is usual in psychology and philosophy. Everyday
consciousness does not know the sharp distinctions of scholarship, and until
now we have merely been dealing with an assimilation of the everyday state of
affairs. My concern is not how scholarship has interpreted consciousness
until now, but rather how consciousness expresses itself in every moment.
|