Stuttgart, March 4th, 1920.
You will perhaps have noticed that in our considerations here, we are
striving for a certain particular goal. We are trying to place
together a series of phenomena taken from the realm of heat in such a
manner that the real nature of warmth may be obvious to us from these
phenomena. We have become acquainted in a general way with certain
relations that meet us from within the realm of heat, and we have in
particular observed the relation of this realm of the expansionability
of bodies. We have followed this with an attempt to picture to
ourselves mentally the nature of form in solid bodies, fluids and
gaseous bodies. I have also spoken of the relation of heat to the
changes produced in bodies in going from the solid to the fluid and
from the fluid to the gaseous or vaporous condition. Now I wish to
bring before you certain relations which come up when we have to do
with gases or vapors. We already know that these are so connected with
heat that by means of this we bring about the gaseous condition, and
again, by appropriate change of temperature that we can obtain a
liquid from a gas. Now you know that when we have a solid body, we
cannot by any means interpenetrate this solid with another. The
observation of such simple elementary relations is of enormous
importance if we really wish to force our way through to the nature of
heat. The experiment I will carry out here will show that water vapor
produced here in this vessel passes through into this second vessel.
And now having filled the second vessel with water vapor, we will
produce in the first vessel another vapor whose formation you can
follow by reason of the fact that it is colored. (The experiment was
carried out.) You see that in spite of our having filled the vessel
with water vapor, the other vapor goes into the space filled with the
water vapor. That is, a gas does not prevent another gas from
penetrating the space it occupies. We may make this clear to ourselves
by saying that gaseous or vaporous bodies may to a certain extent
interpenetrate each other.
I will now show you another phenomenon which will illustrate one more
relation of heat to certain facts. We have here in the left hand tube,
air which is in equilibrium with the outer air with which we are
always surrounded. I must remind you that this outer air surrounding
us is always under a certain pressure, the usual atmospheric pressure,
and it exerts this pressure on us. Thus, we can say that air inside
the left hand tube is under the same pressure as the outer air itself,
which fact is shown by the similar level of mercury in the right and
left hand tubes. You can see that on both right and left hand sides
the mercury column is at the same height, and that since here on the
right the tube is open to the atmosphere the air in the closed tube is
at atmospheric pressure. We will now alter the conditions by bringing
pressure on the air in the left hand tube,
(2 × p).
By doing this we
have added to the usual atmospheric pressure, the pressure due to the
higher mercury column. That is, we have simply added the weight of the
mercury from here to here.
(Fig. 1b
from a to b). By thus increasing
the pressure exerted on this air by the pressure corresponding to the
weight of the mercury column, the volume of the air in the left hand
tube is, as you can see, made smaller. We can therefore say when we
increase the pressure on the gas its volume decreases. We must extend
this and consider it a general phenomenon that the space occupied by a
gas and the pressure exerted on it have an inverse ratio to each
other. The greater the pressure the smaller the volume, and the
greater the volume the smaller must be the pressure acting on the gas.
We can express this in the form of an equation where the volume
V1
divided by the volume
V2
equals the pressure
P2
divided by the pressure
P1.
This expresses a relatively general law (we have to say relative and
will see why later.) This may be stated as follows: volume and
pressure of gases are so related that the volume-pressure product is a
constant at constant temperature. As we have said, such phenomena as
these must be placed side by side if we are to approach the nature of
heat. And now, since our considerations are to be thought of as a
basis for pedagogy we must consider the matter from two aspects. On
the one hand, we must build up a knowledge of the method of thinking
of modern physics and on the other, we must become acquainted with
what must happen if we are to throw aside certain obstacles that
modern physics places in the path to a real understanding of the
nature of heat.
Please picture vividly to ourselves that when we consider the nature
of heat we are necessarily dealing at the same time with volume
increases, that is with changes in space and with alterations of
pressure. In other words, mechanical facts meet us in our
consideration of heat. I have to speak repeatedly in detail of these
things although it is not customary to do this. Space changes,
pressure changes. Mechanical facts meet us.
Now for physics, these facts that meet us when we consider heat are
purely and simply mechanical facts. These mechanical occurrences are,
as it were, the milieu in which heat is observed. The being of heat is
left, so to speak, in the realm of the unknown and attention is
focused on the mechanical phenomena which play themselves out under
its influence. Since the perception of heat is alleged to be purely a
subjective thing, the expansion of mercury, say, accompanying change
of heat condition and of sensation of heat, is considered as something
belonging in the realm of the mechanical. The dependence of gas
pressure, for instance, on the temperature, which we will consider
further, is thought of as essentially mechanical and the being of heat
is left out of consideration. We saw yesterday that there is a good
reason for this. For we saw that when we attempt to calculate heat,
difficulties arise in the usual calculations and that we cannot, for
example, handle the third power of the temperature in the same way as
the third power of an ordinary quantity in space. And since modern
physics has not appreciated the importance of the higher powers of the
temperature, it has simply stricken them out of the expansion formulae
I mentioned to you in former lectures.
