APPENDIX I
ADDITION TO THE REVISED
EDITION OF 1918
VARIOUS
criticisms on the part of philosophers with which this book met
immediately upon its publication, induce me to add to this Revised
Edition the following brief statement.
I can well understand
that there are readers who are interested in the rest of the book,
but who will look upon what follows as a tissue of abstract concepts
which is unnecessary and makes no appeal to them. They may, if they
choose, leave this brief statement unread. But in philosophic world
contemplation problems present themselves which have their origin
rather in certain prejudices on the thinker's part than in the
natural progression of human thinking. With the main body of this
book it seems to me to be a task for everyone to concern himself, who
is striving for clearness about the essential nature of man and his
relation to the world. What follows is rather a problem the
discussion of which certain philosophers demand as necessary to a
treatment of the topics of this book, because these philosophers, by
their whole way of thinking, have created certain difficulties which
do not otherwise occur. If I were to pass by these problems entirely,
certain people would be quick to accuse me of dilettantism, etc. The
impression would thus be created that the author of the views set
down in this book has not thought out his position with regard to
these problems because he has not discussed them in his book.
The problem to which I
refer is this: there are thinkers who find a particular difficulty in
understanding how one's own soul can be affected by another's. They
say: the world of my consciousness is a closed circle within me;
so is the world of another's consciousness within him. I cannot look
into the world of another's consciousness. How, then, do I know that
he and I are in a common world? The theory according to which we can
from the conscious world infer an unconscious world which never can
enter consciousness, attempts to solve this difficulty as
follows. The world, it says, which I have in my consciousness is a
representative image in me of a real world to which I have no
conscious access. In this transcendent world exist the unknown agents
which cause the world in my consciousness. In it, too, exists my own
real being, of which likewise I have only a representative image in
my consciousness. In it, lastly, exists the essential being of the
fellow-man who confronts me. Whatever passes in the consciousness of
my fellow-man corresponds to a reality in his transcendent essence
which is independent of his consciousness. This reality acts on my
own unconscious being in the realm which cannot become conscious; and
in this way in my consciousness a representative element is created
which represents there what is present in another consciousness
wholly beyond the reach of my conscious experience. Clearly the point
of this theory is to imagine in addition to the world accessible to
my consciousness an hypothetical world which is to my immediate
experience inaccessible. This is done to avoid the supposed
alternative of having to say that the external world, which I regard
as existing before me, is nothing but the world of my consciousness,
with the absurd — solipsistic — corollary that other
persons likewise exist only within my consciousness.
Several epistemological
tendencies in recent speculation have joined in creating this
problem. But it is possible to attain to clearness about it by
surveying the situation from the point of view of spiritual
perception which underlies the exposition of this book. What is it
that, in the first instance, I have before me when I confront another
person? To begin with, there is the sensuous appearance of the
other's body, as given in perception. To this we might add the
auditory perception of what he is saying, and so forth. All this I do
not merely gaze at but it sets in motion my thinking activity.
Through the thinking with which I now confront the other person, the
percept of him becomes, as it were, psychically transparent. As my
thinking apprehends the percept, I am compelled to judge that
what I perceive is really quite other than it appears to the outer
senses. The sensuous appearance, it being what it immediately is,
reveals something else which it is mediately. In presenting itself to
me, it at the same time extinguishes itself as a mere sensuous
appearance. But in thus extinguishing itself it reveals something
which compels me as a thinking being to extinguish my own thinking as
long as I am under its influence and to put its thinking in the place
of mine. Its thinking is then apprehended by my thinking as an
experience like my own. Thus I have really perceived another's
thinking. For the immediate percept, in extinguishing itself as
sensuous appearance, is apprehended by my thinking. It is a
process which passes wholly in my consciousness and consists in this,
that the other's thinking takes the place of my thinking. Through the
self-extinction of the sensuous appearance the separation between the
spheres of the two consciousnesses is actually abolished. In my own
consciousness this fusion manifests itself in that, so long as I
experience the contents of the other's consciousness, I am aware of
my own consciousness as little as I am aware of it in dreamless
sleep. Just as my waking consciousness is eliminated from the latter,
so are the contents of my own consciousness eliminated from my
experience of the contents of another's consciousness. Two things
tend to deceive us about the true facts. The first is that, in
perceiving another person, the extinction of the contents of one's
own consciousness is replaced not, as in sleep, by
unconsciousness, but by the contents of the other's consciousness.
