Goethe and the Platonic View of the World.
I
have described the evolution of thought from the age of Plato
to that of Kant in order to be able to show the impressions
which Goethe was bound to receive when he turned to the
outcome of the philosophical thoughts to which he might have
adhered in order to satisfy his intense desire for knowledge.
He found in the philosophies no answer to the innumerable
problems which his nature impelled him to face. Indeed,
whenever he delved into the world-conception of some
particular philosopher, he found an opposition between the
drift of his questions and the world of thought from which he
would have liked to get counsel. The reason for this lies in
the fact that the one-sided Platonic separation of idea and
experience was repugnant to his being. When he observed
Nature the ideas lay there before him. He could therefore
only think of Nature as permeated by ideas. A world of ideas
that neither permeates the objects of Nature nor brings about
their appearance and disappearance, their becoming and
growth, is to him nothing but a feeble web of thought. The
logical fabrication of trains of thoughts without penetration
into the life and creative activity of Nature appeared to him
unfruitful, for he felt himself intimately one with Nature.
He looked upon himself as a living member of Nature. In his
view, all that arose in his spirit had been permitted by
Nature so to arise. Man should not sit away in a corner and
imagine that from there he can spin out of himself a web of
thoughts which elucidates the true being of things. He should
rather allow the stream of world-events to flow through him
perpetually. Then he will feel that the world of ideas is
nothing else than the active, creative power of Nature. He
will not then want to stand above the objects in order to
reflect upon them, but he will sink himself into their depths
and extract from them all that lives and works in them.
Goethe's artistic nature led him to this mode of
thinking. He felt his poetic creations grow out of his
personality with the same necessity as that which makes a
flower blossom. The way in which the spirit within him
produced the work of Art seemed to him no different from the
way in which Nature produces her creatures. And just as in
the work of Art the spiritual element cannot be separated
from the spiritless material, so it was impossible for him,
in face of a natural object, to think the perception without
the idea. A point of view to which the perception is only an
indefinite, confused element and which wishes to see the
world of ideas separated off, purged of all experience, is
therefore foreign to him. In all those world-conceptions in
which the elements of a partially understood Platonism lived,
he sensed something contrary to Nature. For this reason he
could not find in the philosophers what he sought. He was
seeking for the ideas which live in the objects and which
allow all the particulars of experience to appear as if
growing out of a living whole, and the philosophers offered
him husks of thought that they had combined into systems
according to the principles of Logic. He always found that he
was thrown back on himself when he turned to others for
explanation of the problems which Nature set him.
* * * * *
One of the things from which Goethe suffered before his
Italian journey was that his yearning for knowledge could
find no satisfaction. In Italy he was able to form a view of
the motive forces which give rise to works of Art. He
recognised that perfect works of Art contain what men
reverence as the Divine, the Eternal. After beholding the
artistic creations which interested him most deeply, he wrote
these words: “The great works of Art, like the highest
creations of Nature, have been brought forth in conformity
with true and natural law. All that is arbitrary, that is
invented, collapses: there is Necessity, there is God.”
The art of the Greeks drew forth this utterance from him:
“I suspect that the Greeks proceeded according to those
laws by which Nature herself proceeds, and of which I am on
the track.” What Plato believed to have found in the
world of ideas and what the philosophers could never bring
home to Goethe, streamed forth to him from the works of Art
in Italy. What he is able to regard as the basis of knowledge
is revealed to him for the first time, in a perfect form, in
Art. He sees in artistic production a mode and higher stage
of Nature's working; artistic creation is to him an enhanced
Nature-creation. He expressed this later in his
characterisation of Winckelmann: “In that man is placed
on Nature's pinnacle, he regards himself as another whole
Nature, whose task is to bring forth inwardly yet another
pinnacle. For this purpose he heightens his powers, imbues
himself with all perfections and virtues, summons
discrimination, order and harmony, and rises finally to
the production of a work of Art.” Goethe does not
attain to his world-conception along the path of logical
deduction but as a result of the contemplation of the essence
of Art. And what he found in Art he seeks also in Nature.
