V
The
Activity of Knowing the World
It follows
from the preceding consideration that it is impossible, through investigation
of the content of our observation, to prove that our perceptions are mental
pictures. This was supposedly proven by showing that if the process of
perception does take place in the way one pictures it in accordance with the
naive-realistic assumptions about the psychological and physiological
constitution of our individuality, then we do not have to do with
things-in-themselves, but merely with our mental pictures of the things. Now
if naive realism consistently pursued, leads to results which represent the
exact opposite of its presuppositions, then these presuppositions must be
deemed unfit for founding a world view and must be dropped. In any case it is
inadmissible to reject the presuppositions and to allow what follows from
them to hold good, as does the critical idealist, who bases his assertion
that the world is my mental picture upon the line of argument above. (Eduard
von Hartmann, in his book
The Basic Problem of Epistemology,
gives a detailed presentation of this line of argument.
The
correctness of critical idealism is one thing; the power of its proofs to
convince in another. How matters stand with respect to the former will be
shown later in the course of our considerations. But the power of its proof
to convince is nil. If someone builds a house, and with the addition of the
second floor, the ground floor collapses, the second floor falls along with
it. Naive realism and critical idealism relate to each other as this ground
floor to the second floor.
Whoever is of
the view that the entire perceived world is only a mental picture, and indeed
the effect upon my soul of things unknown to me, for him the real question of
knowledge has to do of course not with the mental pictures which are only
present in my soul, but rather with the things which lie beyond our
consciousness and are independent of us. He asks how much we can know
indirectly about the latter, since they are not directly
accessible to our observations. Someone taking this standpoint does not
bother himself about the inner connection of his conscious perceptions, but
only about their no longer conscious causes, which have an existence
independent of him, while, in his view, the perceptions disappear as soon as
he turns his senses away from the things. Our consciousness functions, from
this point of view, like a mirror, whose images of specific things also
disappear the moment its reflecting surface is not directed toward them.
Someone, however, who does not see the things themselves, but only their
mirror images, must, from the behavior of the latter, inform himself
indirectly be inferences about the nature of the former. This is the
stand-point of modern science, which uses perceptions only as a last resort
to obtain information about the processes of matter which stand behind our
perceptions and which alone truly exist. If the philosopher as critical
idealist allows any real being to exist at all, then his striving for
knowledge, using mental pictures as a means, directs itself only to this real
being. His interest skips over the subjective world of mental pictures and
goes straight for what produces these mental pictures.
But the
critical idealist can go so far as to say that I am closed off in my world of
mental pictures and cannot get out of it. If I think a thing behind my mental
pictures, this thought is also, after all, nothing more than my mental
picture. Such an idealist will then either deny the thing-in-itself
completely, or at least declare it to have absolutely no significance for
human beings, which means that it is as good as not there, because we can
know nothing about it.
To a critical
idealist of this sort, the whole world appears as a dream, in the face of
which any urge for knowledge would be simply meaningless. For him there can
be only two types of people: deluded ones, who consider their own
dream-spinnings to be real things, and wise ones, who see into the
nothingness of this dream world and who, by and by, must lose all desire to
bother themselves further about it. From this standpoint even one's own
personality can become a mere dream image. In exactly the same way as our
own dream image appears among the images of our sleep-dreams, the mental
picture of my own “I” joins the mental picture of the outer world
within waking consciousness. We are given in our consciousness then, not our
real “I,” but only our mental picture “I.” Now,
whoever denies that things exist, or at least denies that we can know
anything about them, must also deny the existence — or, at least the
knowledge — of his own personality. The critical idealist comes then
to the declaration, “All reality transforms itself into a wonderful
dream, without a life that is dreamt, and without a spirit who is having
the dream; into a dream that hangs together with a dream about itself.”
(See Fichte,
The Vocation of Man.*)
*Die Bestimmung des Menschen
It does not
matter whether the person who believes that he knows our immediate life to be
a dream imagines there to be nothing behind this dream, or whether he relates
his mental pictures to real things: life itself must lose all scientific
interest for him. But while all science must be total nonsense for the person
who believes that the universe accessible to us is limited to a dream, for
the person who believes himself able to draw inferences about the things from
his mental pictures, science will consist in investigating these
“things-in-themselves.” The first view can be called absolute
illusionism; the second view is called transcendental realism
by Eduard von Hartmann, its most consequential proponent.*
*In terms of this
world view, knowledge is called transcendental which believes itself
to be conscious of the fact that nothing can be directly stated about the
things-in-themselves, but which draws indirect inference, from the known
subjective, about the unknown lying beyond the subjective (the
transcendental). According to this view, the thing-in-itself is beyond
the sphere of the world directly knowable for us: i.e., it
is transcendent. Our world, however, can be related to the transcendental
transcendentally. Hartmann's view is called realism, because it goes
out beyond the subjective, the ideal, to the transcendental, the
real.
