THE REALITY OF FREEDOM
IX
THE FACTORS OF LIFE
ET us
recapitulate the results gained in the previous chapters. The world
appears to man as a multiplicity, as an aggregate of separate
entities. He himself is one of these entities, a thing among things.
Of this structure of the world we say simply that it is given, and
inasmuch as we do not construct it by conscious activity, but simply
find it, we say that it consists of percepts. Within this world of
percepts we perceive ourselves. This percept of Self would remain
merely one among many other percepts, did it not give rise to
something which proves capable of connecting all percepts one with
another and, therefore, the aggregate of all other percepts with the
percept of Self. This something which emerges is no longer a mere
percept; neither is it, like percepts, simply given. It is produced
by our activity. It appears, in the first instance, bound up with
what each of us perceives as his Self. In its inner significance,
however, it transcends the Self. It adds to the separate percepts
ideal determinations, which, however, are related to one another, and
which are grounded in a whole. What self-perception yields is ideally
determined by this something in the same way as all other percepts,
and placed as subject, or “I,” over against the objects.
This something is thought, and the ideal determinations are the
concepts and ideas. Thought, therefore, first manifests itself in
connection with the percept of self. But it is not merely subjective,
for the Self characterizes itself as subject only with the help of
thought. This relation of the Self to itself by means of thought is
one of the fundamental determinations of our personal lives. Through
it we lead a purely ideal existence. By means of it we are aware of
ourselves as thinking beings. This determination of our lives would
remain a purely conceptual (logical) one, if it were not supplemented
by other determinations of our Selves. Our lives would then exhaust
themselves in establishing ideal connections between percepts
themselves, and between them and ourselves. If we call this
establishment of an ideal relation an “act of cognition,”
and the resulting condition of ourselves “knowledge,”
then, assuming the above supposition to be true, we should have to
consider ourselves as beings who merely apprehend or know.
The
supposition is, however, untrue. We relate percepts to ourselves not
merely ideally, through concepts, but also, as we have already seen,
through feeling. In short, the content of our lives is not merely
conceptual. The Naïve Realist holds that the personality
actually lives more genuinely in the life of feeling than in the
purely ideal activity of knowledge. From his point of view he is
quite right in interpreting the matter in this way. Feeling plays on
the subjective side exactly the part which percepts play on the
objective side. From the principle of Naïve Realism, that
everything is real which can be perceived, it follows that feeling is
the guarantee of the reality of one's own personality. Monism,
however, must bestow on feeling the same supplementation which it
considers necessary for percepts, if these are to stand to us for
reality in its full nature. For Monism, feeling is an incomplete
reality which, in the form in which it first appears to us, lacks as
yet its second factor, the concept or idea. This is why, in actual
life, feelings, like percepts, appear prior to knowledge. At first,
we have merely a feeling of existence; and it is only in the course
of our gradual development, that we attain to the point at which the
concept of Self emerges from within the blind mass of feelings which
fills our existence. However, what for us does not appear until
later, is from the first indissolubly bound up with our feelings.
This is how the naïve man comes to believe that in feeling he
grasps existence immediately, in knowledge only mediately. The
development of the affective life, therefore, appears to him more
important than anything else. Not until he has grasped the unity of
the world through feeling will he believe that he has comprehended
it. He attempts to make feeling rather than thought the instrument of
knowledge. Now a feeling is entirely individual, something equivalent
to a percept. Hence a philosophy of feeling makes a cosmic principle
out of something which has significance only within my own
personality. Anyone who holds this view attempts to infuse his own
self into the whole world. What the Monist strives to grasp by means
of concepts, the philosopher of feeling tries to attain through
feeling, and he looks on his own felt union with objects as more
immediate than knowledge.
The
tendency just described, the philosophy of feeling, is Mysticism. The
error in this view is that it seeks to possess by immediate
experience what must be known, that it seeks to develop feeling,
which is individual, into a universal principle.
A feeling
is a purely individual activity. It is the relation of the external
world to the subject, in so far as this relation finds expression in
a purely subjective experience.
There is
yet another expression of human personality. The Self, through
thought, takes part in the universal world-life. Through thought it
establishes purely ideal (conceptual) relations between percepts and
itself, and between itself and percepts. In feeling it has immediate
experience of the relation of objects to itself as subject. In will
the opposite is the case. In volition, we are concerned once more
with a percept, viz., that of the individual relation of the self to
what is objective. Whatever in the act of will is not an ideal
factor, is just as much mere object of perception as is any object in
the external world.
Nevertheless, the Naïve Realist believes here again that he has
before him something far more real than can ever be attained by
thought. He sees in the will an element in which he is immediately
aware of an activity, a causation, in contrast with thought which
afterwards grasps this activity in conceptual form. On this view, the
realization by the Self of its will is a process which is experienced
immediately. The adherent of this philosophy believes that in the
will he has really got hold of one end of reality. Whereas he can
follow other occurrences only from the outside by means of
perception, he is confident that in his will he experiences a real
process quite immediately. The mode of existence presented to him by
the will within himself becomes for him the fundamental reality of
the universe. His own will appears to him as a special case of the
general world-process; hence the latter is conceived as a universal
will. The will becomes the principle of reality just as, in
Mysticism, feeling becomes the principle of knowledge. This kind of
theory is called Voluntarism(Thelism). It makes something which can
be experienced only individually the dominant factor of the
world.
Voluntarismcan as little be called scientific as can Mysticism. For
both assert that the conceptual interpretation of the world is
inadequate. Both demand, in addition to a principle of being which is
ideal, also a principle which is real. But as perception is our only
means of apprehending these so-called real principles, the assertion
of Mysticism and Voluntarismcoincides with the view that we have two
sources of knowledge, viz., thought and perception, the latter
finding individual expression as will and feeling. Since the
immediate experiences which flow from the one source cannot be
directly absorbed into the thoughts which flow from the other,
perception (immediate experience) and thought remain side by side,
without any higher form of experience to mediate between them. Beside
the conceptual principle to which we attain by means of knowledge,
there is also a real principle which must be immediately experienced.
In other words, Mysticism and Voluntarismare both forms of Naïve
Realism because they subscribe to the doctrine that the immediately
perceived (experienced) is real. Compared with Naïve Realism in
its primitive form, they are guilty of the yet further inconsistency
of accepting one definite form of perception (feeling, respectively
will) as the exclusive means of knowing reality. Yet they can do this
only so long as they cling to the general principle that everything
that is perceived is real. They ought, therefore, to attach an equal
value to external perception for purposes of knowledge.
Voluntarism turns into Metaphysical Realism, when it asserts the
existence of will also in those spheres of reality in which will can
no longer, as in the individual subject, be immediately experienced.
It assumes hypothetically that a principle holds outside subjective
experience, for the existence of which, nevertheless, subjective
experience is the sole criterion. As a form of Metaphysical Realism,
Voluntarism is open to the criticism developed in the preceding
chapter, a criticism which makes it necessary to overcome the
contradictory element in every form of Metaphysical Realism, and to
recognize that the will is a universal world-process only in so far
as it is ideally related to the rest of the world.
|