CHAPTER VI
HUMAN INDIVIDUALITY
PHILOSOPHERS
have found the chief difficulty in the explanation of representations
in the fact that we are not the things themselves, and yet our
representations must have a form corresponding to the things. But on
closer inspection it turns out that this difficulty does not really
exist. We certainly are not the external things, but we belong
together with them to one and the same world. The stream of the
universal cosmic process passes through that segment of the world
which, to my perception, is myself as subject. So far as my
perception goes, I am, in the first instance, confined within the
limits bounded by my skin. But all that is contained within the skin
belongs to the cosmos as a whole. Hence, for a relation to subsist
between my organism and an object external to me, it is by no means
necessary that something of the object should slip into me, or make
an impression on my spirit, like a signet ring on wax. The question —
How do I gain knowledge of that tree ten feet away from me —
is utterly misleading. It springs from the view that the boundaries
of my body are absolute barriers, through which information about
things filters into me. The forces which are active within the limit
of my body are the same as those which exist outside. I am,
therefore, really the things, not, however, I in so far as I am
subject of perception, but I in so far as I am a part within the
universal world-process. The percept of the tree belongs to the same
whole as my I. This universal world process produces alike, there the
percept of the tree, and here the percept of my I. Were I a
world-creator instead of a world-knower, object and subject (percept
and I) would originate in one act. For they condition one
another reciprocally. As world-knower I can discover the common
element in both, so far as they are complementary aspects of the
world, only through thinking which by means of concepts relates the
one to the other.
The most difficult to
drive from the field are the so-called physiological proofs of the
subjectivity of our percepts. When I exert pressure on the skin of my
body I perceive it as a pressure sensation. This same pressure can be
sensed as light by the eye, as sound by the ear. I perceive an
electrical shock by the eye as light, by the ear as sound, by the
nerves of the skin as shock, and by the nose as a phosphoric smell.
What follows from these facts? Only this: I perceive an electric
shock, or a pressure, followed by a light, or a sound, or, it may be
a certain smell, etc. If there were no eye present, then no
perception of a light quality would accompany the perception of the
mechanical vibrations in my environment; without the presence of the
ear, no sound, etc. But what right have we to say that in the absence
of sense-organs the whole process would not exist at all? All those
who, from the fact that an electrical process calls forth light in
the eye, conclude that what we sense as light is, when outside our
organism, only a mechanical process of motion, forget that they are
only passing from one percept to another, and not at all to something
altogether outside the range of percepts. Just as we can say that the
eye perceives a mechanical process of motion in its surroundings as
light, so we can affirm that every change in an object, determined by
law, is perceived by us as a process of motion. If I draw twelve
pictures of a horse on the circumference of a rotating disc,
reproducing exactly the positions which the horse's body successively
assumes in movement, I can, by rotating the disc, produce the
illusion of movement. I need only look through an opening in
such a way that, in the proper intervals, I see the successive
positions of the horse. I see, not separate pictures of twelve
horses, but the picture of a single galloping horse.
The above-mentioned
physiological fact cannot, therefore, throw any light on the
relation of percept to representation. Hence, we must seek a
relation in some other way.
The moment a percept
appears in my field of observation, thinking also becomes active
through me. A member of my thought-system, a definite intuition, a
concept, connects itself with the percept. When, next, the percept
disappears from my field of vision, what remains? My intuition, with
the reference to the particular percept which it acquired in the
moment of perception. The degree of vividness with which I can
subsequently recall this reference depends on the manner in which my
spiritual and bodily organism is working. A representation is nothing
but an intuition related to a particular percept; it is a concept
which was once connected with a certain percept, and which retains
the reference to this percept. My concept of a lion is not
constructed out of my percepts of lions; but my representation of a
lion is formed according to a percept. I can convey to someone the
concept of a lion without his ever having seen a lion, but I can
never give him a vivid representation of it without the help of his
own perception.