Both these
views have in common with naive realism that they seek to gain a footing in
the world through an investigation of perceptions. But within this realm they
are nowhere able to find firm ground.
A major
question for the proponent of transcendental realism would have to be how the
“I” brings about the world of mental pictures out of itself. A
serious striving for knowledge about a world of mental pictures given to us,
which disappears as soon as we close our senses to the outer world, can
kindle itself only to the extent that such a world is a means of
investigating indirectly the world of the “I”-in-itself. If the
things of our experience were mental pictures, then our everyday life would
be like a dream and knowledge of the true state of affairs would be like
waking up. Our dream pictures also interest us as long as we are dreaming and
therefore not recognizing them in their dream character. The moment we wake
up we no longer ask about the inner connections of our dream pictures, but
rather about the physical, physiological, and psychological processes that
underlie them. Just as little can the philosopher, who considers the world to
be his mental picture, interest himself in the inner connections of the
details of this world. If he admits to an existing “I” at all, he
will not then ask how one of his mental pictures relates to another, but
rather what occurs, within the soul existing independently of him, while his
consciousness contains a certain train of mental pictures. If I dream that I
am drinking wine which causes a burning in my throat, and then wake up with
an irritation in my throat that makes me cough (see Weygandt,
How Dreams Arise, 1893*),
then the moment I wake up, the dream event ceases to have
an interest for me. My attention is now directed only toward the
physiological and psychological processes through which the irritation in my
throat brings itself symbolically to expression in the dream picture. In the
same way, as soon as he is convinced that the world given him has the
character of mental pictures, the philosopher must skip over this world into
the real soul existing behind it. The situation is far worse, to be sure, if
illusionism totally denies the “I”-in-itself behind the mental
pictures, or at least considers it to be unknowable. One can very easily be
led to such a view by the observation that, in contrast to dreaming, there is
indeed the waking state, in which we have the chance to see through our
dreams and to relate them to real circumstances, but that we have no state
which stands in a similar relationship to our life of waking consciousness.
Whoever adopts this view lacks the insight that there is something which in
fact does relate to mere perceiving in the same way that experience in the
waking state relates to dreaming. This something is thinking.
*Entstehung der Träume.
The naive
person cannot be accused of the lack of insight referred to here. He gives
himself over to life and takes things as real in the form they present
themselves to him in experience. But the first step which is undertaken to go
beyond this standpoint can only consist in the question of how thinking
relates to the perception. Regardless of whether or not the perception
continues to exist in the form presented to me before and after my mental
picturing: if I want to say anything at all about the perception, this can
happen only with the help of thinking. If I say that the world is my mental
picture, I have expressed thereby the result of a thought process, and if my
thinking is not applicable to the world, then this result is an error.
Between the perception and any kind of statement about it, thinking presses
in.
We have
already given the reason why, during the contemplation of things, thinking is
for the most part overlooked (see
page 28).
The reason lies in the fact that
we direct our attention only upon the object we are thinking about, but not
at the same time upon our thinking. The naive consciousness therefore treats
thinking as something which has nothing to do with the things, but which
stands completely apart from them and carries on its contemplation of the
world. The picture of the phenomena of the world that the thinker sketches is
regarded, not as something which belongs to the things, but rather as
something existing only in man's head; the world is also complete
without this picture. The world is set and complete in all its substances and
forces; and of this complete world man sketches a picture. One must only ask
those who think in this way, what right they have to declare the world
complete without thinking. Does not the world bring forth thinking in the
head of man with the same necessity as it brings forth the blossom from the
plant? Plant a seed in the earth. It puts forth root and stem. It opens into
leaves and blossoms. Set the plant before you. It unites in your soul with a
definite concept. Why does this concept belong any less to the whole plant
than leaf and blossom do? You say that the leaves and blossoms are there
without a perceiving subject; that the concept appears only when the human
being stands before the plant. Quite so. But blossoms and leaves also arise
on the plant only when earth is there, into which the seed can be placed,
when light and air are there, within which leaves and blossoms can unfold.
