Introduction
There are magic formulas which continue to act in perpetually new ways
throughout the centuries of the history of ideas. In Greece one such formula
was regarded as an oracle of Apollo. It is, Know thyself. Such
sentences seem to contain an infinite life within themselves. One meets them in
walking the most diverse paths of spiritual life. The more one advances, the
more one penetrates to an understanding of all phenomena, the deeper appears
the meaning of these formulas. At many moments in the course of our
meditations and thoughts they flash like lightning, illuminating our whole
inner life. At such times there arises in us something like the feeling that
we perceive the heartbeat of humanity's development. How close we feel to
personalities of the past when one of their sayings arouses in us the
sensation that they are revealing to us the fact of their having had such
moments! One then feels oneself brought into an intimate relationship with
these personalities. Thus for instance, one becomes intimately acquainted with
Hegel
when, in the third volume of his Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der
Philosophie, Lectures on the History of Philosophy, one comes upon the
words: Such stuff, one says, are the abstractions we behold when we let
the philosophers dispute and quarrel in our study, and decide matters in this
way or in that; these are abstractions made up of mere words. No! No!
They are acts of the universal spirit, and therefore of fate. In this the
philosophers are closer to the master than those who feed upon the crumbs of
the spirit; they read or write the cabinet orders in the original: it is
their function to take part in writing them. The philosophers are the
mystics who were present at the act in the innermost sanctuary and who
participated in it. When Hegel said this he experienced one of the moments
described above. He spoke these sentences when he had reached the end of
Greek philosophy in the course of his analysis. And through them he has
shown that the meaning of Neoplatonist wisdom, of which he speaks at this
point, was at one time illuminated for him as by a stroke of lightning. At
the moment of this illumination he had become intimate with such spirits as
Plotinus and Proclus. And we become intimate with him as we read his words.
And we become intimate with the solitarily meditating vicar in Zschopau, M.
Valentinus Wigelius (Valentin Weigel), when we read the words of
introduction to his booklet, Erkenne dich selbst, Know Thyself, written
in 1578. We read in the old sages the useful proverb, Know
thyself, which, although it is principally used to refer to worldly
behavior, such as, Look well at yourself, what you are; Search in your bosom;
Judge yourself, and
leave others uncensored: although it is, I say, used in human life with respect
to behavior, yet we may well apply this saying, Know thyself, to
the natural and supernatural understanding of the whole man, so that man
shall not only look at himself and thus remember what his behavior should be
with respect to other people, but also understand his nature, internally and
externally, in the spirit and in nature: whence he comes, of what he is made,
and what he is meant for. From his own points of view Valentin Weigel
has thus arrived at insights which were summed up for him in the oracle of
Apollo.
A similar road to understanding, and the same position with respect to the
Know thyself, can be ascribed to a series of penetrating spirits
beginning with Meister Eckhart (12601327) and ending with Angelus Silesius
(16241677), to which Valentin Weigel also belongs.
What is common to these spirits is a strong feeling that in man's
self-knowledge arises a sun which illuminates something beyond the
incidental individual personality of the beholder. What
Spinoza
realized in
the ethereal height of pure thought, that the human soul has a sufficient
knowledge of the eternal and infinite nature of God, lived in them as
immediate perception; and for them self-knowledge was the path by which this
eternal and infinite nature was to be reached. It was clear to them that
self-knowledge in its true form endows man with a new sense which opens to
him a world that has the same relation to what can be attained without this
sense as does the world of the physically sighted to that of the blind. It
would not be easy to find a better description of the importance of this new
sense than that given by
J. G. Fichte in his Berlin lectures in the year
1813. Imagine a world of people born blind, who therefore know only those
objects and their conditions which exist through the sense of touch. Go
among them and speak to them of colors and of the other conditions which
exist only for sight through the medium of light. Either you will speak to
them of nothing, and it will be better if they say so, for in this way you
will soon notice your mistake, and, if you cannot open their eyes, will put an
end to this fruitless talk. Or for some reason they will want to give a
meaning to your teaching; in this case they will only be able to understand
it through what they know from touch: they will want to feel the light, the
colors, and the other conditions of visibility; they will think that they
feel them, will, within the realm of touch, make up something that they call
color and deceive themselves with it. Then they will misunderstand, turn
things around, and misinterpret. Something similar may be said of that
toward which the spirits under discussion strove. In self-knowledge they saw
the opening up of a new sense. And in their opinion this sense leads to
insights which do not exist for one who does not perceive in self-knowledge
that which differentiates it from all other kinds of knowing. One to whom
this sense has not opened itself thinks that self-knowledge arises in a way
similar to knowledge through external senses, or through some other means
acting from the outside. He thinks, Knowledge is knowledge. However,
in one case its object is something situated in the external world, in the
other case it is in his own soul. He hears only words, at best abstract
thoughts, in what, for those who look deeper, constitutes the basis of their
inner life namely, in the dictum that in all other kinds of knowing the
object is outside of ourselves, while in self-knowledge we stand inside the
object; that every other object comes into contact with us as something
completed and closed, while in our self we actively and creatively weave
what we observe in ourselves. This may appear as an explanation consisting
of mere words, perhaps as a triviality, but if properly understood, it can
also appear as a higher light which illuminates all other knowledge in a new
way. He to whom it appears under the first aspect is in the same situation
as a blind man to whom one says, A brilliant object is there. He hears the
words, but for him brilliance does not exist. One can unite in oneself the
sum of the knowledge of a period; if one does not perceive the significance
of self-knowledge then in the higher sense all knowledge is but blind.
