XIII
MORAL IMAGINATION (Darwinism and Morality)
FREE
spirit acts according to his impulses, i.e., intuitions, which
his thought has selected out of the whole world of his ideas. For an
unfree spirit, the reason why he singles out a particular intuition
from his world of ideas, in order to make it the basis of an action,
lies in the perceptual world which is given to him, i.e., in
his past experiences. He recalls, before making a decision, what some
one else has done, or recommended as proper, in an analogous case, or
what God has commanded to be done in such a case, etc., and he acts
on these recollections. A free spirit dispenses with these
preliminaries. His decision is absolutely original. He cares as
little what others have done in such a case as what commands they
have laid down. He has purely ideal (logical) reasons which determine
him to select a particular concept out of the sum of his concepts,
and to realize it in action. But his action will belong to
perceptible reality. Consequently, what he achieves will coincide
with a definite content of perception. His concept will have to be
realized in a concrete particular event. As a concept it will not
contain this event as particular. It will refer to the event only in
its generic character, just as, in general, a concept is related to a
percept, e.g., the concept lion to a particular lion. The link
between concept and percept is the idea (cp. pp. 68 ff.). To the
unfree spirit this intermediate link is given from the outset.
Motives exist in his consciousness from the first in the form of
ideas. Whenever he intends to do anything he acts as he has seen
others act, or he obeys the instructions he receives in each separate
case. Hence authority is most effective in the form of examples,
i.e., in the form of traditional patterns of particular
actions handed down for the guidance of the unfree spirit. A
Christian models his conduct less on the teaching than on the pattern
of the Saviour. Rules have less value for telling men positively what
to do than for telling them what to leave undone. Laws take on the
form of universal concepts only when they forbid actions, not when
they prescribe actions. Laws concerning what we ought to do must be
given to the unfree spirit in wholly concrete form. Clean the street
in front of your door! Pay your taxes to such and such an amount to
the tax-collector! etc. Conceptual form belongs to laws which inhibit
actions. Thou shalt not steal! Thou shalt not commit adultery! But
these laws, too, influence the unfree spirit only by means of a
concrete idea, e.g., the idea of the punishments attached by human
authority, or of the pangs of conscience, or of eternal damnation,
etc.
Even when
the motive to an action exists in universal conceptual form (e.g.,
Thou shalt do good to thy fellow-men! Thou shalt live so that thou
promotest best thy welfare!), there still remains to be found, in the
particular case, the concrete idea of the action (the relation of the
concept to a content of perception). For a free spirit who is not
guided by any model nor by fear of punishment, etc., this translation
of the concept into an idea is always necessary.
Concrete
ideas are formed by us on the basis of our concepts by means of the
imagination. Hence what the free spirit needs in order to realize his
concepts, in order to assert himself in the world, is moral
imagination. This is the source of the free spirit's action. Only
those men, therefore, who are endowed with moral imagination are,
properly speaking, morally productive. Those who merely preach
morality, i.e., those who merely excogitate moral rules
without being able to condense them into concrete ideas, are morally
unproductive. They are like those critics who can explain very
competently how a work of art ought to be made, but who are
themselves incapable of the smallest artistic productions.
Moral
imagination, in order to realize its ideas, must enter into a
determinate sphere of percepts. Human action does not create
percepts, but transforms already existing percepts and gives them a
new character. In order to be able to transform a definite object of
perception, or a sum of such objects, in accordance with a moral
idea, it is necessary to understand the object's law (its mode of
action which one intends to transform, or to which one wants to give
a new direction). Further, it is necessary to discover the procedure
by which it is possible to change the given law into the new one.
This part of effective moral activity depends on knowledge of the
particular world of phenomena with which one has got to deal. We
shall, therefore, find it in some branch of scientific knowledge.
Moral action, then, presupposes, in addition to the faculty of moral
concepts
[Only a superficial critic will find in the
use of the word “faculty,” in this and other passages, a
relapse into the old-fashioned doctrine of faculties of the soul. The
reference to what was said on page 62 defines exactly the meaning of
the word.]
and of moral imagination, the ability to alter the
world of percepts without violating the natural laws by which they
are connected. This ability is moral technique. It may be learnt in
the same sense in which science in general may be learnt. For, in
general, men are better able to find concepts for the world as it is,
than productively to originate out of their imaginations future, and
as yet non-existing, actions. Hence, it is very well possible for men
without moral imagination to receive moral ideas from others, and to
embody these skilfully in the actual world. Vice versa, it may happen
that men with moral imagination lack technical skill, and are
dependent on the service of other men for the realization of their
ideas.
In so far
as we require for moral action knowledge of the objects upon which we
are about to act, our action depends upon such knowledge. What we
need to know here are the laws of nature. These belong to the Natural
Sciences, not to Ethics.
Moral
imagination and the faculty of moral concepts can become objects of
theory only after they have first been employed by the individual.
But, thus regarded, they no longer regulate life, but have already
regulated it. They must now be treated as efficient causes, like all
other causes (they are purposes only for the subject). The study of
them is, as it were, the Natural Science of moral ideas.