The concept of the plant arises in exactly the same way when a thinking
consciousness approaches the plant.
It is entirely
arbitrary to regard the sum of what we experience of a thing through mere
perception as a totality, as a complete whole, and to regard what results
from thinking contemplation as something merely added on which has
nothing to do with the thing itself. If I am given a rosebud today, the
picture presented to my perception is complete only for the moment. If I set
the bud in water, then I will be given a completely different picture of my
object tomorrow. If I do not turn my eye from the rosebud, then I will see
its present stage pass over continuously into tomorrow's through
innumerable intermediary stages. The picture presented to me at any specific
moment is only a chance part taken from an object that is continuously
becoming. If I do not set the bud in water, then it will not bring to
development a whole series of stages which lie in it as potential. Likewise I
can be prevented from further observation of the blossom tomorrow, and thus
have an incomplete picture.
It is a
completely unfounded opinion, bound to chance happenings, which would declare
with reference to the picture presented at one particular time, that
that is the thing.
Just as little
is it admissible to declare that the sum total of a thing's perceptual
characteristics is the thing. It could very well be possible that a spirit
was able to receive the concept at the same time as, and unseparated from, the
perception. It would not occur at all to such a spirit to regard the concept
as something not belonging to the thing. He would have to ascribe to the
concept an existence inseparably bound up with the thing.
Let me make
myself even clearer through an example. If I throw a stone horizontally
through the air, I see it in different places, one after another. I connect
these places into a line in mathematics I learn to know different line forms,
among them the parabola I know the parabola to be a line that arises when a
point moves in a certain lawful way. When I investigate the conditions under
which the thrown stone moves, I find that the line of its motion is identical
with that which I know as a parabola. That the stone happens to move in a
parabola is the result of the given conditions and follows necessarily from
them. The form of the parabola belongs to the whole phenomenon just as much
as everything else about it which comes into consideration. The spirit
described above, who did not have to take the roundabout way of thinking,
would not only be given a sum of sight sensations at different places, but
also, unseparated from the phenomenon, the parabolic form of the trajectory,
which we only then add to the phenomenon through thinking.
It is not due
to the objects that they are given to us at first without their corresponding
concepts, but rather it is due to our spiritual organization. Our total being
functions in such a way that, for each thing within reality, the elements
which come into consideration about the thing flow to us from two sides: from
the sides of perceiving and of thinking.
How I am
organized to grasp things has nothing to do with their nature. The split
between perceiving and thinking is first present the moment I, the observing
person, approach the things. Which elements do or do not belong to the thing
cannot depend at all upon the way I arrive at knowledge about these
elements.
Man is a
limited being. First of all he is a being among other beings. His existence
belongs to space and time. Because of this fact there [is] only a limited
part of the total universe can be given him. But this limited part connects
on all sides, both in time and in space, with other things. Were our
existence joined to things in such a way that every happening in the world
would be at the same time our happening, then there would not be a
distinction between us and things. But then there would also be no individual
things for us. Then all happening would merge together into a continuum.
The cosmos would be a unity and a self-enclosed whole. The flow of happening
would be interrupted nowhere. Because of
our limitations something appears to us as individual which is not in truth
an individual thing. Nowhere, for example, is the individual quality of red
present all by itself. It is surrounded on all sides by other qualities, to
which it belongs, and without which it could not exist. For us, however, it
is necessary to lift certain parts out of the world and to look at them in
their own right. Our eye can grasp individual colors only one by one out of a
complex of many colors; our intellect can grasp only individual concepts out
of a system of interrelated concepts. This separating out is a subjective
act, and is due to the fact that we are not identical with the world process,
but are one being among other beings.