Independent of us, the world lives for us because it communicates itself to
our spirit. What is communicated to us must be expressed in the language
characteristic of us. A book would be meaningless for us if its contents
were to be presented to us in an unknown tongue. In the same way the world
would be meaningless for us if it did not speak to us in our language. The
same language which reaches us from the realm of objects, we also hear in
ourselves. But then it is we who are speaking. It is only a matter of
listening aright to the transformation which occurs when we close our
perception to external objects and listen only to that which then sounds in
ourselves. It is for this that the new sense is necessary. If it is not
awakened we think that in the communications about ourselves we perceive
only communications about an object external to ourselves; we are of the
opinion that there is something hidden somewhere which speaks to us in the
same way as do external objects. If we have the new sense we know that its
perceptions are quite different from those which refer to external objects.
Then we know that this sense does not leave outside of itself that which it
perceives, as the eye leaves outside of itself the object it sees, but that
it can completely incorporate its object within itself. If I see an object,
the object remains outside of me; if I perceive myself, I myself enter into
my perception. One who seeks some part of his self outside what is
perceived, shows that the essential content of what is perceived has not
become apparent to him. Johannes Tauler (13001361) expressed this truth in
the apt words: If I were a king and did not know it, I would not be a king.
If I do not become clear to myself in my self-perception, then I do not
exist for myself. But if I do become clear to myself then in my most
fundamental nature I possess myself in my perception. No part of me remains
outside of my perception.
J. G. Fichte
strongly indicates the difference between self-perception and every other
kind of perception in the following words: It would be easier to get
most people to consider themselves to be a
piece of lava in the moon than a self. He who is not in agreement with
himself about this understands no thoroughgoing philosophy and needs none.
Nature, whose machine he is, will lead him without his doing anything in all
the acts he has to perform. In order to philosophize one needs independence,
and this one can only give to oneself. We should not want to see without
eyes, but we should also not affirm that it is the eye which sees.
The perception of oneself is thus at the same time an awakening of the
self. In our knowing we connect the nature of things with our own nature. The
communications which things make to us in our language become parts of our
own self. A thing which confronts me is no longer separate from me once I
know it. That part of it which I can take in is incorporated into my own
nature. When I awaken my own self, when I perceive what is within me, then I
also awaken to a higher existence what I have incorporated into my nature
from the outside. The light which falls upon me when I awaken, also falls
upon what I have appropriated to myself of the things of the world. A light
flashes in me and illuminates me, and with me everything I know of the
world. Everything I know would remain blind knowledge if this light did not
fall upon it. I could penetrate the whole world with my knowledge; it would
not be what it must become in me if knowledge were not awakened to a higher
existence within me.