The kind of activity by means of which Goethe acquired his
knowledge of Nature does not differ essentially from artistic
activity. Both play into and mutually react on each other. In
Goethe's view the artist must surely become mightier and more
effective when, in addition to his talent, “he is a
well-informed Botanist, when he knows, from the root upwards,
the influence of the different parts on the health and growth
of the plant, their significance and mutual interaction, when
he penetrates into and reflects upon the successive
development of the flowers, leaves, fertilisation, fruit and
new seed. He will not then reveal his own ‘taste’ by a choice
from among the phenomena, but by a true portrayal of the
qualities he will instruct and at the same time fill us with
admiration.” The work of Art is therefore the more
perfect, the more fully it expresses the same law as that
embodied in the work of Nature to which it corresponds. There
is but one uniform realm of truth, and this includes both Art
and Nature. Hence the faculty of artistic creation cannot
differ essentially from the faculty of the cognition of
Nature. Goethe says in reference to the artist's style that
“it is based on the deepest foundations of knowledge,
on the essence of things in so far as it is granted us to
cognise this essence in visible, tangible forms.” The
view of the world that had proceeded from one-sided
understanding of Platonic conceptions draws a sharp boundary
line between Science and Art. It bases artistic activity upon
phantasy, upon feeling, and would represent scientific
results as the outcome of a development of concepts that is
free of the element of phantasy. Goethe sees the matter
differently. When he directs his gaze to Nature he finds
there a sum-total of ideas; but to him the ideal constituent
is not confined within the single object of experience; the
idea points out beyond the particular object to related
objects wherein it manifests in a similar way. The
philosophical observer takes hold of this ideal element and
brings it to direct expression in his thought-creations. This
ideal element works also upon the artist. But it stimulates
him to give form to a creation wherein the idea does not
merely function as in a work of Nature, but becomes present
in appearance. That which in a work of Nature is merely
ideal, and is revealed to the spiritual vision of the
observer, becomes concrete, perceptible reality in the work
of Art. The artist realises the ideas of Nature. It is not,
however, necessary that he should be conscious of these in
the form of ideas. When he contemplates an object or an event
something else assumes direct form in his spirit —
something that contains as actual appearance what Nature
contains only as idea. The artist gives us images of Nature's
works and in these images the ideal content of Nature's works
is transformed into perceptual content. The philosopher shows
how Nature presents herself to contemplative thought; the
artist shows how Nature would appear if she were to reveal
openly her active forces not merely to thought but also to
perception. It is one and the same truth that the philosopher
presents in the form of thought and the artist in the form of
an image. The two differ only in their means of
expression.
The insight into the true relationship of idea and experience
which Goethe acquired in Italy is only the fruit of the seed
that was lying concealed in his nature. The Italian journey
afforded the sun-warmth which was able to ripen the seed. In
the Essay “Nature” which appeared in 1782
in the Tiefurt Journal, and for which Goethe was responsible,
[Compare my proof of Goethe's authorship in
Vol. VII of the publications of the Goethe Society.]
the germs of the later
Goethean world-conception are already to be found. What is
here dim feeling later develops into clear, definite thought.
“Nature! we are surrounded and embraced by her, we
cannot draw back from her, nor can we penetrate more deeply
into her being. She lifts us, unasked and unwarned, into the
gyrations of her dance and whirls us away until we fall
exhausted from her arms. ... She (Nature) has thought and she
broods unceasingly, not as a man but as Nature. ... She has
neither language nor speech, but she creates tongues and
hearts through which she speaks and feels. ... It was not I
who spoke of her. Nay, it was she who spoke it all, true and
false. Hers is the blame for all things, hers the
credit.” At the time when Goethe wrote these sentences
it was not yet clear to him how Nature expresses her ideal
being through man; but what he did feel was that it is the
voice of the Spirit of Nature that sounds in the Spirit of
Man.
* * * * *
In Italy Goethe found the spiritual atmosphere which was able
to develop his organs of cognition in the only way that in
accordance with their inherent nature they could develop, if
he were ever to find complete satisfaction. In Rome he
had “many discussions with Moriz about Art and its
theoretical demands;” as he observed the metamorphosis
of plants on the journey there developed in him a natural
method that later proved fruitful for the cognition of the
whole of organic Nature. “For as vegetation unfolded
her procedure before me stage by stage, I could not fall into
error, but allowing things as I did to take their own course,
I could not fail to recognise the ways and means by which the
most undeveloped state was brought to perfection.” A
few years after his return from Italy Goethe was able to find
a mode of procedure, born of his spiritual needs, for the
observation of inorganic Nature also. “In connection
with physical investigations the conviction was borne
in upon me that in all observation of objects the highest
duty is to search for every condition under which the
phenomenon appears, with the greatest exactitude, and to
strive for the greatest possible perfection of the phenomena;
because ultimately they are bound to range themselves
alongside each other or rather overlap each other, to form a
kind of organisation before the gaze of the investigator, and
to manifest their inner, common life.”