A representation is,
therefore, an individualized concept. And now we can see how real
objects can be represented to us by representations. The full reality
of a thing is present to us in the moment of observation through the
combination of concept and percept. The concept acquires by means of
a percept an individualized form, a relation to this particular
percept. In this individualized form which carries with it, as an
essential feature, the reference to the percept, it lives on in us
and constitutes the representation of the thing in question. If
we come across a second thing with which the same concept connects
itself, we recognize the second as belonging to the same kind as the
first; if we come across the same thing twice, we find in our
conceptual system, not merely a corresponding concept, but the
individualized concept with its characteristic relation to the same
object, and thus we recognize the object again.
Thus, the
representation stands between percept and concept. It is the
determinate concept which points to the percept.
The sum of those things
about which I can form representations may be called my experience.
The man who has the greater number of individualized concepts will be
the man of richer experience. A man who lacks all power of intuition
is not capable of acquiring experience. The objects simply disappear
again from his field of vision, because he lacks the concepts which
he ought to bring into relation with them. On the other hand, a man
whose faculty of thinking is well developed, but whose perception
functions badly owing to his clumsy sense-organs, will be no better
able to gather experience. He can, it is true, by one means and
another acquire concepts; but his intuitions lack the vivid reference
to definite things. The unthinking traveler and the scholar living in
abstract conceptual systems are alike incapable of acquiring a rich
experience.
Reality presents itself
to us as percept and concept; and the subjective representative of
this reality presents itself to us as representation.
If our personality
expressed itself only in cognition, the totality of all that is
objective would be contained in percept, concept and
representation.
However, we are not
satisfied merely to refer the percept, by means of thinking,
to the concept, but we relate them also to our private subjectivity,
our individual Ego. The expression of this relation to us as
individuals is feeling, which manifests itself as pleasure or
displeasure.
Thinking and feeling
correspond to the two-fold nature of our being to which reference has
already been made. By means of thinking we take part in the universal
cosmic process. By means of feeling we withdraw ourselves into the
narrow precincts of our own being.
Our thinking links us
to the world; our feeling leads us back into ourselves and thus makes
us individuals. Were we merely thinking and perceiving beings, our
whole life would flow along in monotonous indifference. Could we only
know ourselves as Selves, we should be totally indifferent to
ourselves. It is only because with self-knowledge we experience
self-feeling, and with the perception of objects pleasure and
pain, that we live as individuals whose existence is not exhausted by
the conceptual relations in which they stand to the rest of the
world, but who have moreover a special value in themselves.
One might be tempted to
regard the life of feeling as something more richly saturated with
reality than the consideration of the world through thinking. But the
reply to this is that the life of feeling, after all, has this richer
meaning only for my individual self. For the universe as a whole my
life of feeling can be of value only if, as percept of my Self, the
feeling enters into connection with a concept and in this roundabout
way links itself to the cosmos.
Our life is a continual
oscillation between our living with the universal world-process and
our own individual existence. The farther we ascend into the
universal nature of thinking where the individual, at last, interests
us only as an example, an instance, of the concept, the more the
character of the particular Being, of the quite determinate, single
personality, becomes lost in us. The farther we descend into the
depths of our own life and allow our feelings to resound with our
experiences of the outer world, the more we cut ourselves off from
the universal life. True individuality belongs to him who reaches up
with his feelings to the farthest possible extent into the region of
the ideal. There are men in whom even the most general Ideas still
bear that peculiar personal tinge which shows unmistakably their
connection with their author. There are others whose concepts come
before us as devoid of any trace of individual colouring as if they
had not been produced by a being of flesh and blood at all.
The act of representing
gives our conceptual life at once an individual stamp. Each one of us
has his special place from which he looks out on the world. His
concepts link themselves to his percepts. He thinks the general
concepts in his own special way. This special determination results
for each of us from the place where he stands and is dependent on the
range of percepts peculiar to his place in life.
This determination is
distinct from another which depends on our particular organization.
Our organization is, indeed, a special, definite, individual thing.
Each of us combines special feelings, and these in the most varying
degrees of intensity, with his percepts. This is just the individual
element in the personality of each of us. It is what remains over
when we have allowed fully for all the determining factors in our
milieu.
A life of feeling,
wholly devoid of thinking, would gradually lose all connection with
the world. But man is meant to be a whole, and knowledge of objects
will go hand-in-hand for him with the development and education of
the life of feeling. Feeling is the means whereby, in the first
instance, concepts gain concrete life.
|