Preface to the First Edition
(Slightly condensed in translation.)
In publishing a work of this kind at the present time one must be
resigned from the outset to every kind of criticism. A reader, for
example, versed in the accepted theories, can be heard commenting on
the way scientific themes have here been treated: It is amazing
that such absurdities can be put forward in our time. The author
betrays utter ignorance of the most elementary notions. He writes of
heat and warmth as though untouched by the
whole trend of modern Physics. Such vagaries do not even deserve to be
called amateurish. Ore in this vein can be imagined: One
need only read a few pages to discard the book according to
one's temperament, with a smile or with indignation shelving it
with other literary curiosities such as turn up from time to
time.
What then will the author say to these damning criticisms? Will he
not, from his own standpoint, have to regard his critics as without
discernment or even lacking the good will for an intelligent judgment?
The answer is, No not necessarily. He is well aware that those
who condemn his work will often be men of high intelligence, competent
scientists and anxious to judge fairly. Knowing well the reasons for
these adverse judgments, he can put himself in the critic's place. He
must here be permitted a few personal observations which would be out
of place save in so far as they relate to his resolve to write the
book at all. For it would have no raison de'etre if merely
personal and subjective. The contents of this book must be accessible
to every human mind; also the manner of presentation should as
far as possible be free of personal coloring. The following remarks on
the author's life and work are therefore only meant to show how he
could come to write this book while understanding only too well the
apparent grounds of adverse judgment. Even these remarks would be
superfluous if it were possible to show in detail that the contents
are after all in harmony with the known facts of science. But this
would need several volumes, far more than can be done under present
circumstances.
The author would certainly never have ventured to publish what is here
said about heat or warmth, for example, if he
were not conversant with the commonly accepted view. In this student
days, some thirty years ago, he made a thorough study of Physics.
Concerning the phenomena of heat, the so-called Mechanical
Theory of Heat was in the forefront at that time, and this
engaged his keen attention he studied the historical development of
all such explanations and lines of thought associated with such names
as J. R. Mayer, Helmholtz, Clausius and Joule. This has enabled him
also to keep abreast of subsequent developments. If he were not in
this position, he would not have felt justified in writing about
warmth or heat as in this book. For he has made it his principle only
to speak or write of any subject from the aspect of spiritual science
where he would also be qualified to give an adequate account of the
accepted scientific knowledge. He does not mean that every writer
should be subject to the same restriction. A man may naturally feel
impelled to communicate what he arrives at by his own judgment and
feeling for the truth, even if ignorant of what contemporary science
has to say. But for his own part the author is resolved to adhere to
the principle above-mentioned. Thus he would never have written the
few sentences this book contains about the human glandular and nervous
systems were he not also in a position to describe them in
contemporary scientific terms.
Therefore however plausible the verdict that to speak of heat or
warmth as in this book argues an utter ignorance of Physics, the fact
is that the author feels justified in writing as he has done precisely
because he has kept abreast of present-day research and would refrain
from writing if he had not. No doubt this too may be mistaken for lack
of scientific modesty. Yet it must be avowed, if only to forestall
even worse misunderstandings.
Equally devastating criticisms might easily be voiced from a
philosophic standpoint. One can imagine such a reader's question:
Has the author been asleep to all the work that has been and is
still being done in fundamental theory of knowledge? Has he never even
heard of Kant, who proved how inadmissible it is to make such
statements as are here contained? … To a trained mind this
uncritical and amateurish stuff is quite intolerable a sheer
waste of time.