Now you need only consider the following. You need consider only that
in the sphere of outer nature heat always appears in external
mechanical phenomena, primarily in space phenomena. Space phenomena
are there to begin with and in them the heat appears. This it is, my
dear friends, that constrains us to think of heat as we do of lines in
space and that leads us to proceed from the first power of extension
in space to the second power of the extension.
When we observe the first power of the extension, the line, and we
wish to go over to the second power, we have to go out of the line.
That is, we must add a second dimension to the first. The standard of
measurement of the second power has to be thought of as entirely
different from that of the first power. We have to proceed in an
entirely similar fashion when we consider a temperature condition. The
first power is, so to speak, present in the expansion. Change of
temperature and expansion are so related that they may be expressed by
rectilinear coordination
(Fig. 2).
I am obliged, when I wish to make
the graph representing change in expansion with change in temperature,
to add the axis of abscissae to the axis of ordinates. But this makes
it necessary to consider what is appearing as temperature not as a
first power but as a second power, and the second power as a third.
When we deal with the third power of the temperature, we can no longer
stay in our ordinary space. A simple consideration, dealing it is true
with rather subtle distinctions, will show you that in dealing with
the heat manifesting itself as the third power, we cannot limit
ourselves to the three directions of space. It will show you how, the
moment we deal with the third power, we are obliged, so far as heat
effects are concerned, to go out of space.
In order to explain the phenomena, modern physics sets itself the
problem of doing so and remaining within the three dimensional space.
You see, here we have an important point where physical science has to
cross a kind of Rubicon to a higher view of the world. And one is
obliged to emphasize the fact that since so little attempt is made to
attain clarity at this point, a corresponding lack enters into the
comprehensive world view.
Imagine to yourselves that physicists would so present these matters
to their students as to show that one must leave ordinary space in
which mechanical phenomena play when heat phenomena are to be
observed. In such a case, these teachers of physics would call forth
in their students, who are intelligent people since they find
themselves able to study the subject, the idea that a person cannot
really know it without leaving the three dimensional space. Then it
would be much easier to place a higher world-view before people. For
people in general, even if they were not students of physics, would
say, We cannot form a judgment on the matter, but those who have
studied know that the human being must rise through the physics of
space to other relations than the purely spatial relations.
Therefore so much depends on our getting into this science such ideas
as those put forth in our considerations here. Then what is
investigated would have an effect on a spiritually founded world view
among people in general quite different from what it has now. The
physicist announces that he explains all phenomena by means of purely
mechanical facts. This causes people to say, Well, there are
only mechanical facts in space. Life must be a mechanical thing, soul
phenomena must be mechanical and spiritual things must be
mechanical. Exact sciences will not admit the
possibility of a spiritual foundation for the world. And exact
science works as an especially powerful authority because they
are not familiar with it. What people know, they pass their own
judgment on and do not permit it to exercise such an authority. What
they do not know they accept on authority. If more were done to
popularize the so-called rigidly exact science, the
authority of some of those who sit entrenched in possession of this
exact science would practically disappear.
During the course of the 19th century there was added to
the facts that we have already observed, another one of which I have
spoken briefly. This is that mechanical phenomena not only appear in
connection with the phenomena of heat, but that heat can be
transformed into mechanical phenomena. This process you see in the
ordinary steam locomotive where heat is applied and forward motion
results. Also mechanical processes, friction and the like, can be
transformed back again into heat since the mechanical processes, as it
is said, bring about the appearance of heat. Thus mechanical processes
and heat processes may be mutually transformed into each other.
We will sketch the matter today in a preliminary fashion and go into
the details pertaining to this realm in subsequent lectures.
Further, it has been found that not only heat but electrical and
chemical processes may be changed into mechanical processes And from
this has been developed what has been called during the
19th century the mechanical theory of heat.
This mechanical theory of heat has as its principal postulate that
heat and mechanical effects are mutually convertible one into the
other. Now suppose we consider this idea somewhat closely. I am unable
to avoid for you the consideration of these elementary things of the
realm of physics. If we pass by the elementary things in our basic
consideration, we will have to give up attaining any clarity in this
realm of heat. We must therefore ask the questions: what does it
really mean then when I say: Heat as it is applied in the steam engine
shows itself as motion, as mechanical work? What does it mean when I
draw from this idea: through heat, mechanical work is produced in the
external world? Let us distinguish clearly between what we can
establish as fact and the ideas which we add to these facts. We can
establish the fact that a process subsequently is revealed as
mechanical work, or shows itself as a mechanical process. Then the
conclusion is drawn that the heat process, the heat as such, has been
changed into a mechanical thing, into work.