The other is that my consciousness of my own self oscillates so
rapidly between extinction and recurrence, that these alternations
usually escape observation. The whole problem is to be solved, not
through artificial construction of concepts, involving an inference
from what is in consciousness to what can never become conscious, but
through genuine experience of what results from the co-operation of
thinking and perceiving. This applies to many other problems which
appear in philosophical literature. Thinkers should seek the road to
unprejudiced spiritual observation, instead of putting an artificial
structure of concepts in front of reality.
In a monograph by
Eduard von Hartmann on
The Ultimate Problems of Epistemology and Metaphysics
(in the Zeitschrift für Philosophie und
Philosophische Kritik, Vol. 108, p. 55), my Philosophy of
Spiritual Activity has been classed with the philosophical
tendency which seeks to build upon an “epistemological Monism.”
Eduard von Hartmann rejects this position as untenable. This is
explained as follows. According to the point of view maintained in
his monograph, there are only three possible positions in the theory
of knowledge. The first consists in remaining at the naive point of
view, which regards perceived phenomena as real things existing
outside the human consciousness. This, urges von Hartmann, implies a
lack of critical reflection. I fail to realize that with all my
contents of consciousness I remain imprisoned in my own
consciousness. I fail to perceive that I am dealing, not with the
“table-in-itself,” but only with an object in my own
consciousness. If I stop at this point of view, or if for whatever
reasons I return to it, I am a Naive Realist. But this whole position
is untenable, for it ignores that consciousness has no other objects
than its own contents. The second position consists in appreciating
this situation and confessing it to oneself. As a result, I become a
Transcendental Idealist. As such, says von Hartmann, I am obliged to
deny that a “thing-in-itself” can ever appear in any way
within the human consciousness. But, if developed with unflinching
consistency, this view ends in Absolute Illusionism. For the world
which confronts me is now transformed into a mere sum of objects of
consciousness, and, moreover, of objects of my private
consciousness. The objects of other human minds, too, I am then
compelled to conceive — absurdly enough — as present
solely in my own consciousness. Hence, the only tenable position,
according to von Hartmann, is the third, viz., Transcendental
Realism. On this view, there are “things-in-themselves,”
but consciousness can have no dealings with them by way of immediate
experience. Existing beyond the sphere of human consciousness, they
cause, in a way of which we remain unconscious, the appearance of
objects in consciousness. These “things-in-themselves”
can be only inferred from the contents of consciousness, which are
immediately experienced but for that very reason, purely
representational. Eduard von Hartmann maintains in the monograph
cited above, that “epistemological Monism” — for
such he takes my point of view to be — is bound to declare
itself identical with one or other of the above three positions; and
that its failure to do so is due only to its inconsistency in not
drawing the actual consequences of its presuppositions. The monograph
goes on to say: “If we want to find out which epistemological
position a so-called Epistemological Monist occupies, all we have to
do is to put to him certain questions and compel him to answer them.
For, out of his own initiative, no Monist will condescend to state
his views on these points, and likewise he will seek to dodge in
every way giving an answer to our direct questions, because every
answer he may give will betray that Epistemological Monism does not
differ from one or other of the three positions. Our questions are
the following: (1) Are things continuous or intermittent in their
existence? If the answer is ‘continuous,’ we have before
us some or other form of Naive Realism. If the answer is
‘intermittent,’ we have Transcendental Idealism. But if
the answer is: ‘They are, on the one hand, continuous, viz., as
contents of the Absolute Mind, or as unconscious representations, or
as possibilities of perception, but, on the other hand, intermittent,
viz., as contents of finite consciousness,’ we recognize
Transcendental Realism. (2) When three persons are sitting at a
table, how many distinct tables are there? The Naive Realist answers
‘one’; the Transcendental Idealist answers ‘three’;
but the Transcendental Idealist answers ‘four.’ This last
answer does, indeed, presuppose that it is legitimate to group
together in the single question, ‘How many tables?’