Ethics as
a Normative Science, over and above this science, is impossible.
Some
would maintain the normative character of moral laws at least in the
sense that Ethics is to be taken as a kind of dietetic which, from
the conditions of the organism's life, deduces general rules, on the
basis of which it hopes to give detailed directions to the body
(Paulsen,
System der Ethik).
This comparison is mistaken, because our moral life cannot be compared
with the life of the organism. The behaviour of the organism occurs
without any volition on our part. Its laws are fixed data in our
world; hence we can discover them and apply them when discovered.
Moral laws, on the other hand, do not exist until we create them. We
cannot apply them until we have created them. The error is due to the
fact that moral laws are not at every moment new creations, but are
handed down by tradition. Those which we take over from our ancestors
appear to be given like the natural laws of the organism. But it does
not follow that a later generation has the right to apply them in the
same way as dietetic rules. For they apply to individuals, and not,
like natural laws, to specimens of a genus. Considered as an
organism, I am such a generic specimen, and I shall live in
accordance with nature if I apply the laws of my genus to my
particular case. As a moral agent I am an individual and have my own
private laws.
[When Paulsen, p. 15 of the book
mentioned above, says: “Different natural endowments and
different conditions of life demand both a different bodily and also
a different mental and moral diet,” he is very close to the
correct view, but yet he misses the decisive point. In so far as I am
an individual, I need no diet. Dietetic means the art of bringing a
particular specimen into harmony with the universal laws of the
genus. But as an individual I am not a specimen of a
genus.]
The view
here upheld appears to contradict that fundamental doctrine of modern
Natural Science which is known as the Theory of Evolution. But it
only appears to do so. By evolution we mean the real development of
the later out of the earlier in accordance with natural law. In the
organic world, evolution means that the later (more perfect) organic
forms are real descendants of the earlier imperfect forms, and have
grown out of them in accordance with natural laws. The upholders of
the theory of organic evolution believe that there was once a time on
our earth, when we could have observed with our own eyes the gradual
evolution of reptiles out of Proto-Amniotes, supposing that we could
have been present as men, and had been endowed with a sufficiently
long span of life. Similarly, Evolutionists suppose that man could
have watched the development of the solar system out of the
primordial nebula of the Kant-Laplace hypothesis, if he could have
occupied a suitable spot in the world-ether during that infinitely
long period. But no Evolutionist will dream of maintaining that he
could from his concept of the primordial Amnion deduce that of the
reptile with all its qualities, even if he had never seen a reptile.
Just as little would it be possible to derive the solar system from
the concept of the Kant-Laplace nebula, if this concept of an
original nebula had been formed only from the percept of the nebula.
In other words, if the Evolutionist is to think consistently, he is
bound to maintain that out of earlier phases of evolution later ones
really develop; that once the concept of the imperfect and that of
the perfect have been given, we can understand the connection. But in
no case will he admit that the concept formed from the earlier phases
is, in itself, sufficient for deducing from it the later phases. From
this it follows for Ethics that, whilst we can understand the
connection of later moral concepts with earlier ones, it is not
possible to deduce a single new moral idea from earlier ones. The
individual, as a moral being, produces his own content. This content,
thus produced, is for Ethics a datum, as much as reptiles are a datum
for Natural Science. Reptiles have evolved out of the Proto-Amniotes,
but the scientist cannot manufacture the concept of reptiles out of
the concept of the Proto-Amniotes. Later moral ideas evolve out of
the earlier ones, but Ethics cannot manufacture out of the moral
principles of an earlier age those of a later one. The confusion is
due to the fact that, as scientists, we start with the facts before
us, and then make a theory about them, whereas in moral action we
first produce the facts ourselves, and then theorize about them. In
the evolution of the moral world-order we accomplish what, at a lower
level, Nature accomplishes: we alter some part of the perceptual
world. Hence the ethical norm cannot straightway be made an object of
knowledge, like a law of nature, for it must first be created. Only
when that has been done can the norm become an object of
knowledge.
But is it
not possible to make the old a measure for the new? Is not every man
compelled to measure the deliverances of his moral imagination by the
standard of traditional moral principles? If he would be truly
productive in morality, such measuring is as much an absurdity as it
would be an absurdity if one were to measure a new species in nature
by an old one and say that reptiles, because they do not agree with
the Proto-Amniotes, are an illegitimate (degenerate) species.
Ethical
Individualism, then, so far from being in opposition to the theory of
evolution, is a direct consequence of it. Haeckel's genealogical tree
from protozoa up to man as an organic being, ought to be capable of
being worked out without a breach of natural law, and without a gap
in its uniform evolution, up to the individual as a being with a
determinate moral nature. But, whilst it is quite true that the moral
ideas of the individual have perceptibly grown out of those of his
ancestors, it is also true that the individual is morally barren,
unless he has moral ideas of his own.
The same
Ethical Individualism which I have developed on the basis of the
preceding principles, might be equally well developed on the basis of
the theory of evolution. The final result would be the same; only the
path by which it was reached would be different.
