Part 1
Friedrich Nietzsche, A Fighter Against his Time
i THE CHARACTER
|
|
1.
RIEDRICH NIETZSCHE
characterizes himself as a
lonely ponderer and friend of riddles, as a personality not
made for the age in which he lived. The one who follows such paths
as his, “meets no one; this is a part of going one's own way. No
one approaches to help him; all that happens to him of danger, accidents,
evil and bad weather, he must get along with alone,” he says in
the preface of the second edition of his Morgenröte, Dawn.
But it is stimulating to follow him into his loneliness. In the words
in which he expressed his relationship to Schopenhauer, I would like
to describe my relationship to Nietzsche: “I belong to those readers
of Nietzsche who, after they have read the first page, know with certainty
that they will read all pages, and listen to every word he has said.
My confidence in him was there immediately ... I understood him as
if he had written just for me, in order to express all that I would
say intelligibly but immediately and foolishly.” One can speak
thus and yet be far from acknowledging oneself as a “believer”
in Nietzsche's world conception. But Nietzsche himself could not be
further from wishing to have such “believers.” Did he not
put into Zarathustra's mouth these words:
“You say you believe
in Zarathustra, but of what account is Zarathustra? You are my believer,
but of what account are all believers?
“You have not searched
for yourselves as yet; there you found me. Thus do all believers, but,
for that reason, there is so little in all believing.
“Now I advise you
to forsake me and to find yourselves; and only when all of you have
denied me will I return to you.”
Nietzsche is no Messianic
founder of a religion; therefore he can wish for friends who support
his opinion, but he cannot wish for confessors to his teaching, who
give up their own selves to find his.
In Nietzsche's personality
are found instincts which are contrary to the complete gamut of the
ideas of his contemporaries. With instinctive aversion he rejects most
of the important cultural ideas of those amid whom he developed himself
and, indeed, not as one rejects an assertion in which one has discovered
a logical contradiction, but rather as one turns away from a color which
causes pain to the eye. The aversion starts from the immediate feeling
to begin with, conscious thinking does not come into consideration at
all. What other people feel when such thoughts as guilt, conscience,
sin, life beyond, ideal happiness, fatherland, pass through their heads,
works unpleasantly upon Nietzsche. The instinctive manner of rejection
of these ideas also differentiates Nietzsche from the so-called “free
thinkers” of the present. The latter know all the intellectual
objections to “the old illusionary ideas,” but how rarely
is one found who can say that his instincts no longer depend
upon them! It is precisely the instincts which play bad tricks upon
the free thinkers of the present time. The thinking takes on a character
independent of the inherited ideas, but the instincts cannot adapt themselves
to the changed character of the intellect. These “free thinkers”
put just any belief of modern science in place of an old idea, but they
speak about it in such a way that one realizes that the intellect goes
another way from that of the instincts. The intellect searches in
matter, in power, in the laws of nature, for the
origin of phenomena; but the instincts misguide so that one has the same
feeling toward this being that others have toward their personal God.
Intellects of this type defend themselves against the accusation of the
denial of God, but they do not do this because their world conception leads
them to something which is in harmony with any form of God, but rather
because from their forefathers they have inherited the tendency to feel
an instinctive shudder at the expression, “the denial
of God.” Great natural scientists emphasize that they do not wish
to banish such ideas as God and immortality, but rather that they wish
to transform them, in the sense of modern science. Their instincts simply
have remained behind their intellect.
A large number of these
“free spirits” are of the opinion that the will of man is
unfree. They say that under certain circumstances man must
behave as his character and the conditions working upon him force him
to act. But if we look at the opponents of the theory of “free
will,” we shall find that the instincts of these “free spirits”
turn away from a doer of an “evil” deed with exactly the same
aversion as do the instincts of those who represent the opinion that
according to its desires the “free will” could turn itself
toward good or toward evil.
The contradiction between
intellect and instinct is the mark of our “modern spirits.”
Within the most liberal thinkers of the present age the implanted instincts
of Christian orthodoxy also still live. Exactly opposite instincts are
active in Nietzsche's nature. He does not need first to reflect whether
there are reasons against the acceptance of a personal world leader.
