THE SCIENCE OF SPIRITUAL ACTIVITY
(FREEDOM)
CHAPTER I
CONSCIOUS HUMAN ACTION
IS
man in his thinking and acting a spiritually free being, or is he
compelled by the iron necessity of natural laws? There are few
questions on which so much ingenuity has been expended. The idea of
the freedom of the human will has found enthusiastic supporters and
stubborn opponents in plenty. There are those who, in their moral
fervour, label anyone a man of limited intelligence who can deny so
patent a fact as freedom. Opposed to them are others who regard it as
the acme of unscientific thinking for anyone to believe that the
uniformity of natural law is broken in the sphere of human action and
thought. One and the same thing is thus proclaimed, now as the most
precious possession of humanity, now as its most fatal illusion.
Infinite subtlety has been employed to explain how human freedom can
be consistent with the laws working in nature, of which man, after
all, is a part. Others have been at no less pains to explain how such
a delusion as this could have arisen. That we are dealing here with
one of the most important questions for life, religion, conduct,
science, must be felt by anyone whose most prominent trait is not the
reverse of thoroughness. It is one of the sad signs of the
superficiality of present-day thought, that a book which attempts to
develop a new faith out of the results of recent scientific research
(David Friedrich Strauss, Der alte und neue Glaube), has
nothing more to say on this question than these words: “With
the question of the freedom of the human will we are not concerned.
The alleged freedom of indifferent choice has been recognized as an
empty illusion by every philosophy worthy of the name. The moral
valuation of human action and character remains untouched by this
problem.” It is not because I consider that the book in which
it occurs has any special importance that I quote this passage, but
because it seems to me to express the view to which the thinking of
the majority of our contemporaries is able to rise in this matter.
Everyone who has grown beyond the kindergarten-stage of science
appears to know nowadays that freedom cannot consist in choosing, at
one's pleasure, one or other of two possible courses of action. There
is always, so we are told, a perfectly definite reason why, out of
several possible actions, we carry out just one and no other.
This seems obvious.
Nevertheless, down to the present day, the main attacks of the
opponents of freedom are directed only against freedom of choice.
Even Herbert Spencer, in fact, whose doctrines are gaining ground
daily, says, “That everyone is at liberty to desire or not to
desire, which is the real proposition involved in the dogma of free
will, is negatived as much by the analysis of consciousness, as
by the contents of the preceding chapter.” (The Principles
of Psychology, Part IV, Chap. ix., par. 219.) Others, too, start
from the same point of view in combating the concept of free will.
The germs of all the relevant arguments are to be found as early as
Spinoza. All that he brought forward in clear and simple language
against the idea of freedom has since been repeated times without
number, but as a rule enveloped in the most sophisticated doctrines,
so that it is difficult to recognize the straightforward train
of thought which is alone in question. Spinoza writes in a letter of
October or November, 1674, “I call a thing free which exists
and acts from the pure necessity of its nature, and I call that
unfree, of which the being and action are precisely and fixedly
determined by something else. Thus, e.g., God, though
necessary, is free because he exists only through the necessity of
his own nature. Similarly, God cognizes himself and all else freely,
because it follows solely from the necessity of his nature that he
cognizes all. You see, therefore, that for me freedom consists not in
free decision, but in free necessity.
“But let us come
down to created things which are all determined by external causes to
exist and to act in a fixed and definite manner. To perceive this
more clearly, let us imagine a perfectly simple case. A stone, for
example, receives from an external cause acting upon it a certain
quantity of motion, by reason of which it necessarily continues to
move, after the impact of the external cause has ceased. The
continued motion of the stone is due to compulsion, not to the
necessity of its own nature, because it requires to be defined by the
thrust of an external cause. What is true here for the stone is true
also for every other particular thing, however complicated and
many-sided it may be, namely, that everything is necessarily
determined by external causes to exist and to act in a fixed and
definite manner.
“Now, pray,
assume that this stone during its motion thinks and knows that it is
striving to the best of its power to continue in motion. This stone
which is conscious only of its striving and is by no means
indifferent, will believe that it is absolutely free, and that it
continues in motion for no other reason than its own will to
continue. Now this is that human freedom which everybody claims to
possess and which consists in nothing but this, that men are
conscious of their desires, but ignorant of the causes by which they
are determined. Thus the child believes that he desires milk of his
own free will, the angry boy regards his desire for vengeance as
free, and the coward his desire for flight. Again, the drunken man
believes that he says of his own free will what, sober again, he
would fain have left unsaid, and as this prejudice is innate in all
men, it is difficult to free oneself from it. For, although
experience teaches us often enough that man least of all can temper
his desires, and that, moved by conflicting passions, he sees the
better and pursues the worse, yet he considers himself free because
there are some things which he desires less strongly, and some
desires which he can easily inhibit through the recollection of
something else which it is often possible to recall.”