What I add to things by this awakening is not a new idea, is not an
enrichment of the content of my knowledge; it is a raising of knowledge, of
cognition, to a higher level, on which everything is endowed with a new
brilliance. As long as I do not raise my cognition to this level, all
knowledge remains worthless to me in the higher sense. Things exist without
me too. They have their being in themselves. What does it mean if with their
existence, which they have outside without me, I connect another spiritual
existence, which repeats things within me? If it were a matter of a mere
repetition of things, it would be senseless to do this. But it is a
matter of a mere repetition only so long as I do not awaken to a higher
existence within my own self the spiritual content of things received into
myself. When this happens, then I have not repeated the nature of things within
me, but have given it a rebirth on a higher level. With the awakening of my self
there takes place a spiritual rebirth of the things of the world. What
things show in this rebirth they did not possess previously. There outside
stands a tree. I take it into my mind. I throw my inner light upon what I
have apprehended. Within me the tree becomes more than it is outside. That
part of it which enters through the portal of the senses is received into a
spiritual content. An ideal counterpart to the tree is in me. This says
infinitely much about the tree, which the tree outside cannot tell me.
What the tree is only shines upon it out of me. Now the tree is no
longer the isolated being which it is in external space. It becomes a part of
the whole spiritual world living within me. It combines its content with other
ideas which exist in me. It becomes a part of the whole world of ideas, which
embraces the vegetable kingdom; it is further integrated into the
evolutionary scale of every living thing. Another example: I throw a
stone in a horizontal direction. It moves in a curved line, and after some time
falls to the ground. In successive moments of time I see it in different
locations. Through reflection I arrive at the following: During its movement
the stone is subject to differing influences. If it were only under the
influence of the impulse I gave to it, it would fly on forever in a straight
line, without any change in its velocity. But the earth also exercises an
influence upon it. It attracts it. If I had simply let it go without giving
it an impulse, it would have fallen vertically to the earth. During the fall
its velocity would have constantly increased. The reciprocal action of these
two influences produces what I actually see. Let us assume that I was not
able to separate the two influences mentally, and to reconstruct mentally
what I see from their combination according to certain laws; matters would
remain at that which is seen. It would be a spiritually blind looking-on, a
perception of the successive positions occupied by the stone. But in fact
matters do not remain at this. The whole process occurs twice. Once
outside, and there my eye sees it; then my mind lets the whole process occur
again, in a mental fashion. My inner sense must be directed upon the mental
process, which my eye does not see, in order for it to realize that with my
own forces I awaken the process in its mental aspect. One can again
adduce a dictum of J. G. Fichte, which makes this fact clearly intelligible.
The new sense is thus the sense for the spirit; that sense for which
only the spirit
exists and nothing else, and for which the other, the given existence, also
assumes the form of the spirit and becomes transformed into it, for which
therefore existence in its own form has actually disappeared . . . This sense
has been used for seeing as long as men have existed, and everything great
and excellent in the world, and which alone makes mankind endure, has its
origin in the visions of this sense. But it was not the case that this sense
saw itself in its difference from and its opposition to the other, ordinary
sense. The impressions of the two senses became fused; life split into these
two halves without a unifying bond. The unifying bond is created by the
fact that the inner sense perceives the spiritual, which it awakens in its
intercourse with the external world, in its spirituality. Because of this,
that part of things which we take up into our spirit ceases to appear as a
meaningless repetition. It appears as something new in opposition to what
external perception can give. The simple process of throwing a stone, and my
perception of it, appear in a higher light when I make clear to myself the
task of my inner sense in this whole matter. In order to combine
intellectually the two influences and their manners of acting, a sum of
mental content is required which I must already have acquired when I
perceive the flying stone. I thus use a mental content already stored within
me upon something which confronts me in the external world. And this process
of the external world is integrated into the pre-existing intellectual
content. In its essence it shows itself to be an expression of this content.
Through a comprehension of my inner sense the relationship of the content of
this sense to the things of the external world thus becomes apparent to me.