Everything
depends now on determining the place of that being, which we ourselves are,
in relationship to the other beings. This determination must be distinguished
from the mere becoming conscious of ourselves. This last is based on the act
of perceiving, just as is our becoming conscious of every other thing. The
perceptions of myself shows me a sum of characteristics, which I bring
together into my personality as a whole, in the same way that I bring
together the characteristics of yellow, metallically-shiny, hard, etc., into
the unity “gold.” The perception of myself does not lead me out
of the realm of what belongs to me. This perception of myself is to be
distinguished from what I determine, thinking, about myself. Just as,
through my thinking, I incorporate an individual perception of the outer
world into the whole world complex, so do I incorporate the perceptions I
have about myself into the world process through thinking. My perceiving of
myself encloses me within definite limits; my thinking has nothing to do with
these limits. In this sense I am a twofold being. I am enclosed within the
region which I perceive as that of my personality, but I am the bearer of an
activity which, from a higher sphere, determines my limited existence. Our
thinking is not individual the way our experiencing and feeling are. It is
universal. It receives an individual stamp in each single person only through
the fact that it is related to his individual feeling and experiencing.
Through these particular colorings of the universal thinking, individual
people differ from one another. A triangle has only one single concept.
For the content of this concept it is a matter of indifference whether the
human bearer of consciousness who grasps it is A or B. But the content of
this concept will be grasped in an individual way by each of the two bearers
of consciousness.
This thought
is opposed by a preconception people have which is difficult to overcome.
This bias does not attain to the insight that the concept of the triangle
which my head grasps is the same as the one comprehended by the head of my
neighbor. The naive person considers himself to be the creator of his
concepts. He believes, therefore, that each person has his own concepts. It
is a fundamental requirement of philosophical thinking that it overcome this
preconception. The oneness of the concept “triangle” does not
become a plurality through the fact that it is thought by many. For the
thinking of the many is itself a oneness.
In thinking we
have given to us the element which fuses our particular individuality into
one whole with the cosmos. Inasmuch as we experience and feel (and also
perceive), we are separate beings; inasmuch as we think, we are the all-one
being; which permeate all. This is the deeper basis of our twofold nature: we
see an utterly absolute power come into existence within us, a power which is
universal; but we learn to know it, not where it streams forth from the
center of the world, but rather at a point on the periphery. If the first
were the case, then the moment we came to consciousness, we would know the
solution to the whole riddle of the world. Since we stand at a point on the
periphery, however, and find our own existence enclosed within certain
limits, we must learn to know the region which lies outside of our own being
with the help of thinking, which projects into us out of the general world
existence.
Through the
fact that the thinking in us reaches out beyond our separate existence and
relates itself to universal existence, there arises in us the drive for
knowledge. Beings without thinking do not have this drive. When other things
confront them, no questions are aroused thereby. These other things remain
external to such beings. With thinking beings, when confronted by an outer
thing, the concept wells up. The concept is what we receive from the thing,
not from without, but rather from within. Knowledge is meant to yield
the balance, the union of the two elements, the inner and the outer.
A perception*
is therefore nothing finished, closed off, but rather it is the one side of
total reality. The other side is the concept. The act of knowledge is the
synthesis of perception and concept. The perception and the concept of a
thing, however, first constitute the entire thing.
*
By “perception” Rudolf Steiner still means the object
of perception, not the act of perceiving. See
pages 32–34.
— Translator's note.
The preceding
considerations yield proof that it is nonsensical to seek something which the
individual entities of the world have in common beyond the ideal content with
which thinking presents us. All attempts must founder which strive for any
world unity other than this self-coherent ideal content which we acquire for
ourselves through thinking contemplation of our perceptions. Not a human
personal god, nor force or matter, nor will without idea (Schopenhauer) can
be considered by us to be a valid universal world unity. These beings all
belong to only one limited region of our observations. Humanly limited
personality we perceive only with respect to ourselves, force and matter only
with respect to outer things. With respect to the will, it can only be
considered to be what our limited personality manifests as activity.
Schopenhauer wants to avoid making “abstract” thinking into the
bearer of world unity, and seeks, instead of it, something which presents
itself to him directly as real. This philosopher believes that we will never
really get at the world as long as we regard it as an outer world. “In
actuality, the sought-for meaning of the world which confront me solely as my
mental picture, or the transition from this world, as mere mental picture of
the subject knowing it, over to what it might still be besides mental
picture, could nevermore be found, if the researcher himself were nothing
more than purely knowing subject (winged angel's head without body).