His instinct is too proud to bow before such a one; for this reason
he rejects such a representation. He says in his Zarathustra,
“But that I may reveal to you my heart, to you, my friends: if
there were Gods, how could I stand it not to be a God! Therefore,
there are no Gods.” Nothing in his inner being compels him to accuse
either himself or another as “guilty” of a committed action.
To consider such a “guilty” action as unseemly, he needs no
theory of “free” or “unfree” will.
The patriotic feelings of his
German compatriots are also repugnant to Nietzsche's instincts. He cannot
make his feelings and his thinking dependent upon the circles of the people
amid whom he was born and reared, nor upon the age in which he lives.
“It is so small-townish,” he says in his
Schopenhauer als Erzieher,
Schopenhauer as Educator, “to make oneself duty-bound
to opinions which no longer bind one a few hundred miles away. Orient
and Occident are strokes of chalk which someone draws before our eyes
to make fools of our timidity. I will make the attempt to come to freedom,
says the young soul to itself; and then should it be hindered because
accidentally two nations hate and fight each other, or because an ocean
lies between two parts of the earth, or because there a religion is taught
which did not exist a few thousand years previously?” The soul
experiences of the Germans during the War of 1870 found so little echo in
his soul that “while the thunder of battle passed from Wörth over
Europe,” he sat in a small corner of the Alps, “brooding and
puzzled, consequently most grieved, and at the same time not grieved,”
and wrote down his thoughts about the Greeks. And, a few weeks later,
as he found himself “under the walls of Metz,” he still
was not freed from the questions which he had concerning the life and
art of the Greeks.
(See Versuch einer Selbstkritik,
Attempt at a Self-Critique, in the 2nd edition of his
Geburt der Tragödie,
Birth of Tragedy.) When the war came to an end, he entered so little
enthusiasm of his German contemporaries over the decisive victory that in
the year 1873 in his writing about David Strauss he spoke about “the
bad and dangerous consequences” of the victorious struggle. He even
represented it as insanity that German culture should have been victorious
in this struggle, and he described this insanity as dangerous because if it
should become dominant within the German nation, the danger would exist
of transforming the victory into complete defeat; a defeat, yes, an
extirpation of the German spirit in favor of “the German realm.”
This was Nietzsche's attitude at a time when the whole of Europe was
filled with national fanaticism. It is the thinking of a personality
not in harmony with his time, of a fighter against his time.
Much more could be added to what has been said to show that Nietzsche's
life of feeling and reflection was completely different from that of
his contemporaries.
2.
Nietzsche is no “thinker”
in the usual sense of the word. For the deeply penetrating and valid
questions which he had to ask in regard to the world and life, mere
thinking was not sufficient. For these questions, all the forces of
human nature must be unchained; intellectual thinking alone
is not sufficient for the task. Nietzsche has no confidence in merely
intellectually conceived reasons for an opinion. “There is
a mistrust in me for dialectic, even for proofs” he writes to Georg
Brandes on the 2nd of December 1887 (see his
Menschen und Werke,
Men and Works, p. 212). For those who would ask the reasons for his
opinions, he is ready with the answer of Zarathustra, “You ask
why? I do not belong to those of whom one may ask their why.” For
him, a criterion was not that an opinion could be proved logically,
but rather if it acted upon all forces of the human personality in such
a way that it had value for life. He grants validity to a thought
only if he finds it will add to the development of life. To see man
as healthy as possible, as powerful as possible, as creative as possible,
is his desire. Truth, beauty, all ideals, have value and concern the
human being only to the extent that they foster life.
The question about the
value of truth appears in several of Nietzsche's writings.
In the most daring form it is asked in his
Jenseits von Gut und Böse,
Beyond Good and Evil. “The will for truth which has misled us
into so many hazards, that famous truthfulness, about which all
philosophers have spoken with awe: what questions this will for
truth has already put before us! What marvelous, difficult, worthy
questions! This is already a long story, yet it seems that it has barely
begun. Is it any wonder that we finally become mistrustful, lose patience,
turn about impatiently? Is it any wonder that from the Sphinx we ourselves
also learn to ask questions? Then who is it who asks questions here? What
is it in us that really wants to penetrate ‘to truth?’ In fact,
we had to stand for a long time before the question about the cause
of will — until we finally remained completely still before a yet more
fundamental question. We asked about the value of willing. That is,
provided we want truth; why not rather untruth?”