Fichte could say that without a comprehension of this sense, for me the
world splits into two halves: into things outside of me, and into images of
these things within me. The two halves become united when the inner sense
understands itself, and therewith realizes what kind of light it sheds
upon things in the process of cognition. And Fichte could also say that this
inner sense sees only spirit. For it sees how the spirit illuminates the
world of the senses by integrating it into the world of the spiritual. The
inner sense lets the external sensory existence arise within it as a
spiritual essence on a higher level. An external thing is completely known
when there is no part of it which has not experienced a spiritual rebirth in
this way. Every external thing is thus integrated with a spiritual content,
which, when it is seized upon by the inner sense, participates in the
destiny of self-knowledge. The spiritual content which belongs to a thing
enters wholly into the world of ideas through the illumination from inside,
just as does our own self. This exposition contains nothing which is
either capable of a logical proof or requires one. It is nothing but a
result of inner experiences. One who denies its purport only shows that he lacks
this inner experience. One cannot dispute with him any more than one disputes
about color with a blind man. It must not however be asserted that this
inner experience is made possible only through the gift possessed by a few
chosen ones. It is a common human quality. Everyone who does not refuse to
do so can enter upon the path to it. This refusal however is frequent
enough. And one always has the feeling when one meets with objections made
in this vein: it is not a matter of people who cannot acquire the inner
experience, but of those who block their access to it by a net of various
logical chimeras. It is almost as if someone who looks through a telescope
sees a new planet, but nevertheless denies its existence because his
calculations have shown him that there can be no planet in that location.
At the same time there exists in most people a definite feeling that with
what the external senses and the analytic intellect perceive, not all of the
nature of things can be given. They then think that the remainder must lie
in the outside world, just as do the objects of external perception
themselves. What they should attain by perceiving again, with the inner sense
and on a higher level, that is, the object which they have perceived and seized
upon with the intellect, they displace into the outside world as something
inaccessible and unknown. They then speak of limits to cognition which prevent
us from attaining the thing in itself. They speak of the unknown
nature of things. That this nature of things becomes
clear when the inner sense lets its light fall upon things, they will not
acknowledge. An especially telling example of the error which lies hidden here
was furnished by the famous Ignorabimus speech of the scientist,
Du Bois-Reymond,
in the year 1876. Everywhere we should go only so far as to
see manifestations of matter in the processes of nature. Of what
matter itself is, we are not to know anything. Du Bois-Reymond
asserts that we shall never be able to penetrate to the point where matter
haunts space. But the reason we cannot penetrate to this point lies in the fact
that nothing whatsoever can be found there. One who speaks like Du Bois-Reymond
has a feeling that the understanding of nature gives results which point to
something else, which this understanding itself cannot give. But he does not
want to enter upon the path which leads to this something else, namely the
path of inner experience. Therefore he is helpless when confronted by the
question of matter, as by a dark mystery. In the one who enters
upon the path of inner experience things come to a rebirth; and what in them
remains unknown to external experience then becomes clear.
Thus the inner life of man not only elucidates itself, but also external
things. From this point an infinite perspective for human cognition opens
up. Within glows a light which does not confine its luminosity to this
interior. It is a sun which illuminates all reality at once. Something
appears in us which unites us with the whole world. We are no longer merely
the single accidental man, no longer this or that individual. In us the
whole world reveals itself. To us it discloses its own interconnection, and
it shows us how we ourselves as individuals are connected with it. Out of
self-knowledge is born knowledge of the world. And our own limited
individuality takes its place spiritually in the great interconnection of
the world because something comes to life in it which reaches beyond this
individuality, which embraces everything of which this individuality is a
part.
Thinking which with logical prejudices does not block its way to inner
experience will at last always reach a recognition of the essential nature
working within us, which connects us with the whole world, because through
it we overcome the contrast of inner and outer where man is concerned.
Paul Asmus,
the prematurely deceased, clearsighted philosopher, comments on this
state of affairs in the following way
(cf. his work: Das Ich und das Ding an sich,
The Self and the Thing in Itself, p. 14f.): We shall make this
clearer to ourselves by means of an example. Let us imagine a piece of
sugar; it is round, sweet, impenetrable, etc.; all these are qualities we
understand; there is only one thing in all this that appears to us as
something absolutely different, that we do not understand, that is so
different from us that we cannot penetrate into it without losing ourselves,
from the mere surface of which our thought timidly recoils. This one thing
is the bearer of all these qualities, and is unknown to us; it is the very
essence which constitutes the innermost self of this object. Thus Hegel says
correctly that the whole content of our idea is only related to this dark
subject as an accident, and that we only attach qualifications to this
essence without penetrating to its depths, qualifications which finally,
since we do not know it itself, have no truly objective value, are
subjective. Comprehending thinking, on the other hand, has no such
unknowable subject in which its qualifications are only accidents, rather
the objective subject falls within the concept. If I comprehend something,
it is present in my concept in its totality; I am at home in the innermost
sanctuary of its nature, not because it has no essence of its own, but because
it compels me, through the necessity, poised over both of us, of the
concept, which appears subjectively in me, objectively in it, to re-think
its concept. Through this re-thinking there is revealed to us, as Hegel
says, just as this is our subjective activity, at the same
time the true nature of the object. Only he can speak in this
way who is able to illuminate the processes of thought with the light of inner
experience.