It is easy to detect
the fundamental error of this view, because it is so clearly and
definitely expressed. The same necessity by which a stone makes a
definite movement as the result of an impact, is said to compel a man
to carry out an action when impelled thereto by any reason. It is
only because man is conscious of his action, that he thinks himself
to be its originator. In doing so, he overlooks the fact that he is
driven by a cause which he must obey unconditionally. The error in
this train of thought is easily brought to light. Spinoza, and all
who think like him, overlook the fact that man not only is conscious
of his action, but also may become conscious of the causes which
guide him. Anyone can see that a child is not free when he desires
milk, nor the drunken man when he says things which he later regrets.
Neither knows anything of the causes, working deep within their
organisms, which exercise irresistible control over them. But is it
justifiable to lump together actions of this kind with those in which
a man is conscious not only of his actions but also of the reasons
which cause him to. act? Are the actions of men really all of one
kind? Should the act of a soldier on the field of battle, of the
scientific researcher in his laboratory, of the statesman in the most
complicated diplomatic negotiations, be placed scientifically on the
same level with that of the child when he desires milk? It is, no
doubt, true that it is best to seek the solution of a problem where
the conditions are simplest. But lack of ability to see distinctions
has before now caused endless confusion. There is, after all, a
profound difference between knowing why I am acting and not knowing
it. At first sight this seems a self-evident truth. And yet the
opponents of freedom never ask themselves whether a motive of action
which I recognize and see through, is to be regarded as compulsory
for me in the same sense as the organic process which causes the
child to cry for milk.
Eduard von Hartmann, in
his
Phaenomenologie des sittlichen Bewusstseins (p. 451),
asserts that the human will depends on two chief factors, the motives
and the character. If one regards men as all alike, or at any rate
the differences between them as negligible, then their will appears
as determined from without, viz., by the circumstances which come to
meet them. But if one bears in mind that men adopt a “representation”
[German: Vorstellung, cf.
Translator's Preface, p. ix.] as the motive of their action,
only if their character is such that this representation arouses a
desire in them, then men appear as determined from within and not
from without. Now, because a representation given to us from without,
must first in accordance with our characters be adopted as a motive,
men believe that they are free, i.e., independent of external
impulses. The truth, however, according to Eduard von Hartmann, is
that “even though we (must) first adopt a representation as a
motive, we do so not arbitrarily, but according to the
characterological disposition, that is, we are anything but free.”
Here again the difference between motives which I allow to influence me
only after I have permeated them with my consciousness, and those which
I follow without any clear knowledge of them, is absolutely ignored.
This leads us straight to the standpoint from which the subject will
be treated here. Have we any right to consider the question of the
freedom of the will by itself at all? And if not, with what other
question must it necessarily be connected?
If there is a difference between a conscious motive and an
unconscious impulse of action, then those actions which result from
the former should be judged otherwise than one springing from blind
impulse. Hence our first question will concern this difference, and
on the result of this inquiry will depend what attitude we ought to
take up towards the question of freedom proper.
What does it mean to have knowledge of the motives of one's
action? Too little attention has been paid to this question, because,
unfortunately, we have torn asunder into two parts that which is an
inseparable whole: Man. The agent has been divorced from the knower,
whilst he who matters more than everything else, viz., the man who
acts because he knows, has been utterly overlooked.
It is said that man is free when he is controlled only by his reason,
and not by his animal passions. Or, again, that to be free means to
be able to determine one's life and action by purposes
and deliberate decisions.
Nothing is gained by assertions of this sort. For the
question is just whether reason, purposes, and decisions exercise
the same kind of compulsion over a man as his animal passions. If
without my doing, a rational decision emerges in me with the same
necessity with which hunger and thirst happen to me, then I must
needs obey it, and my freedom is an illusion.
Another form of expression runs: to be free means, not that we can
will what we will, but that we can do what we will. This thought has
been expressed with great clearness by the poet-philosopher Robert
Hamerling in his Atomistik des Willens. “Man can, it is
true, do what he wills, but he cannot will what he wills, because his
will is determined by motives! He cannot will what he wills? Let us
consider these phrases more closely. Have they any intelligible
meaning? Does freedom of will, then, mean being able to will without
ground, without motive? What does willing mean if not to have grounds
for doing, or striving to do, this rather than that? To will anything
without ground or motive would mean to will something without willing
it. The concept of motive is indissolubly bound up with that of will.