This is a thought of a
boldness hardly to be surpassed. If one places beside it what another
daring “ponderer and friend of riddles,” Johann Gottlieb Fichte,
said about the striving after truth, then one realizes for the first
time from what depths of human nature Nietzsche brings forth his ideas.
“I am destined,” said Fichte, “to bear witness to truth;
upon my life and my destiny, nothing depends; upon the effects of my
life, infinitely much depends. I am a priest of truth; I am in its debt;
for it I have bound myself to do all, to dare all, and to suffer all.”
(Fichte,
Über die Bestimmung des Gelehrten,
On the Task of the Scholar, Lecture 4). These words describe the relationship
of the most noble spirits of the newer Western culture to truth. In the
face of all of Nietzsche's cited expressions, they appear superficial.
Against them one can ask, Is it not possible that untruth has more valuable
effects upon life than truth? Is it impossible that truth harms life?
Has Fichte himself posed these questions? Have others done it who have
borne “witness to truth?”
But Nietzsche poses these
questions. And he believes that he can become clear only when he treats
this striving after truth not merely as an intellectual matter, but
seeks the instincts which bring forth this striving. For it could well
have been that these instincts make use of truth only as a medium to
accomplish something which stands higher than truth. Nietzsche thinks
after he has “looked at the philosophers long enough between the
lines and upon the fingers,” that “most thinking of philosophers
is secretly led by their instincts, and forced along definite ways.”
The philosophers consider that the final impulse to action is the striving
after truth. They believe this because they are unable to look into
the depths of human nature. In reality, this striving after truth is
guided by the will to power. With the help of truth, this power
and fullness of life should be increased for the personality. The conscious
thinking of the philosopher is of the opinion that the recognition of
truth is a final goal; the unconsicous instinct that motivates this
thinking strives toward the fostering of life. From this instinct, “the
falsity of a judgment is no real objection toward a judgment;”
for him only the question comes into consideration, “to what extent
is it life furthering, life supporting, species supporting, perhaps
even species cultivating.”
(Jenseits von Gut und Böse,
Beyond Good and Evil, ¶ 4.)
“Do you call will
to truth, you wisest ones, that which impels you and makes you ardent?
“Will for the conceivableness
of all being: thus do I name your will!
“All being would you
first make conceivable, because you doubt with good reason
whether it is already thinkable.
“But it shall yield
to you and bend itself to you! So wills your will. Smooth shall it
become, and subject to the spirit, as its mirror and reflection.
“That is your entire
will, you wisest ones, a Will to Power.”
(Zarathustra,
second part,
The Self Surpassing.)
Truth is to make the world
subservient to the spirit, and thereby serve life. Only as a life necessity
has it value. But can one not go further and ask, what is this life
worth in itself? Nietzsche considers such a question to be impossible.
That everything alive wants to live as powerfully, as meaningfully as
possible, he accepts as a fact about which he ponders no further. Life
instincts ask no further about the value of life. They ask only what
possibilities there are to increase the strength of its bearers. “Judgments,
evaluations of life, either for or against, can never be true, in the
final analysis; they have value only as symptoms, they come into consideration
only as symptoms, and in themselves such judgments are nonsense. One
must absolutely stretch out one's fingers and try to comprehend the
astonishing finesse in the fact that the value of life cannot be
measured. It cannot be measured by a living person because he partakes
of it; indeed, for him it is even an object of strife: therefore he
is no judge; neither can it be appraised by a dead person, for another
reason. For a philosopher to see a problem in the value of life remains,
so to speak, an accusation against him, a question concerning his wisdom
and lack of wisdom.”
(Götzendämmerung, Das Problem des Sokrates,
The Twilight of Idols, The Problem of Socrates.)
The question about the value of life exists only for a poorly educated,
sick personality. A well-rounded personality lives without
asking how much his life is worth.