But now he himself has roots in that world, finds himself in it, namely, as an
individual, which means that this activity of knowing, which is the
determining bearer of the whole world as a mental picture, is after all given
entirely through the medium of a body, whose sensations, as shown, are the
starting point for the intellect in viewing the world. For the purely knowing
subject as such, this body is a mental picture like any other, an object
among objects: the motions, the actions of it are known to him in that
respect no differently than the changes in all other observable objects, and
would be just as foreign and incomprehensible to him, if the significance of
his own motions and actions were not disclosed to him somehow in a completely
different way. ... To the knowing subject, which arises as an individual
through its identification with the body, this body is given in two
completely different ways: one is as a mental picture when the body is viewed
intellectually, as object among objects, and subject to the laws of these
objects but then at the same time in a completely different way also as that
something, known directly by everyone, which the word
“will” characterizes. Every true act of his will is
immediately and unfailingly also a movement of his body; he cannot really
will an act, without at the same time perceiving that it manifests as a
movement of his body. The act of will and the action of the body are not two
objectively known different states, connected by the bond of causality; they
do not stand in the relationship of cause and effect; but they are rather one
and the same, only given in two completely different ways: one completely
direct and one for the intellect in contemplation.” By this train of
thought Schopenhauer believe himself justified in finding the
objectivity of will within the human body. He is of the opinion that,
in the actions of the body, he feels directly a reality, the
thing-in-itself in concrete. Against these arguments it must be objected that
the actions of our body come to consciousness only through self-perceptions
and as such have nothing over other perceptions. If we want to know
their nature, we can do this only through thinking contemplation, that
means through incorporating them into the ideal system of our concepts and
ideas.
Most deeply
rooted in the naive consciousness of mankind is the opinion that thinking is
abstract, without any concrete content. It can give at most an
“ideal” reflection of the world whole, but definitely not this
world whole itself. Whoever judges in this way has never made clear to
himself what a perception is without its concept. But let us look at this
world of perception: it appears as mere juxtaposition in space and succession
in time, an aggregate of particulars without interconnection. Not one of the
things which come and go there upon the stage of perception has anything,
which can be perceived, to do directly with any other. There, the world is a
multiplicity of objects of equal value. None plays a role greater than any
other in the functioning of the world. If we want to become clear about
whether this or that fact has greater significance than the other, then we
must consult our thinking. If our thinking is not working, we see an
animal's rudimentary organ, which has no significance for its life, as
of equal value with its mot important bodily member. The individual facts
come forth in their significance, both for themselves and with respect to the
other parts of the world, only when thinking weaves its threads from being to
being. This activity of thinking is one full of content. For only
through an altogether definite and concrete content can I know why the snail
stands at a lower stage of development than does the lion. Mere sight, mere
perception gives me no content which could instruct me as to the level of
organization.
Thinking, out
of man's world of concepts and ideas, brings this content to meet the
perception. In contrast to the content of perception, which is given us from
outside, the content of thought appears within us. Let us call the form in
which it first arises, “intuition.” Intuition is for
thinking what observation is for the perception. Intuition and
observation are the sources of our knowledge. We confront an observed thing
in the world as foreign to us, as long as we do not have within us the
corresponding intuition which fills in the piece of reality missing in the
perception. For someone who does not have the ability to find the intuitions
which correspond to the things, full reality remains closed. Just as the
colorblind person sees only differences in brightness without the qualities
of color, so the person without intuition can only observe unconnected
perceptual fragments.
To
explain a thing, to make it comprehensible, means nothing other
than to set it into the context out of which it has been torn through the
configuration of our organization described above. There is no such thing as
an object separated off from the whole world. All separating off has only
subjective validity for our organization. For us the whole world breaks down
into above and below, before and after, cause and effect, thing and mental
picture, matter and force, object and subject, etc. The single things which
confront us in observation join themselves together, part by part, through
the interconnected, unified world of our intuitions; and through thinking we
join together again into oneness everything which we have separated through
our perceiving.
The puzzling
aspect of an object lies in its separate existence. This puzzling aspect,
however, is evoked by us, and can, within the conceptual world, also be
dispelled again.
Other than
through thinking and perceiving, nothing is given us directly. The question
now arises as to how things stand, in the light of these considerations, with
respect to the significance of the perception. We have, to be sure,
recognized that the proof which critical idealism brings of the subjective
nature of our perceptions collapses; but along with this insight into the
incorrectness of its proof, it is still not yet determined that the view
itself is based on error. Critical idealism, in marshalling its proof, does
not take its start form the absolute nature of thinking, but rather bases
itself upon the fact that naive realism, consistently pursued, cancels itself
out. How does the matter present itself if the absoluteness of thinking is
recognized?