Without the determining motive the will is an empty faculty; it is
the motive which makes it active and real. It is, therefore, quite
true that the human will is not ‘free,’ inasmuch as its direction
is always determined by the strongest motive. But, on the other hand, it
must be admitted that it is absurd to speak, in contrast with this
‘unfreedom,’ of a conceivable ‘freedom’ of the will,
which would consist in being able to will what one does not will.”
(Atomistik des Willens, p. 213 ff.)
Here, again, only motives in general are mentioned, without taking
into account the difference between unconscious and conscious
motives. If a motive affects me, and I am compelled to act on it
because it proves to be the “strongest” of its kind, then
the thought of freedom ceases to have any meaning. How should it
matter to me whether I can do a thing or not, if I am forced by the
motive to do it? The primary question is, not whether I can do a
thing or not when impelled by a motive, but whether there are any
motives except such as impel me with absolute necessity. If I am
compelled to will something, then I may well be absolutely
indifferent as to whether I can also do it. And if, through my
character, or through circumstances prevailing in my environment, a
motive is forced on me which to my thinking is unreasonable, then I
should even have to be glad if I could not do what I will.
The question is, not
whether I can carry out a decision once made, but how the decision is
brought about within me.
What distinguishes man
from all other organic beings is his rational thinking. Activity is
common to him with other organisms. Nothing is gained by seeking
analogies in the animal world to clear up the concept of freedom as
applied to the actions of human beings. Modern science loves these
analogies. When scientists have succeeded in finding among animals
something similar to human behaviour, they believe they have touched
on the most important question of the science of man. To what
misunderstandings this view leads is seen, for example, in the book
Die Illusion der Willensfreiheit, by P. Rée, 1885, where, on
page 5, the following remark on freedom appears: “It is easy to
explain why the movement of a stone seems to us necessary, while the
volition of a donkey does not. The causes which set the stone in
motion are external and visible, while the causes which determine the
donkey's volition are internal and invisible. Between us and the
place of their activity there is the skull cap of the ass ... The
causal nexus is not visible and, therefore, thought to be
non-existent. The volition, it is explained, is, indeed, the cause of
the donkey's turning round, but is itself unconditioned; it is an
absolute beginning.” Here again human actions in which there is
a consciousness of the motives are simply ignored, for Rée
declares, “that between us and the sphere of their activity
there is the skull cap of the ass.” As these words show, it has
not so much as dawned on Rée that there are actions, not
indeed of the ass, but of human beings, in which the motive that has
become conscious, lies between us and the action. Rée
demonstrates his blindness once again, a few pages further on, when
he says, “We do not perceive the causes by which our will is
determined, hence we think it is not causally determined at all.”
But enough of examples
which prove that many argue against freedom without knowing in the
least what freedom is.
That an action cannot
be free, of which the agent does not know why he performs it, goes
without saying. But what of the freedom of an action about the
motives of which we know? This leads us to the question of the origin
and meaning of thinking. For without the recognition of the thinking
activity of the soul, it is impossible to understand what is meant by
knowledge of something or what is meant by action. When we know what
thinking in general means, it will be easier to see clearly the role
which thinking plays in human action. As Hegel rightly says, “It
is thinking which turns the soul, common to us and animals, into
spirit.” Hence it is thinking which we may expect to give to
human action its characteristic stamp.
I do not mean to imply
that all our active doing springs only from the sober deliberations
of our reason. I am very far from calling only those actions “human”
in the highest sense, which proceed from abstract judgments. But as
soon as our conduct rises above the sphere of the satisfaction of
purely animal desires, our motives are always permeated by thoughts.
Love, pity, and patriotism are springs of action which cannot be
analysed away into cold concepts of the understanding. It is said
that here the heart, the mood of the soul, hold sway. This is no
doubt true. But the heart and the mood of the soul do not create the
motives. They presuppose them and let them enter. Pity enters my
heart when the representation of a person who arouses pity comes
forward in my consciousness.
The way to the heart is through the
head. Love is no exception. Whenever it is not merely the expression
of bare sexual instinct, it depends on the representation we form of
the loved one. And the more idealistic these representations are,
just so much the more blessed is our love. Here, too, thought is the
father of feeling. It is said that love makes us blind to the
failings of the loved one. But the opposite view can be taken,
namely, that it is precisely for the good points that love opens the
eyes. Many pass by these good points without notice. One, however,
perceives them, and just because he does, love awakens in his soul.
What else has he done except to have achieved a representation of
what hundreds have failed to see? Love is not theirs, because they
lack the representation.
From whatever point we
regard the subject, it becomes more and more clear that the question
of the nature of human action presupposes that of the origin of
thinking. I shall, therefore, turn next to this question.
|