Because Nietzsche has the
point of view described above, he places such little weight upon logical
proofs for a judgment. It is of little account to him that a judgment
lets itself be proved logically; he is interested in whether one can
live well under its influence. Not alone the intellect, but the whole
personality of the human being must be satisfied. The best thoughts
are those which bring all forces of human nature into an activity adapted
to the person.
Only thoughts of this nature
have interest for Nietzsche. He is not a philosophical brain, but a
“gatherer of honey of the intellect” who searches for “honey
baskets” of knowledge, and tries to bring home what benefits life.
3.
In Nietzsche's personality,
those instincts rule which make man a dominating, controlling being.
Everything pleases him which manifests might; everything displeases
him which discloses weakness. He feels happy only so long as he finds
himself in conditions of life which heighten his power. He loves hindrances,
obstacles against his activity, because he becomes aware of his own
power by overcoming them. He looks for the most difficult paths which the
human being can take. A fundamental trait of his character is expressed in
the verse which he has written on the title page of the second edition of his
Fröhliche Wissenschaft,
Joyful Wisdom:
“I live in my own house,
Have never copied anything from anyone,
And have ridiculed every master
Who has not ridiculed himself.”
Every kind of subordination
to a strange power Nietzsche feels as weakness. And he thinks differently
about that which is a “strange power” than many a one who
considers himself to be “an independent, free spirit.” Nietzsche
considers it a weakness when the human being; subordinates his thinking
and his doing to so-called “eternal, brazen” laws of the intellect.
Whatever the uniformly developed personality does, it does not allow
it to be prescribed by a moral science, but only by the impulses of
its own self. Man is already weak at the moment he searches
for laws and rules according to which he shall think and act.
Out of his own being the strong individual controls his way
of thinking and doing.
Nietzsche expresses this
opinion in the crudest form in sentences, because of which narrow-minded
people have characterized him as a downright dangerous spirit: “When
the Christian Crusaders in the East came into collision with that invincible
order of assassins, those orders of free thinking spirits, par
excellence, whose lowest order lived in a state of discipline such as no
order of monks ever attained, in some way or other they managed to get an
inkling of that symbol and motto that was reserved for the highest grade
alone, as their secret: ‘Nothing is true, everything is
permissible!’ ... Truly, that was freedom of the spirit; thereby
faith itself was giving notice to truth.”
(Genealogie der Moral,
Genealogy of Morals, 3rd Section, ¶ 24.)
That these sentences are the
expression of feelings of an aristocratic, of a master nature, which will not
permit the individual to live freely according to his own laws, with no
regard to the eternal truths and rules of morality, those people do not feel
who by nature are adjusted to subordination. A personality such as Nietzsche
cannot bear those tyrants who appear in the form of abstract moral
commandments. I determine how I am to think, how I am to act, says such
a nature.
There are people who base their
justification for calling themselves “free thinkers” upon the
fact that in their thinking and acting they do not subject themselves to
those laws which are derived from other human beings, but only to “the
eternal laws of the intellect,” the “incontrovertible
concepts of duty,” or “the Will of God.” Nietzsche does
not regard such people as really strong personalities. For
they do not think and act according to their own nature, but according
to the commands of a higher authority. Whether the slave follows
the arbitrariness of his master, the religious the revealed verities
of a God, or the philosopher the demands of the intellect, this changes
nothing of the fact that they are all obeyers. What does the
commanding is of no importance; the deciding factor is that
there is commanding, that the human being does not give his own direction
for his acting, but thinks that there is a power which delineates this
direction.
The strong, truly free
human being will not receive truth, he will create it; he
will not let something “be permitted” him; he will not obey.
“The real philosophers are commanders and law givers;
they say, ‘Thus shall it be,’ they first decide the
‘why’ and ‘wherefore’ and thereby dispose of the
preliminary labor of all philosophical workers, all conquerors of the past;
they grasp at the future with creative hands and all that is and was becomes
for them a means, a tool, a hammer. Their ‘knowing’ is
creating, their creating is a law-giving, their will to truth is
Will to Power. Are there such philosophers today? Were there once
such philosophers? Must there not be such philosophers?”