Let us assume
that a certain perception, red for example, arises in my consciousness. The
perception shows itself, as I continue looking, to be connected with other
perceptions, for example with that of a certain shape, with certain
temperature and tactile perceptions. This combination I designate as an
object of the sense world. I can now ask myself what else is to be found,
besides this object, in that section of space within which the above
perceptions appear to me. I will find mechanical, chemical, and other
processes within this part of space. Now I
go further and investigate the processes that I find on the way from the
object to my sense organ. I can find processes of motion within an elastic
medium which, by their very nature, do not have the least thing in common with
the original perceptions. I get the same result when I investigate the
further transmitting from sense organ to brain. In each of these areas I have
new perceptions, but what weaves as a connecting medium through all these
spatially and temporally separated perceptions is thinking. The vibrations of
the air which transmit the sound are given to me as perceptions in exactly
the same way as the sound itself. Only thinking joins all these perceptions
to each other and reveals them in their mutual interrelationships. We cannot
say that anything other than what is directly perceived exists except what is
known through the ideal interconnections of our perceptions (ideal in that
they are to be discovered through thinking). The relationship, going beyond
what is merely perceived, of the object of perception to the subject of
perception, is therefore a purely ideal one, that means, expressible only
through concepts. Only in the event that I could perceive how the object of
perception affects the subject of perception, or, the other way round, that I
could observe the building up of the perceptible entity by the subject, would
it be possible to speak as does modern physiology and the critical idealism
founded upon it. This view confuses an ideal relationship (of the object to
the subject) with a process which could only be spoken of if it were
perceivable. The sentence: “No color without a color-sensitive
eye,” therefore cannot mean that the eye brings forth the color, but
rather only that an ideal connection, knowable through thinking, exists
between the perception “color” and the perception
“eye.” Empirical science will have to determine how the
characteristics of the eye and those of colors relate to each other; through
which configurations, the organ of sight transmits the perception of colors,
etc. I can follow how one perception follows upon another, how it stands
spatially in relationship with other perceptions; and I can bring this then
into a conceptual formulation; but I cannot perceive how a perception comes
forth out of the unperceivable. All endeavors to seek relationships between
perceptions other than thought relationships must necessarily founder.
What, then, is
a perception? This question, when asked in a general way, is absurd. A
perception always arises as an entirely specific one, as a definite content.
This content is directly given, and is all that is in the given. One can only
ask with respect to this given, what it is besides perception, i.e., what it
is for thinking. Thus, the question about the “what” of a
perception can only refer to the conceptual intuition that corresponds to it.
From this point of view the question the question as to the subjectivity of
the perception in the sense of critical idealism cannot be raised at all.
Only that may be labeled as subjective which is perceived as belonging to the
subject. To form the bond between subjective and objective is not the task of
any real process in the naive sense, i.e. of any perceptible happening;
rather, it is the task of thinking alone. For us, therefore, something is
objective which presents itself to perception as situated outside of the
perceiving subject. My perceiving subject remains perceptible to me when the
table now standing in front of me will have disappeared from the circle of my
observations. The observation of the table has called forth in me a change,
which likewise remains. I retain the ability to create a picture of the table
again later. This ability to bring forth a picture remains connected with me.
Psychology calls this picture a memory picture. It is, however, that which
alone can rightly be called the mental picture of the table. This
picture corresponds, namely, to the perceptible change of my own state
through the presence of the table within my field of vision. And indeed, this
change does not refer to any “I-in-itself” standing behind the
perceiving subject, but rather the change of the perceptible subject himself.
The mental picture is therefore a subjective perception in contrast to the
objective perception when the object is present on the horizon of perception.
The confusing of the subjective with the objective perception leads to the
mistaken view of idealism: that the world is my mental picture.
It will now be
our next task to determine more closely the concept of the mental picture.
What we have brought forward so far about the mental picture is not its
concept, but only indicates the path along which it is to be found within the
field of perception. The exact concept of the mental picture will then also
make it possible for us to gain a satisfactory explanation of the
relationship of mental picture and object. This will then also lead us over
the boundary where the relationship between human subject and the object
belonging to the world will be led down from the purely conceptual field of
knowing activity into our concrete individual life. Once we know what
to make of the world, it will be an easy matter also to orient ourselves
accordingly. We can be active with our full strength only when we know the
object, belonging to the world, to which we are devoting our activity.