Well now, my dear friends, if I come into this room and find the
temperature such that I am comfortable, I may think to myself, perhaps
unconsciously without saying it in words: In this room it is
comfortable. I sit down at the desk and write something. Then
following the same course of reasoning as has given rise to the
mechanical theory of heat, I would say: I came into the room, the heat
condition worked on me and what I wrote down is a consequence of this
heat condition. Speaking in a certain sense I might say that if I had
found the place cold like a cellar, I would have hurried out and would
not have done this work of writing. If now I add to the above the
conclusion that the heat conducted to me has been changed into the
work I did, then obviously something has been left out of my thinking.
I have left out all that which can only take place through myself. If
I am to comprehend the whole reality I must insert into my judgment of
it this which I have left out. The question now arises: When the
corresponding conclusion is drawn in the realm of heat, by assuming
that the motion of the locomotive is simply the transformed heat from
the boiler, have I not fallen into the error noted above? That is,
have I not committed the same fallacy as when I speak of a
transformation of heat into an effect which can only take place
because I myself am part of the picture? It may appear to be trivial
to direct attention to such a thing as this, but it is just these
trivialities that have been completely forgotten in the entire
mechanical theory of heat. What is more, enormously important things
depend on this. Two things are bound together here. First, when we
pass over from the mechanical realm into the realm where heat is
active we really have to leave three dimensional space, and then we
have to consider that when external nature is observed, we simply do
not have that which is interpolated in the case, where heat is changed
over into my writing. When heat is changed into my writing, I can note
from observation of my external bodily nature that something has been
interpolated in the process. Suppose however, that I simply consider
the fact that I must leave three dimensional space in order to relate
the transformation of heat into mechanical effects. Then I can say,
perhaps the most important factor involved in this change plays its
part outside of three dimensional space. In the example that concerned
myself which I gave you, the manner in which I entered into the
process took place outside of three dimensions. And when I speak of
simple transformation of heat into work I am guilty of the same
superficiality as when I consider transformation of heat into a piece
of written work and leave myself out.
This, however, leads to a very weighty consequence. For it requires me
to consider in external nature even lifeless inorganic nature, a being
not manifested in three dimensional space. This being, as it were,
rules behind the three dimensions. Now this is very fundamental in
relation to our studies of heat itself.
Since we have outlined the fundamentals of our conception of the realm
of heat, we may look back again on something we have already
indicated, namely on man's own relation to heat. We may compare the
perception of heat to perception in other realms. I have already
called attention to the fact that, for instance, when we perceive
light, we note this perception of light to be bound up with a special
organ. This organ is simply inserted into our body and we cannot,
therefore, speak of being related to color and light with our whole
organism, but our relation to it concerns a part of us only. Likewise
with acoustical or sound phenomena, we are related to them with a
portion of our organism, namely the organ of hearing. To the being of
heat we are related through our entire organism. This fact, however,
conditions our relation to the being of heat. We are related to it
with our entire organism. And when we look more closely, when we try,
as it were, to express these facts in terms of human consciousness, we
are obliged to say, We are really ourselves this heat being. In
so far as we are men moving around in space, we are ourselves this
heat being. Imagine the temperature were to be raised a couple
of hundred degrees; at that moment we could no longer be identical
with it, and the same thing applies if you imagine it lowered several
hundred degrees. Thus the heat condition belongs to that in which we
continually live, but do not take up into our consciousness. We
experience it as independent beings, but we do not experience it
consciously. Only when some variation from the normal condition
occurs, does it take conscious form.
Now with this fact a more inclusive one may be connected. It is this.
You may say to yourselves when you contact a warm object and perceive
the heat condition by means of your organism, that you can do it with
the tip of your tongue, with the tip of your finger, you can do it
with other parts of your organism: with the lobes of your ears, let us
say. In fact, you can perceive the heat condition with your entire
organism. But there is something else you can perceive with your
entire organism. You can perceive anything exerting pressure. And here
again, you are not limited strictly as you are in the case of the eye
and color perception to a certain member of your entire organism. If
would be very convenient if our heads, at least, were an exception to
this rule of pressure perception; we would not then be made so
uncomfortable from a rap on the head.
We can say there is an inner kinship between the nature of our
relationship to the outer world perceived as heat and perceived as
pressure. We have today spoken of pressure volume relations. We come
back now to our own organism and find an inner kinship between our
relation to heat and to pressure. Such a fact must be considered as a
groundwork for what will follow.
But there is something else that must be taken into account as a
preliminary to further observations. You know that in the most popular
text books of physiology, a good deal of emphasis is laid on the fact
that we have certain organs within our bodies by means of which we
perceive the usual sense qualities. We have the eye for color, the ear
for sound, the organ of taste for certain chemical processes, etc. We
have spread over our entire organism, as it were, the undifferentiated
heat organ, and the undifferentiated pressure organ.