Here once again and at the risk of fresh misunderstanding, the author
has to introduce a more personal note. He began studying Kant at the
age of sixteen, and believes himself to be up-to-date also in this
respect qualified to judge from a Kantian standpoint what is
put forward in this volume. Here too, he would have had good reason to
leave the book unwritten were he not fully aware that the Kantian
boundaries of knowledge are here overstepped. One can be equally well
aware that Herbart would have found in it a naïve realism
of which the concepts had not been properly worked-over; or that the
pragmatic school of William James, Schiller and others would judge it
to be trespassing beyond the bounds of those genuine conceptions which
man is really able to assimilate, to make effective and to verify in
action.1
In spite of all this nay even because of it one could
feel justified in writing the book. The author himself has written
critically and historically of these and other trends of thought in
his philosophic work: The Theory of Knowledge implicit in Goethe's
World-Conception, Truth and Science, The Philosophy of Spiritual
Activity, Goethe's Conception of the World, Nineteenth-Century
Philosophic Views of Life and of the World, Riddles of Philosophy.
Other criticisms are imaginable. A reader of the author's earlier
writings for example his work on nineteenth century
philosophies or his short essay on Haeckel and his Opponents
might well be saying: How can one and the same man be the
author of these works and of the book Theosophy (published in
1904) or of the present volume? How can he take up the cudgels for
Haeckel and then offend so grossly against the straightforward monism,
the philosophic outcome of Haeckel's researches? One could well
understand the writer of this Occult Science attacking all that
Haeckel stood for; that he defended him and even dedicated to him one
of his
main works2
appears preposterously
inconsistent. Haeckel would have declined the dedication in no
uncertain terms, had he known that the same author would one day
produce the unwieldy dualism of the present work.
Yet in the author's view one can appreciate Haeckel without having to
stigmatize as nonsense whatever is not the direct outcome of his range
of thought and his assumptions. We do justice to Haeckel by entering
into the spirit of his scientific work, not by attacking him as
has been done with every weapon that comes to hand. Least of
all does the author hold any brief for those of Haeckel's adversaries
against whom he defended the great naturalist in his essay on
Haeckel and his Opponents. If then he goes beyond Haeckel's
assumptions and placed the spiritual view side by side with Haeckel's
purely naturalistic view of the Universe, this surely does not rank
him with Haeckel's opponents. Anyone who takes sufficient trouble will
perceive that there is no insuperable contradiction between the
author's present work and his former writings.
The author can also put himself in the place of the kind of critic who
without more ado will discard the whole book as an outpouring of wild
fancy. This attitude is answered in the book itself, where it is
pointed out that reasoned thinking can and must be the touchstone of
all that is here presented. Only those who will apply to the contents
of this book the test of reason even as they would to a
description of natural-scientific facts will be in a position
to decide.
A word may also be addressed to those already predisposed to give the
book a sympathetic hearing. (They will find most of what is relevant
in the introductory chapter.) Although the book concerns researches
beyond the reach of the sense-bound intellect, nothing is here
presented which cannot be grasped with open-minded thought and with
the healthy feeling for the truth possessed by everyone who will apply
these gifts of human nature. The author frankly confesses: he would
like readers who will not accept what is here presented on blind
faith, but rather put it to the
test of their own insight and experience of life.3
He desires careful readers readers who will
allow only what is sound and reasonable. This book would not be valid
if relaying on blind faith; it is of value only inasmuch as it can
pass the test of open-minded thinking. Credulity too easily mistakes
folly and superstition for the truth. People who are content with
vague belief in the supersensible may criticize this book for its
excessive appeal to the lift of thought. But in these matters the
scrupulous and conscientious form of presentation is no less essential
than the substance. In the field of Occult Science irresponsible
charlatanism and the highest truths, genuine knowledge and mere
superstition are often separated by a thin dividing line, and it is
all too easy to mistake the one for the other.
Readers already conversant with supersensible realities will no doubt
recognize the author's care to keep within the bounds of what can and
should be communicated at the present time. They will be well aware
that there are aspects of supersensible knowledge for which a
different form of communication is required, if not a later period of
time should be awaited.
Footnotes:
- Even in the more recent schools Bergson, the As
If philosophy, and the Critique of Language
have been studied and appraised in this connection.
- Nineteenth-century Philosophic Views of Life and
of the World (published in 1900)
- This does not only refer to the spiritual test of
supersensible research, but to the test unquestionably valid
of open-minded thought, the test of healthy human intelligence
and reflection.