(Jenseits von Gut und Böse,
Beyond Good and Evil, ¶ 211.)
4.
Nietzsche sees a special
indication of human weakness in every type of belief in a world beyond,
in a world other than that in which man lives. According to him, one
can do no greater harm to life than to order one's existence in this
world according to another life in a world beyond. One cannot give oneself
over to greater confusion than when one assumes the existence of beings
behind the phenomena of this world, beings which are not approachable
by human knowledge, and which are to be considered as the real basis,
as the decisive factor in all existence. By such an assumption one ruins
for oneself the joy in this world. One degrades it to illusion, to a
mere reflection of the inaccessible. One interprets the world known
to us, the world which for us is the only real one, as a futile dream,
and attributes true reality to an imaginary, fictitious other world.
One interprets the human senses as deceivers, who give us only illusory
pictures instead of realities.
Such a point of view cannot
stem from weakness. For the strong person who is deeply rooted in reality,
who has joy in life, will not let it enter his head to imagine another
reality. He is occupied with this world and needs no other. But the
suffering, the ill, those dissatisfied with this life, take refuge in
the yonder. What this life has taken away from them, the world beyond
is to offer them. The strong, healthy person who has well developed
senses fitted to search for the causes of this world in this world itself,
requires no causes or beings of the world beyond for the understanding
of the appearances within which he lives. The weak person, who perceives
reality with crippled eyes and ears, needs causes behind the appearances.
Out of suffering and sick
longing, the belief in the yonder world is born. Out of the inability to
penetrate the real world all acceptances of “things in themselves”
have originated.
All who have reason to
deny the real life say Yes to an imaginary
one. Nietzsche wants to be an affirmer in face of reality.
He will explore this world in all directions; he will penetrate into
the depths of existence; of another life he wants to know nothing. Even
suffering itself cannot provoke him to say No to life, for
suffering also is a means to knowledge. “Like a traveler who plans
to awaken at a certain hour, and then peacefully succumbs to sleep,
we philosophers surrender ourselves to sickness, provided that we have
become ill for a time in body and soul; we also close our eyes. And
as the traveler knows that somewhere something does not sleep,
that something counts the hours and will awaken him, so we also know
that the decisive moment will find us awake — that then something will
spring forth and catch the spirit in the act; I mean, in the
weakness or the turning back or the surrendering or the hardening or
the beclouding, as all the many sick conditions of the spirit are called,
which in days of health had the pride of spirit against them.
After such a self-questioning, self-examination, one learns to look
with a finer eye at everything which had been philosophized about until
now.” (Preface to the second edition of
Fröhliche Wissenschalt,
Joyful Wisdom.)
5.
Nietzsche's friendly attitude
toward life and reality shows itself also in his point of view in regard to
men and their relationships with each other. In this field Nietzsche is a
complete individualist. Each human being is for him a world in itself, a
unicum. “This marvelously colorful manifoldness which is
unified to a ‘oneness’ and faces us as a certain human being,
no accident, however strange, could shake together in a like way a second
time.”
(Schopenhauer als Erzieher,
Schopenhauer as Educator, ¶ 1.)
Very few human beings, however, are inclined to unfold their
individualities, which exist but once. They are in terror of the loneliness
into which they are forced because of this. It is more comfortable and
less dangerous to live in the same way as one's fellow men; there one
always finds company. The one who arranges his life in his own way is
not understood by others, and finds no companions. Loneliness has a
special attraction for Nietzsche. He loves to search for secrets within
his own self. He flees from the community of human beings. For the most
part, his ways of thought are attempts to search for treasures which
lie deeply hidden within his personality. The light which others offer
him, he despises; the air one breathes where the “community of
human beings,” the “average man” lives, he will not breathe.
Instinctively he strives toward his “citadel and privacy”
where he is free from the crowds, from the many, from the majority.
(Jenseits van Gut und Böse,
Beyond Good and Evil, ¶ 26).