Nowhere did Goethe find enlightenment. He had always to
enlighten himself. He tried to find the reason for this and
came to the conclusion that he had no facility for philosophy
in the proper sense. The reason, however, lies in the fact
that the one-sided comprehension of the Platonic mode of
thought which dominated all philosophies accessible to Goethe
was contrary to the healthy tendency of his nature. In his
youth he had repeatedly turned to Spinoza. He admits that
this philosopher always had a “pacifying effect”
upon him. The reason for this is that Spinoza conceives of
the universe as one great unity with the single parts
proceeding necessarily from the whole. But when Goethe
entered into the content of Spinoza's Philosophy he still
felt it to be alien to him. “It must not be imagined
that I was able to agree absolutely with his writings and
admit their truth word for word; for I had already realised
only too clearly that no one person understands another, nor
thinks as another, even although their words may be the same;
I had realised that a conversation or reading would awaken
different trains of thought in different people. And one will
credit the author of Werther and Faust with the fact that,
deeply permeated by such misunderstandings, he is not
conceited enough to imagine that he has perfect understanding
of a man, who, as a disciple of Descartes has raised himself
through mathematical and rabbinical culture to the summit of
thought which up to the present time seems to be the goal of
all speculative endeavours.” It was not the fact
that Spinoza had been taught by Descartes, nor that Spinoza
had attained to the summit of thought as the result of
mathematical and rabbinical culture that made him an element
to which Goethe could not wholly surrender himself, but it
was Spinoza's purely logical method of handling knowledge
— a method that is alien to reality. Goethe could not
surrender himself to a mode of pure thinking free of all
element of experience, because he could not separate this
from the sum-total of the real. He did not want to connect
one thought with another in a merely logical sense. Such an
activity of thought seemed to him rather to depart from true
reality. He felt that he must sink his spirit into the
experience in order to reach the idea. The mutual interplay
of idea and perception was to Goethe a spiritual breathing.
“Time is regulated by the swings of the pendulum; the
moral scientific world is regulated by the interplay of idea
and experience.” To observe the world and its phenomena
in the sense of these words seemed to Goethe to be in
conformity with Nature. For he had no doubt but that Nature
observes the same procedure; that she (Nature) is a
development from a mysterious, living Whole into the diverse
and specific phenomena that fill space and time. The
mysterious Whole is the world of the idea. “The idea is
eternal and unique; that we also use the plural is
unfortunate. All things that we perceive and of which we can
speak are but manifestations of the idea; we utter concepts
and to this extent the idea is itself a concept.”
Nature's creative activity proceeds from the ideal Whole into
the particular that is given to perception as something real.
The observer ought therefore “to recognise the ideal in
the real and allay his temporary dissatisfaction with the
finite by rising to the infinite.” Goethe is convinced
that “Nature proceeds according to idea just in the
same way as man follows an idea in all that he
undertakes.” When man really succeeds in rising to the
idea and in comprehending from out of the idea the details of
perception, he accomplishes the same thing as Nature
accomplishes by allowing her creations to issue forth from
the mysterious Whole. So long as man has no sense of the
working and creative activity of the idea, his thinking is
divorced from living Nature. He must regard thinking as a
purely subjective activity that is able to project an
abstract picture of Nature. But directly he senses the way in
which the idea lives and is active in his inner being he
regards himself and Nature as one Whole, and what makes its
appearance in his inner being as a subjective element is for
him at the same time objective; he knows that he no longer
confronts Nature as a stranger, but he feels that he has
grown together with the whole of her. The subjective has
become objective; the objective is wholly permeated with the
spirit. Goethe thinks that Kant's fundamental error consists
in the fact that he (Kant) “regards the subjective,
cognitive faculty itself as object, and makes indeed a sharp
but not wholly correct division at the point where subjective
and objective meet “ (Weimar Edition, Part II. Volume
II. Page 376.). The cognitive faculty appears to man as
subjective only so long as he does not notice that it is
Nature herself who speaks through this faculty. Subjective
and objective meet when the objective world of ideas lives in
the subject and when all that is active in Nature herself
lives in the spirit of man. When this happens, all antithesis
between subject and object ceases. This antithesis has
meaning only so long as it is artificially sustained and man
regards the ideas as being his own thoughts by which the
being of Nature is reflected, but in which, however, this
being is not itself active. Kant and his followers had no
inkling of the fact that the essential being of objects is
directly experienced in the ideas of reason. To them the
ideal is merely subjective, and they therefore came to the
conclusion that the ideal can necessarily only be valid if
that to which it is related, the world of experience, is also
merely subjective. The Kantian mode of thought is in sharp
contrast to Goethe's views. There are, it is true, isolated
utterances of Goethe where he speaks with some
appreciation of Kant's views. He says that he has been
present at many discussions of these views. “With a
little attention I was able to observe the reappearance of
the old cardinal question — the question as to how much
the Self and how much the external world contributes to our
spiritual existence. I had never separated these two,
and when I philosophized in my own fashion about objects, I
did so with unconscious naiveté and really believed that
I saw my opinions clearly before me. As soon, however, as
that dispute came into the discussion, I wanted to
range myself on that side which does man most credit, and I
gave entire approbation to all those friends who maintained
with Kant that even if all knowledge commences with
experience it is not necessarily all derived from
experience.” Neither does the idea, in Goethe's view,
originate from that portion of experience which may be
perceived through the senses of man. Reason, Imagination
(Phantasie) must be active and penetrate to the inner being
of things in order to master the ideal element of existence.