Addendum to
the Revised Edition of 1918. The view characterized here can be regarded
as one to which man is at first as though naturally impelled when he begins
to reflect upon his relationship to the world. He seems himself entangled in
a thought configuration which unravels for him as he is forming it. This
thought configuration is of such a kind that everything necessary for it is
not yet fulfilled with its merely theoretical refutation. One must live it
through in order, out of insight into the aberration into which it leads,
to find the way out. It must appear within an investigation of the
relationship of man to the world, not because one wants to refute others whom
one believes to hold an incorrect view about this relationships, but rather
because one must know what perplexity every first reflection upon such a
relationship can bring. One must gain the insight as to how one can
refute oneself with respect to these first reflections. This is the
point of view from which the above line of argumentation is put forward.
Whoever wants
to develop for himself a view about the relationship of man to the world
becomes conscious that he brings about at least a part of this relationship
through the fact that he makes mental pictures for himself about the things
and occurrences of the world. Through this, his gaze is drawn away from what
is outside in the world and directed upon his inner world, upon his
life of mental pictures. He begins to say to himself, “I can have a
relationship to no thing and to no occurrence, if a mental picture does not
arise in me.” From noting this fact, it is only a step to the opinion
that I do, after all, experience only my mental picture: I know of a world
outside of me only insofar as it is a mental picture within me.
With this opinion the naive standpoint of reality is abandoned which the
human being takes before any reflecting about his relationship to the world.
From this standpoint, he believes he has to do with real things.
Self-reflection forces him away from this standpoint. It does not let him
look at all upon a reality such as naive consciousness believes to have
before itself. It lets him look merely upon his mental pictures; these
interpose themselves between one's own being and a supposed real world
such as the naive standpoint believes itself justified in affirming. The
human being can no longer look through the intervening world of mental
images, upon a reality such as that. He must assume that he is blind to this
reality. In this way there arises the thought of a
“thing-in-itself” which is inaccessible to knowledge. — So
long as one goes no further than to contemplate the relationship to the world
into which man seem to enter through his life of mental pictures, one will
not be able to escape this thought configuration. One cannot remain at the
naive standpoint of reality if one does not want to close oneself off
artificially to the desire for knowledge. The fact that this desire for
knowledge about the relationship of man and world is present, shows that this
naive standpoint must be abandoned. If the naive standpoint offered something
which one can acknowledge as the truth, then one could not feel this desire.
— But one does not arrive at something different which one could regard
as the truth, if one merely abandons the naive standpoint, but —
without noticing it — retains the kind of thinking which this standpoint
imposes. One falls into just such an error when one says to oneself, “I
experience only my mental pictures, and although I believe that I am dealing
with realities, I am only conscious of my mental pictures of realities; I
must therefore assume that only outside of the circle of my consciousness do
the true realities, the ‘things-in-themselves,’ life, of which I
know absolutely nothing directly, which somehow approach me and influence me
in such a way that my world of mental pictures arises in me.” Whoever
thinks in this way only adds in thought, to the world lying before him,
another one; but, with respect to this world, he would actually have to start
all over again from the beginning with his thought work. For the unknown
“thing-in-itself” is thereby thought to be no different at all in
its relationship to man's own being than the known thing of the naive
standpoint of reality. — One escapes the perplexity into which one
comes through pondering this standpoint critically only when one notices that
there is something — within what a person can experience and
perceive inside himself and outside in the world — that absolutely
cannot suffer the fate of having the mental picture interpose itself between
the occurrence and the contemplating human being. And this is
thinking. With respect to thinking, the human being can remain
upon the naive standpoint towards reality. If he does not do so, it is only
because he has noticed that for something else he must abandon this
standpoint, but does not become aware that the insight thus gained is not
applicable to thinking. If he becomes aware of this, then he opens the way
for himself to the other insight, that within thinking and
through thinking, he must come to know that element to which man seems
to blind himself through the fact that he must interpose his life of mental
pictures between the world and himself. — The author of this book has
been reproached by someone highly esteemed by him for remaining, in his
consideration of thinking, at a naive realism of thinking like the sort which
exists when one regards the real world and the mentally pictured world as
one. But the author of these considerations believes that he has in fact shown
that the validity of this “naive realism” for thinking
does necessarily follow out of an unprejudiced observation of thinking; and
that the naive realism which is otherwise not valid is overcome through the
knowledge of the true being of thinking.
|