In his
Fröliche Wissenschaft,
Joyful Wisdom,
he complains that it is difficult for him to “digest” his
fellow men; and in
Jenseits van Gut und Böse,
Beyond Good and Evil, ¶ 282,
he discloses that at the least he carried away dangerous intestinal
disturbances when he sat down at the table where the diet of “ordinary
human beings” was served. Human beings must not come too close
to Nietzsche if he is to stand them.
6.
Nietzsche grants validity
to a thought, a judgment, in the form to which the free-reigning life
instincts give their assent. Attitudes which are decided by life he
does not allow to be removed by logical doubt. For this reason his thinking
has a firm, free swing. It is not confused by reflections as to whether
an assumption is also true “objectively,” whether it does
not go beyond the boundaries, of the possibilities of human knowledge,
etc. When Nietzsche has recognized the value of a judgment for life,
he no longer asks for a further “objective” meaning and validity.
And he does not worry about the limits of knowledge. It is his opinion
that a healthy thinking creates what it is able to create, and does
not torment itself with the useless question, what can I not
do?
The one who wishes to determine
the value of a judgment by the degree to which it furthers life, can,
of course, only do this on the basis of his own personal life impulses
and instincts. He can never wish to say more than, Insofar as my own
life instincts are concerned, I consider this particular judgment to
be valuable. And Nietzsche never wishes to say anything else when he
expresses a point of view. It is just this relationship of his to his
thought world which works so beneficially upon the reader who is orientated
toward freedom. It gives Nietzsche's writings a character of unselfish,
modest dignity. In comparison, how repellent and immodest it sounds when
other thinkers believe their person to be the organ by which eternal,
irrefutable verities are made known to the world. One can find sentences
in Nietzsche's works which express his strong ego-consciousness, for
example, “I have given to mankind the deepest book which it possesses,
my Zarathustra; soon I shall give it the most independent.”
(Götzendämmerung,
Twilight of Idols, ¶ 51.)
But what do these words indicate? I have dared to write a book whose
content is drawn from lower depths of a personality than is usual in
similar books, and I shall offer a book which is more independent of
every strange judgment than other philosophical writings, for I shall
speak about the most important things only in the way they relate to
my personal instincts. That is dignified modesty. It would of course
go against the taste of those whose lying humility says, I am nothing,
my work is everything; I bring nothing of my personal feelings into
my books, but I express only what the pure intellect allows me to express.
Such people want to deny their person in order to assert that their
expressions are those of a higher spirit. Nietzsche considers his thoughts
to be the results of his own person and nothing more.
7.
The specialist philosophers
may smile about Nietzsche, or give us their impressions about the “dangers”
of his “world conception” as best they can. Of course, many
of these spirits, who are nothing but animated textbooks of logic, are
not able to praise Nietzsche's creations, which spring from the most
mighty, most immediate life impulses.
In any case, with his bold
thought Nietzsche leaps and hits upon deeper secrets of human nature
than many a logical thinker with his cautious creeping. Of what use
is all logic if it catches only worthless content in its net of concepts?
When valuable thoughts are communicated to us, we rejoice in them alone,
even if they are not tied together with logical threads. The salvation
of life does not depend upon logic alone, but also upon the production
of thoughts. At present our specialized philosophy is sufficiently unproductive,
and it could very well use the stimulation of the thoughts of a courageous,
bold writer like Nietzsche. The power of development of their specialized
philosophy is paralyzed through the influence which the thinking of
Kant has made upon them. Through this influence it has lost all originality,
all courage. From the academic philosophy of his time Kant has taken
over the concept of truth which originates from “pure reason,”
He has tried to show that through such truth we cannot learn to know
things which lie beyond our experience of “things in themselves.”
During the last century, infinite, immeasurable cleverness was expended
to penetrate into these thoughts of Kant's from all directions, The
results of this sharp thinking are unfortunately rather meager and trivial,
Should one translate the banalities of many a current philosophical
book from academic formulae into healthy speech, such content would
compare rather poorly with many a short aphorism of Nietzsche's, In
view of present-day philosophy, the latter could speak the proud sentence
with a certain justice, “It is my ambition to say in ten sentences
what others say in one book — what every other person does not say
in one book ...”
8.
