XV
THE INDIVIDUAL AND THE GENUS
HE view
that man is a wholly self-contained, free individuality stands in
apparent conflict with the facts, that he appears as a member of a
natural whole (race, tribe, nation, family, male or female sex), and
that he acts within a whole (state, church, etc.). He exhibits the
general characteristics of the community to which he belongs, and
gives to his actions a content which is defined by the place which he
occupies within a social whole.
This
being so, is any individuality left at all? Can we regard man as a
whole in himself, in view of the fact that he grows out of a whole
and fits as a member into a whole?
The
character and function of a member of a whole are defined by the
whole. A tribe is a whole, and all members of the tribe exhibit the
peculiar characteristics which are conditioned by the nature of the
tribe. The character and activity of the individual member are
determined by the character of the tribe. Hence the physiognomy and
the conduct of the individual have something generic about them. When
we ask why this or that is so or so, we are referred from the
individual to the genus. The genus explains why something in the
individual appears in the forms observed by us.
But man
emancipates himself from these generic characteristics. He develops
qualities and activities the reason for which we can seek only in
himself. The generic factors serve him only as a means to develop his
own individual nature. He uses the peculiarities with which nature
has endowed him as material, and gives them a form which expresses
his own individuality. We seek in vain for the reason of such an
expression of a man's individuality in the laws of the genus. We are
dealing here with an individual who can be explained only through
himself. If a man has reached the point of emancipation from what is
generic in him, and we still attempt to explain all his qualities by
reference to the character of the genus, then we lack the organ for
apprehending what is individual.
It is
impossible to understand a human being completely if one makes the
concept of the genus the basis of one's judgment. The tendency to
judge according to the genus is most persistent where differences of
sex are involved. Man sees in woman, woman in man, almost always too
much of the generic characteristics of the other's sex, and too
little of what is individual in the other. In practical life this
does less harm to men than to women. The social position of women is,
in most instances, so low because it is not determined by the
individual characteristics of each woman herself, but by the general
ideas which are current concerning the natural function and needs of
woman. A man's activity in life is determined by his individual
capacity and inclination, whereas a woman's activity is supposed to
be determined solely by the fact that she is just a woman. Woman is
to be the slave of the generic, of the general idea of womanhood. So
long as men debate whether woman, from her “natural
disposition,” is fitted for this, that, or the other
profession, the so-called Woman's Question will never advance beyond
the most elementary stage. What it lies in woman's nature to strive
for had better be left to woman herself to decide. If it is true that
women are fitted only for that profession which is theirs at present,
then they will hardly have it in them to attain any other. But they
must be allowed to decide for themselves what is conformable to their
nature. To all who fear an upheaval of our social structure, should
women be treated as individuals and not as specimens of their sex, we
need only reply that a social structure in which the status of
one-half of humanity is unworthy of a human being stands itself in
great need of improvement.
Anyone
who judges human beings according to their generic character stops
short at the very point beyond which they begin to be individuals
whose activity rests on free self-determination. Whatever lies short
of this point may naturally become matter for scientific study. Thus
the characteristics of race, tribe, nation, and sex are the
subject-matter of special sciences. Only men who are simply specimens
of the genus could possibly fit the generic picture which the methods
of these sciences produce. But all these sciences are unable to get
as far as the unique character of the single individual. Where the
sphere of freedom (thinking and acting) begins, there the possibility
of determining the individual according to the laws of his genus
ceases. The conceptual content which man, by an act of thought, has
to connect with percepts, in order to possess himself fully of
reality (cp. pp. 57 ff.), cannot be fixed by anyone once and for all,
and handed down to humanity ready-made. The individual must gain his
concepts through his own intuition. It is impossible to deduce from
any concept of the genus how the individual ought to think; that
depends singly and solely on the individual himself. So, again, it is
just as impossible to determine, on the basis of the universal
characteristics of human nature, what concrete ends the individual
will set before himself. Anyone who wants to understand the single
individual must penetrate to the innermost core of his being, and not
stop short at those qualities which he shares with others. In this
sense every single human being is a problem. And every science which
deals only with abstract thoughts and generic concepts is but a
preparation for the kind of knowledge which we gain when a human
individual communicates to us his way of viewing the world, and for
that other kind of knowledge which each of us gains from the content
of his own will. Wherever we feel that here we are dealing with a man
who has emancipated his thinking from all that is generic, and his
will from the grooves typical of his kind, there we must cease to
call in any concepts of our own making if we would understand his
nature. Knowledge consists in the combination by thought of a concept
and a percept. With all other objects the observer has to gain his
concepts through his intuition. But if the problem is to understand a
free individuality, we need only to take over into our own minds
those concepts by which the individual determines himself in their
pure form (without admixture). Those who always mix their own ideas
into their judgment on another person can never attain to the
understanding of an individuality. Just as the free individual
emancipates himself from the characteristics of the genus, so our
knowledge of the individual must emancipate itself from the methods
by which we understand what is generic.
A man
counts as a free spirit in a human community only to the degree in
which he has emancipated himself, in the way we have indicated, from
all that is generic. No man is all genus, none is all individuality;
but every man gradually emancipates a greater or lesser sphere of his
being, both from the generic characteristics of animal life and from
the laws of human authorities which rule him despotically.
In
respect of that part of his nature for which man is not able to win
this freedom for himself, he forms a member within the organism of
nature and of spirit. He lives, in this respect, by the imitation of
others, or in obedience to their command. But ethical value belongs
only to that part of his conduct which springs from his intuitions.
This is his contribution to the already existing total of moral
ideas. In such ethical intuitions all moral activity of men has its
root. To put this differently: the moral life of humanity is the
sum-total of the products of the moral imagination of free human
individuals. This is Monism's confession of faith. Monism looks upon
the history of the moral life, not as the education of the human race
by a transcendent God, but as the gradual living out in practice of
all concepts and ideas which spring from the moral imagination.
|