To this extent the spirit of man participates in the birth of
knowledge. Goethe thinks that honour is due to man because
the higher reality which is inaccessible to the senses, is
made manifest in his spirit; Kant, on the other hand, denies
the character of higher reality of the world of experience,
because it contains elements that are derived from the
spirit. Goethe was only able to find himself in some measure
of agreement with the Kantian principles when he had
interpreted them in the light of his own world-conception.
The fundamental principles of the Kantian mode of
thought are strongly antagonistic to Goethe's nature. If he
does not emphasise this sharply enough, it is really only
because he will not allow himself to enter into these
fundamental principles because they are too alien to him.
“It was the Introduction (to
The Critique of Pure Reason)
that pleased me; I could not venture into the
labyrinth itself for here I was restrained by my poetic gift
and there by the human intellect, and I felt no benefit
anywhere.” In reference to his discussions with the
followers of Kant, Goethe had to make this confession:
“They listened to me, it is true, but could give me no
reply nor be helpful in any way. More than once it happened
that one or another of them admitted in smiling
admiration, ‘it is certainly analogous to the Kantian
mode of conception, but in a very peculiar sense.’” ...
It was, as I have shown, not analogous at all, but the very
reverse of Kant's mode of conception.
* * * * *
It is interesting to see how Schiller tries to explain to
himself the difference between the Goethean mode of thinking
and his own. He senses the originality and freedom of
Goethe's world-conception. He cannot, however, rid his mind
of thought elements that are the result of a one-sided
conception of Platonism. He cannot attain the insight that
idea and perception are not separated from each other in
reality, but are only thought of as separated by the
intellect that has been led astray by a misguided trend of
ideas. Therefore in contrast to the Goethean mode of thinking
which he describes as intuitive, he places his own
speculative mode of thinking and asserts that both must lead
to one and the same goal if they only operate with sufficient
power. Schiller assumes that the intuitive mind adheres to
the empirical, the individual, and rises from there to the
law, to the idea. If such a mind is endowed with the quality
of genius it will cognise in the empirical, the necessary; in
the individual, the species. The speculative mind, on the
other hand, must proceed by the reverse path. The law, the
idea, has first to be given to it and from thence it descends
to the empirical and individual. If such a mind is endowed
with the quality of genius it will of course always have the
species only in view, but with the possibility of life and
with an established relation to real objects. The assumption
of a special type of mind — of the speculative in
contradistinction to the intuitive — is based on the
belief that the world of ideas has an existence separate and
distinct from the world of perception. If this were the case
a path could be found along which the content of the ideas
about the objects of perception might enter the mind even
when the mind does not seek it in experience. If, however,
the world of ideas is inseparably bound up with the reality
given in experience, if the two only exist as one
Whole, there can only be an intuitive cognition that seeks
for the idea in the experience and apprehends the species
along with the individual. The truth is that there is no
purely speculative mind in Schiller's sense. For the species
exist only within the sphere to which the individuals also
pertain. The mind cannot find them elsewhere. If a so-called
speculative mind really has conceptions of species, these are
derived from observation of the real world. When the living
feeling for this origin, for the essential connection of the
species with the individual, is lost, there arises the
opinion that such ideas can arise in the reason also without
experience. Those who hold this opinion describe a number of
abstract conceptions of species as the content of the pure
reason because they do not see the threads which bind these
ideas to experience. Such an illusion can occur most easily
in connection with ideas that are the most general and
comprehensive in character. Because such ideas cover a wide
region of reality, a great deal that appertains to the
entities belonging to this region is effaced or obliterated.