In my
Philosophie der Freiheit,
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity,
departing
from different points of view, I also have pointed to the primordial fact of
the inner life: There is thus no doubt: in thinking we hold the universal
processes by a corner where we have to be present if they are to take place
at all. And it is just this which is important. This is just the reason why
things confront me in such a mysterious fashion, that I am so unconcerned
with the process of their becoming. I simply come upon them, but in thinking
I know how it is done. Therefore there is no more primordial point of
departure for the contemplation of the universal processes than thinking.
To the one who regards the inner experience of man in this way the meaning
of human cognition within the whole universal process is also clear. It is
not an unimportant addition to the rest of the universal process. This is
what it would be if it represented only a repetition, in the form of ideas, of
what exists externally. But in understanding occurs what does not occur
anywhere in the external world: the universal process confronts itself with
its own spiritual nature. This universal process would be forever incomplete
if this confrontation did not take place. With it the inner experience of
man becomes integrated into the objective universal process; the latter
would be incomplete without it.
It can be seen that only that life which is dominated by the inner sense,
man's highest spiritual life in the truest sense, thus raises him above
himself. For it is only in this life that the nature of things is revealed
in confrontation with itself. Matters are different with the lower faculty
of perception. The eye for instance, which mediates the sight of an object,
is the scene of a process which, in relation to the inner life, is
completely similar to any other external process. My organs are parts of the
spatial world like other things, and their perceptions are temporal
processes like others. Their nature too only becomes apparent when they are
submerged in the inner experience. I thus live a double life: the life of a
thing among other things, which lives within its corporeality and through
its organs perceives what lies outside this corporeality, and above this
life a higher one, which knows no such inside and outside, and extends over
both the external world and itself. I shall therefore have to say: At one
time I am an individual, a limited I; at the other time I am a general,
universal I. This too Paul Asmus has put into apt words (cf. his book: Die
indogermanischen Religionen in den Hauptpunkten ihrer Entwicklung, The
Indo-European Religions in the Main Points of their Development, p. 29 of the
first volume): We call the activity of submerging ourselves in something
else, thinking; in thinking the I has fulfilled its concept, it
has given up its existence as something separate; therefore in thinking we
find ourselves in a sphere that is the same for all, for the principle of
isolation, which lies in the relationship of our I to what is different from
it, has disappeared in the activity of the self-suspension of the separate
I; there is only the selfhood common to all.
Spinoza has exactly the same thing in mind when he describes the highest
activity of cognition as that which advances from the sufficient
conception of the real nature of some attributes of God to the sufficient
cognition of the nature of things. This advance is nothing other than
illumination of things with the light of inner experience. Spinoza describes
the life of this inner experience in glorious colors: The highest
virtue of the soul is to apprehend God,
or to comprehend things in the third the highest kind of
cognition. This virtue becomes the greater the more the soul comprehends
things in this way of cognition; therefore the one who grasps things in this
way of cognition attains the highest human perfection and consequently
becomes filled with the highest joy, accompanied by the conceptions of
himself and of virtue. Hence from this kind of cognition springs the highest
possible peace of soul. One who comprehends things in this way transforms
himself within himself; for at such moments his separate I is absorbed by
the All-I; all beings do not appear in subordination to a separate, limited
individual; they appear to themselves. At this level there is no longer any
difference between
Plato
and me; what separates us belongs to a lower level
of cognition. We are only separate as individuals; the universal which acts
in us is one and the same. About this fact also one cannot dispute with one
who has no experience of it. He will always insist: Plato and you are two.
That this duality, that all multiplicity is reborn as unity in the unfolding
of the highest level of cognition, cannot be proved:
it must be experienced.
Paradoxical as it may sound, it is true: the idea which Plato represented to
himself and the same idea which I represent to myself are not two ideas.