As Nietzsche does not want
to express anything but the results of his personal instincts and impulses,
so to him strange points of view are nothing more than symptoms from
which he draws conclusions about the ruling instincts of individual
human beings or whole peoples, races, and so on. He does not occupy
himself with discussions or arguments over strange opinions. But he
looks for the instincts which are expressed in these opinions. He tries
to discover the character of the personalities or people from their
attitudes. Whether an attitude indicates the dominance of instincts
for health, courage, dignity, joy, and life, or whether it originates
from unhealthy, slavish, tired instincts, inimical to life, all this
interests him. Truths in themselves are indifferent to him; he concerns
himself with the way people develop their truths according to their
instincts, and how they further their life goals through them. He looks
for the natural causes of human attitudes.
Nietzsche's striving, of
course, is not according to the tendencies of those idealists who attribute
an independent value to truth, who want to give it “a purer, higher
origin” than that of the instincts. He explains human views as
the result of natural forces, just as the natural scientist explains
the structure of the eye from the cooperation of natural causes. He
recognizes an explanation of the spiritual development of mankind out
of special moral purposes, or ideals out of a moral world order, as
little as the natural scientist of today recognizes the explanation
that nature has built the eye in a certain way for the reason
that nature had the intention to create an organ of seeing
for the organism. In every ideal Nietzsche sees only the expression
of an instinct which looks toward satisfaction in a definite form, just
as the modern natural scientist sees in the intentional arrangement of
an organ, the result of organic formative laws. If at present there
still exist natural scientists and philosophers who reject all purposeful
creating in nature, but, who stop short before moral idealism, and
see in history the realization of a divine will, an ideal order of things,
this belief is an incompleteness of the instinct. Such people lack the
necessary perspective for the judging of spiritual happenings, while
they have it for the observation of natural happenings. When a human
being thinks he is striving toward an ideal which does not derive from
reality, he thinks this only because he does not recognize the instinct
from which this ideal stems.
Nietzsche is an anti-idealist
in that sense in which the modern natural scientist opposes the assumption
of purposes which nature is to materialize. He speaks just as little
about moral purposes as the natural scientist speaks about natural purposes.
Nietzsche does not consider it wiser to say, Man should materialize
a moral ideal, than to explain that the bull has horns so that he may
gore with them. He considers the one as well as the other expression
to be a product of a world explanation which speaks about “divine
providence,” “wise omnipotence,” instead of natural causes.
This world clarification
is a check to all sound thinking; it produces a fictitious fog of ideals
which prevents that natural power of seeing, orientated to the observation
of reality, that ability to fathom world events; finally, it completely
dulls all sense for reality.
9.
When Nietzsche engages
in a spiritual battle he doesn't wish to contradict foreign opinions
as such, but he does so because these opinions point to instincts harmful
and contrary to nature, against which he wishes to fight. In this regard
his intention is similar to that of someone who attacks a harmful natural
phenomenon or destroys a dangerous creature. He does not count on the
“convincing” power of truth, but on the fact that he will
conquer his opponent because the latter has unsound, harmful instincts,
while he himself has sound, life-furthering instincts. He looks for
no further justification for such a battle when his instinct considers
his opponent to be harmful. He does not believe that he has to fight
as the representative of an idea, but he fights because his instincts
compel him to do so. Of course, it is the same with any spiritual battle,
but ordinarily the fighters are as little aware of the real motivations
as are the philosophers of their “Will to Power,” or the followers
of a moral world order of the natural causes of their moral ideals.
They believe that only opinions fight opinions, and they disguise their
true motives by cloaks of concepts. They also do not mention the instincts
of the opponents which are unsympathetic to them; indeed, perhaps these
do not enter their consciousness at all. In short, these forces which
are really hostile toward each other do not come out into the open at
all. Nietzsche mentions unreservedly those instincts of his opponents
which are disagreeable to him, and he also mentions the instincts with
which he opposes them. One who wishes to call this cynicism may
well do so. But he must be certain not to overlook the fact that never
in all human activity has there existed anything other than such cynicism,
and that all idealistic, illusory webs are spun by this cynicism.
|