That
absolutely new moral ideas should be developed by the moral
imagination is for the theory of evolution no more inexplicable than
the development of one animal species out of another, provided only
that this theory, as a Monistic world-view, rejects, in morality as
in science, every transcendent (metaphysical) influence. In doing so,
it follows the same principle by which it is guided in seeking the
causes of new organic forms in forms already existing, but not in the
interference of an extra-mundane God, who produces every new species
in accordance with a new creative idea through supernatural
interference. Just as Monism has no use for supernatural creative
ideas in explaining living organisms, so it is equally impossible for
it to derive the moral world-order from causes which do not lie
within the world. It cannot admit any continuous supernatural
influence upon moral life (divine government of the world from the
outside), nor an influence through a particular act of revelation at
a particular moment in history (giving of the ten commandments), or
through God's appearance on the earth (divinity of Christ). Moral
processes are, for Monism, natural products like everything else that
exists, and their causes must be looked for in nature, i.e.,
in man, because man is the bearer of morality.
Ethical
Individualism, then, is the crown of the edifice that Darwin and
Haeckel have erected for Natural Science. It is the theory of
evolution applied to the moral life.
Anyone
who restricts the concept of the natural from the outset to an
artificially limited and narrowed sphere, is easily tempted not to
allow any room within it for free individual action. The consistent
Evolutionist does not easily fall a prey to such a narrow-minded
view. He cannot let the process of evolution terminate with the ape,
and acknowledge for man a supernatural origin. Again, he cannot stop
short at the organic reactions of man and regard only these as
natural. He has to treat also the life of moral self-determination as
the continuation of organic life.
The
Evolutionist, then, in accordance with his fundamental principles,
can maintain only that moral action evolves out of the less perfect
forms of natural processes. He must leave the characterization of
action, i.e., its determination as free action, to the
immediate observation of each agent. All that he maintains is only
that men have developed out of monkeys. What the nature of men
actually is must be determined by observation of men themselves. The
results of this observation cannot possibly contradict the history of
evolution. Only the assertion that the results are such as to exclude
their being due to a natural world-order would contradict recent
developments in the Natural Sciences.
[We are entitled
to speak of thoughts (ethical ideas) as objects of observation. For,
although the products of thinking do not enter the field of
observation, so long as the thinking goes on, they may well become
objects of observation subsequently. In this way we have gained our
characterization of action.]
Ethical
Individualism, then, has nothing to fear from a Natural Science which
understands itself. Observation yields freedom as the characteristic
quality of the perfect form of human action. The establishment of a
conceptual connection between this fact of observation and other
kinds of processes results in the theory of the natural origin of
free actions.
What,
then, from the standpoint of nature are we to say of the distinction,
already mentioned above (p. 13), between the two statements,
“To be free means to be able to do what you will,” and
“To be able, as you please, to strive or not to strive is the
real meaning of the dogma of free will”? Hamerling bases his
theory of free will precisely on this distinction, by declaring the
first statement to be correct but the second to be an absurd
tautology. He says, “I can do what I will, but to say I can
will what I will is an empty tautology.” Whether I am able to
do, i.e., to make real, what I will, i.e., what I have
set before myself as my idea of action, that depends on external
circumstances and on my technical skill (cp. p. 118). To be free
means to be able to determine by moral imagination out of oneself,
those ideas (motives) which lie at the basis of action. Freedom is
impossible if anything other than I myself (whether a mechanical
process or God) determines my moral ideas. In other words, I am free
only when I myself produce these ideas, but not when I am merely able
to realize the ideas which another being has implanted in me. A free
being is one who can will what he regards as right. Whoever does
anything other than what he wills must be impelled to it by motives
which do not lie in himself. Such a man is unfree in his action.
Accordingly, to be able to will, as you please, what you consider
right or wrong means to be free or unfree as you please. This is, of
course, just as absurd as to identify freedom with the faculty of
doing what one is compelled to will. But this is just what Hamerling
maintains when he says, “It is perfectly true that the will is
always determined by motives, but it is absurd to say that on this
ground it is unfree; for a greater freedom can neither be desired nor
conceived than the freedom to realize oneself in proportion to one's
own power and strength of will.” On the contrary, it is well
possible to desire a greater freedom and that a true freedom, viz.,
the freedom to determine for oneself the motives of one's
volitions.
Under
certain conditions a man may be induced to abandon the execution of
his will; but to allow others to prescribe to him what he shall do
― in other words, to will what another and not what he himself
regards as right ―to this a man will submit only when he does
not feel free.
External
powers may prevent me from doing what I will, but that is only to
condemn me to do nothing. Not until they enslave my spirit, drive my
motives out of my head, and put their own motives in the place of
mine, do they really aim at making me unfree. That is the reason why
the church attacks not only the mere doing, but especially the impure
thoughts, i.e., motives of my action. And for the church all
those motives are impure which she has not herself authorized. A
church does not produce genuine slaves until her priests turn
themselves into advisers of consciences, i.e., until the
faithful depend upon the church, i.e., upon the confessional,
for the motives of their actions.
|