They are one and the same idea. And there are not two ideas, one in Plato's
head, the other in mine; rather in the higher sense Plato's head and mine
interpenetrate; all heads which grasp the same, single idea,
interpenetrate; and this unique idea exists only once. It is there, and the
heads all transport themselves to one and the same place in order to contain
this idea.
The transformation which is effected in the whole nature of man when he looks
at things in this way is indicated in beautiful words in the Indian poem,
The Bhagavad Gita, of which Wilhelm von Humboldt therefore said that
he was grateful to his destiny for having permitted him to live until he
could be in a position to become acquainted with this work. The inner light
says in this poem, An external ray from me, who has attained to a special
existence in the world of personal life, attracts to itself the five senses and
the individual soul, which belong to nature. When the effulgent spirit
materializes in space and time, or when it dematerializes, it seizes upon
things and carries them along with itself, as the breath of the wind seizes
upon the perfumes of flowers and sweeps them away with itself. The inner
light dominates the ear, the touch, the taste, and the smell, as well as the
mind; it forms a bond between itself and the things of the senses. Fools
do not know when the inner light flames up and when it is extinguished, or when
it unites with things; only he who partakes of the inner light can know of
this. So strongly does The Bhagavad Gita point to the
transformation of man that it says of the sage that he can no
longer err, no longer sin. If he
seems to err or sin he must illuminate his thoughts or his actions with a
light in which that no longer appears as error and as sin which appears as
such to the ordinary consciousness. He who has raised himself and whose
knowledge is of the purest kind does not kill and does not defile himself,
even though he should slay another. This only indicates the same basic
disposition of the soul, springing from the highest cognition, concerning
which Spinoza, after describing it in his Ethics, breaks into the
thrilling words: With this I have concluded what I wanted to set forth
concerning the
power of the soul over the affections and over the freedom of the soul. From
this it appears how superior is a wise man to an ignorant one, and how much
more powerful than one who is merely driven by passions. For the ignorant
man is not only driven in many directions by external causes and never
attains to true peace of soul, but he also lives in ignorance of himself, of
God, and of objects, and when his suffering comes to an end, his existence
also comes to an end; while the wise man, as such, hardly experiences any
agitation in his spirit, but rather never ceases to exist in the as it were
necessary knowledge of himself, of God, and of objects, and always enjoys
true peace of soul. Although the path I have described as leading to this
appears very difficult, it can be found nevertheless. And it may well be
troublesome, since it is found so seldom. For how is it possible that, if
salvation were close at hand and to be found without great effort, it is
neglected by almost everyone? But everything sublime is as difficult as it
is rare.
Goethe
has adumbrated the point of view of the highest cognition in monumental
fashion in the words: If I know my relationship to myself and
to the external world, I call it truth. And thus everyone can have his own
truth, and it is still always the same truth. Everyone has his own truth,
because everyone is an individual, distinct being beside and together with
others. These other beings act upon him through his organs. From the
individual point of view, where he is placed, and according to the nature of
his faculty of perception, he forms his own truth in intercourse with
things. He achieves his relationship to things. Then when he enters into
self-knowledge, when he comes to know his relationship to himself, his
particular truth becomes dissolved in the general truth; this general truth
is the same in everyone.
The understanding of the suspension of what is individual in the
personality, of the I in favor of the all-I, is regarded by deeper natures
as the secret revealing itself within man, as the primordial mystery of
life. For this too Goethe has found an apt expression: And as long as you
do not have it, this Die and Become, you are only a dreary guest on the dark
earth.
What takes place in the inner life of man is not a mental repetition, but a
real part of the universal process. The world would not be what it is if it
were not active in the human soul. And if one calls the highest which is
attainable by man the divine, then one must say that the divine does not exist
as something external to be repeated as an image in the human spirit,
but that the divine is awakened in man. For this Angelus Silesius has
found the right words: I know that without me God cannot live for
a moment; if I come to naught He must needs give up the ghost. God
cannot make a single worm without me; if I do not preserve it with Him, it must
fall apart forthwith. Such an assertion can only be made by one who
premises that something appears in man without which an external being cannot
exist. If everything which belongs to the worm also existed without
man, it would be impossible to say that the worm must fall apart
if man does not preserve it.
In self-knowledge the innermost core of the world comes to life as spiritual
content. For man, the experiencing of self-knowledge means an acting within
the core of the world. One who is penetrated by self-knowledge naturally
also performs his own actions in the light of self-knowledge. In general,
human action is determined by motives.