A man may absorb a number of such general ideas through
tradition and then come to believe that they are inborn in
human beings or that they have been spun by man from out of
pure reason. A mind that lapses into such a belief may regard
itself as speculative in character. It will, however, never
be able to extract from its world of ideas any ideas other
than have been placed there by tradition. Schiller is in
error when he says that the speculative mind, if it is
endowed with the quality of genius, produces “indeed
only species but with the possibility of life and with an
established relation to real objects” (Compare
Schiller's letter to Goethe, 23rd August, 1794.). A truly
speculative mind, living only in concepts of species, could
find in its world of ideas no established relationship to
reality other than that already existing within that world of
ideas. A mind that has relation to the reality of Nature and
in spite of this designates itself as speculative, is
labouring under a delusion as to its own nature. This
delusion can mislead it into negligence of its relation to
reality and to actual life. It will imagine itself able to
dispense with direct perception because it believes that
other sources of truth are in its possession. The result of
this always is that the ideal world of such a mind bears a
dull, pale character. The fresh colours of life will be
lacking from its thoughts. Those who wish to live with
reality will be able to acquire little from such a world of
thought. It cannot be admitted that the speculative type of
mind is on the same level as the intuitive; it is stunted and
impoverished. The intuitive mind is not concerned with
individuals alone, it does not seek the character of
necessity in the empirical. But when it applies itself to
Nature, perception and idea coalesce into unity. Both
are seen to exist within each other and are perceived as one
Whole. The intuitive mind may rise to the most universal
truths, to the highest abstractions, but direct, actual life
will always be evident in its world of thought. Goethe's
thinking was of this nature. In his Anthropology,
Heinroth has spoken about this kind of thinking in striking
words that pleased Goethe in the highest degree, because they
explained to him his own nature. “Dr. Heinroth speaks
favourably of my nature and activity, indeed he describes my
modus operandi as original; he says that my thinking
faculty is objectively active, by which he means to express
that my thinking does not sever itself from the objects; that
the elements inherent in the objects and the perceptions
enter into my thinking and are permeated by it in a most
intimate way; that my perceiving is itself thinking, my
thinking, perceiving.” Fundamentally speaking, Heinroth
is describing nothing else than the way in which all sound
thinking is related to objects. Any other mode of procedure
is a deviation from the natural path. If perception
predominates in a man he adheres to the individual element;
he cannot penetrate to the deeper foundations of reality. If
abstract thought predominates in him, his concepts are
manifestly inadequate to comprehend the whole living content
of the real. The extreme of the first deviation from the
natural path produces the crude empiricist who contents
himself with the individual facts; the extreme of the other
deviation is represented in the philosopher who worships pure
Reason and who merely thinks, without realising that thoughts
in their essential being, are bound up with perception. In
beautiful imagery Goethe describes the feeling of the thinker
who rises to the highest truths without losing the sense for
living experience. At the beginning of the year 1784 he
writes an Essay on Granite. He goes to a hill composed of
this stone where he is able to soliloquise as follows:
“Here you are resting on a substructure that extends to
the very depths of the Earth; no newer stratum, no deposited,
heaped-up fragments are laid between you and the firm
foundation of the primordial world; you are not passing over
a continuous grave as in yonder fruitful valleys; these peaks
have brought forth no living thing, have devoured no living
thing; they are antecedent to all life, they transcend all
life. In this moment when the inner attractive and moving
forces of the Earth are working directly upon me, when the
influence of the heavens hovers more closely around me, it is
given to me to attain to a more sublime perception of Nature,
and as the human spirit gives life to everything, an
image whose sublimity I cannot withstand, is stirred to
activity within me. looking down this naked peak with scanty
moss hardly perceptible at its base, I say to myself that
this loneliness overtakes one who would fain open his soul
only to the first, oldest, deepest feelings of truth. Such an
one can say to himself: here on the most ancient,
imperishable altar, built immediately above the depths of
Creation, I bring a sacrifice to the Being of all Beings. I
feel the first firm beginnings of our existence; I look over
the world with its valleys now rugged, now undulating, its
wide fertile meadows, and my soul, raised above itself
and all else, yearns for the Heavens that draw nigh. But soon
the burning sun calls back thirst and hunger — human
needs — and one looks around for those valleys above
which one's spirit had raised itself.” Such enthusiasm
in knowledge, such a sense for the oldest, immutable truths
can only develop in a man who continually finds his way back
from the spheres of the world of ideas to direct
perceptions.
|