things so unlike each other as the one table which is the
‘thing-in-itself’ and the three tables which are the
perceptual objects in the three consciousnesses. If this seems too
great a license to anyone, he will have to answer ‘one and
three,’ instead of ‘four.’ (3) When two persons are
alone together in a room, how many distinct persons are there? If you
answer ‘two’ — you are a Naive Realist. If you
answer ‘four,’ viz., in each of the two minds one ‘I’
and one ‘Other,’ you are a Transcendental Idealist. If
you answer ‘six,’ viz., two persons as
‘things-in-themselves’ and four persons as
representational objects in the two consciousnesses, you are a
Transcendental Realist. In order to show that Epistemological Monism
is not one of these three positions, we should have to give another
answer than the above to each of these three questions. But I cannot
imagine what answer this could be.” The answers of the
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
would have to be: (1) Whoever
apprehends only perceptual contents of a thing and takes them for the
reality of the thing, is a Naive Realist. He does not realize that,
strictly, he ought to regard these perceptual contents as existing
only so long as he is looking at the things, so that he ought to
conceive the things before him as intermittent. As soon, however, as
it becomes clear to him that reality is to be met with only in the
percepts which are permeated by thinking, he attains to the insight
that the percepts which appear as intermittent events, reveal
themselves as continuously in existence as soon as they are
permeated by the results of thinking. Hence continuity of existence
must be predicated of the contents of perception which living
thinking has grasped. Only that part which is merely perceived would
have to be regarded as intermittent, if — which is not the case
— it were real. (2) When three persons are sitting at a table,
how many distinct tables are there? There is only one table. But so
long as the three persons stop short at their perceptual images, they
ought to say: “These percepts are not a reality at all.”
As soon as they pass on to the table as apprehended by thinking,
there is revealed to them the one reality of the table. They are then
united with their three contents of consciousness in this one
reality. (3) When two persons are alone together in a room, how many
distinct persons are there? Most assuredly there are not six —
not even in the sense of the Transcendental Realist's theory —
but only two. Only, at first, each person has nothing but the unreal
perceptual image of himself and of the other person. There are four
such images, the presence of which is the stimulus for the
apprehension, by the two persons, of reality by their thinking. In
this activity of thinking each of the two persons transcends the
sphere of his own consciousness. A living awareness of the
consciousness of the other person as well as of his own arises in
each. In these moments of living awareness the persons are as little
imprisoned within their consciousness as they are in sleep. But
at other moments consciousness of this identification with the other
returns, so that the consciousness of each person, in the experience
of thinking, apprehends both himself and the other person. I know
that a Transcendental Realist describes this view as a relapse into
Naive Realism. But, then, I have already pointed out in this book
that Naive Realism retains its justification for our experienced
thinking. The Transcendental Realist completely ignores the true
situation in the process of cognition. He cuts himself off from the
facts by a tissue of thoughts and entangles himself in it. Moreover,
the Monism which appears in the
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
ought not to be labeled “epistemological,” but, if an
epithet is wanted, then a “Monism of Thought.” All this
has been misunderstood by Eduard von Hartmann. Ignoring all that is
specific in the argumentation of the
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity,
he has charged me with having attempted to combine
Hegel's Universalistic Panlogism with Hume's Individualistic Phenomenalism
(Zeitschrift für Philosophie, Vol. 108, p.
71, note). But, in truth, the
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
has nothing whatever to do with the two positions which it is accused
of trying to combine. (This, too, is the reason why I could not feel
inclined to deal, e.g., with the Epistemological Monism of
Johannes Rehmke. The point of view of the
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
is simply quite different from what Eduard von .Hartmann
and others call “Epistemological Monism.”)
|