Robert Hamerling,
the poet-philosopher, has rightly said (Atomistik des Willens,
Atomism of the Will, p. 213f.): It is true that man can do what he
wills, but he cannot will what he wills, because his will is determined by
motives. He cannot
will what he wills. Let us examine these words more closely. Do they contain
a rational meaning? Would freedom of willing then consist in being able to
will something without cause, without motive? But what does willing mean if
not to have a cause
for preferring to do or to aspire to this rather than
that? To will something without cause, without motive, would mean to will
something without willing it.
The concept of motive is inseparably connected
with that of willing. Without a definite motive the will is an empty
capacity;
only through the motive does it become active and real. It is thus
quite correct that the human will is not free insofar as its direction is
always determined by the strongest motive. For every action which does not
take place in the light of self-knowledge the motive, the cause of the
action must be felt as a compulsion. Matters are different when the cause is
included within the bounds of self-knowledge. Then this cause has become a
part of the self. The will is no longer determined; it determines itself.
The conformity to laws, the motives of willing, now no longer predominate
over the one who wills; they are one and the same with this willing. To
illuminate one's actions with the light of self-observation means to
overcome all coercion by motives. Thereby the will places itself into the
realm of freedom.
Not all human actions bear the character of freedom. Only that acting which
is inspired in each one of its parts by self-observation is free. And
because self-observation raises the individual I to the general I, free
acting is that which proceeds from the all-I. The old issue of whether the
will of man is free or subordinated to a general regularity, an unalterable
necessity, is an improperly posed question. Those actions which are
performed by man as an individual are unfree; those are free which he
performs after his spiritual rebirth. Man is thus, in general, not
either
free or unfree. He is the one as well as the other.
He is unfree before his
rebirth, and he can become free through this rebirth.
The individual upward
development of man consists in the transformation
of this unfree willing
into one which bears the character of freedom. The man who has penetrated
the regularity of his actions as being his own, has overcome the compulsion
of this regularity, and therewith his unfreedom. Freedom is not a fact of
human existence from the first, but rather a goal.
With free acting man resolves a contradiction between the world and himself.
His own deeds become deeds of the universal existence. He feels himself to
be in full harmony with this universal existence. Each dissonance between
himself and another he feels to be the result of a not yet fully awakened
self. But the destiny of the self is that only in its separation from the
universe can it find contact with this universe. Man would not be man if as
an I he were not separated from everything else; but he would not be man in
the highest sense if, as such a separated I, he did not enlarge himself out
of himself to the all-I. Above all, it is characteristic of human nature
that it should overcome a contradiction which originally lies within it.
The one who will allow spirit to be only the logical intellect may feel his
blood run cold at the thought that things should experience their rebirth in
the spirit. He will compare the fresh, living flower outside, in the
fullness of its colors, with the cold, pale, schematic thought of the
flower. He will feel especially uncomfortable at the idea that the man who
takes his motives for acting out of the solitude of his self-knowledge
should be freer than the spontaneous, naïve personality which acts out of
its immediate impulses, out of the fullness of its nature. To such a man,
who sees only the one-sided logical aspect, one who submerges himself within
himself will appear as a walking schema of concepts, as a phantom, in
contrast to one who remains in his natural individuality. One hears such
objections to the rebirth of things in the spirit especially among those who
are, it is true, equipped with healthy organs for sensory perception and
with lively drives and passions, but whose faculty of observation fails when
confronted with objects of a purely spiritual content. As soon as they are
expected to perceive something purely spiritual, their perception is
wanting; they are dealing with the mere shells of concepts, if not indeed
with empty words. Therefore, when it is a matter of spiritual content, they
remain the dry, abstract men of intellect. But for one who has a gift of
observation in the purely spiritual like that in the sensory realm, life
naturally does not become poorer when he enriches it with spiritual content.
I look at a flower; why should its rich colors lose even the smallest part
of their freshness if it is not only my eye which sees the colors, but
also
my inner sense which sees the spiritual nature of the flower as well. Why
should the life of my personality become poorer if I do not follow my
passions and impulses in spiritual blindness, but rather irradiate them with
the light of a higher knowledge. Not poorer, but fuller, richer is the life
reflected in spirit.