Now, usually, attention is drawn to the fact that there are certain
other things of which we are aware but for which we have no organs.
Magnetism and electricity are known to us only through their effects
and stand, as it were, outside of us, not immediately perceived. It is
said sometimes that if we imagine our eyes were electrically sensitive
instead of light sensitive, then when we turned them towards a
telegraph wire we would perceive the streaming electricity in it.
Electricity would be known not merely by its effects, but like light
and color, would be immediately perceived. We cannot do this. We must
therefore say: electricity is an example of something for whose
immediate perception we have no organ. There are aspects of nature,
thus, for which we have organs and aspects of nature for which we do
not have organs. So it is said.
The question is whether perhaps a more unbiased observer would not
come to a different conclusion from those whose view is expressed
above. You all know, my dear friends, that what we call our ordinary
passive concepts through which we apprehend the world, are closely
bound up with the impressions received through the eye, the ear and
somewhat less so with taste and smell impressions. If you will simply
consider language, you may draw from it the summation of your
conceptual life, and you will become aware that the words themselves
used to represent our ideas are residues of our sense impressions.
Even when we speak the very abstract word Sein (being), the
derivation is from Ich habe gesehen, (I have seen.) What I have
seen I can speak of as possessing being. In
being there is included what has been seen.
Now without becoming completely materialistic (and we will see later
why it is not necessary to become so), it may be said that our
conceptual world is really a kind of residue of seeing and hearing and
to a lesser extent of smelling and tasting. (Those last two enter less
into our higher sense impressions.) Through the intimate connection
between our consciousness and our sense impressions, this
consciousness is enabled to take up the passive concept world.
But within the soul nature, from another side, comes the will, and you
remember how I have often told you in these anthroposophical lectures
that man is really asleep so far as his will is concerned. He is,
properly considered, awake only in the passive conceptual realm. What
you will, you apprehend, only through these ideas or concepts. You
have the idea. I will raise this glass. Now, in so far as your mental
act contains ideas, it is a residue of sense impressions. You place
before yourself in thought something which belongs entirely in the
realm of the seen, and when you think of it, you have an image of
something seen. Such an immediately derived image you cannot create
from a will process proper, from what happens when you stretch out
your arm and actually grasp the glass with your hand and raise it.
That act is entirely outside of your consciousness. You are not aware
of what happens between your consciousness and the delicate processes
in your arm. Our unconsciousness of it is as complete as our
unconsciousness between falling asleep and waking up. But something
really is there and takes place, and can its existence be denied
simply because it does not enter our consciousness? Those processes
must be intimately bound up with us as human beings, because after
all, it is we who raise the glass. Thus we are led in considering our
human nature from that which is immediately alive in consciousness to
will processes taking place, as it were, outside of consciousness.
(Fig. 3)
Imagine to yourselves that everything above this line is in
the realm of consciousness. What is underneath is in the realm of will
and is outside of consciousness. Starting from this point we proceed
to the outer phenomena of nature and find our eye intimately connected
with color phenomena, something which we can consciously apprehend; we
find our ear intimately connected with sound, as something we can
consciously apprehend. Tasting and smelling are, however, apprehended
in a more dreamlike way. We have here something which is in the realm
of consciousness and yet is intimately bound up with the outer world.
If now, we go to magnetic and electrical phenomena, the entity which
is active in these is withdrawn from us in contrast with those
phenomena of nature which have immediate connection with us through
certain organs. This entity escapes us. Therefore, say the physicists
and physiologists: we have no organ for it; it is cut off from us. It
lies outside us.
(Fig. 3
above) We have realms that we approach when
we draw near the outer world the realms of light and heat. How
do electrical phenomena escape us? We can trace no connection between
them and any of our organs. Within us we have the results of our
working over of light and sound phenomena as residues in the form of
ideas. When, however, we plunge down
(Fig. 3
below), our own being
disappears from us into will.
I will now tell you something a bit paradoxical, but think it over
until tomorrow. Imagine we were not living men, but living rainbows,
and that our consciousness dwelt in the green portion of the spectrum.
On the one side we would trail off into unconsciousness in the yellow
and red and this would escape us inwardly like our will. If we were
rainbows, we would not perceive green, because that we are in our
beings, we do not perceive immediately; we live it. We would touch the
border of the real inner when we tried, as it were, to pass from the
green to the yellow. We would say: I, as a rainbow, approach my red
portion, but cannot take it up as a real inner experience; I approach
my blue-violet, but it escapes me. If we were thinking rainbows, we
would thus live in the green and have on the one side a blue-violet
pole and on the other side a yellow-red pole. Similarly, we now as men
are placed with our consciousness between what escapes us as external
natural phenomena in the form of electricity and as inner phenomena in
the form of will.
Figure 1a
|
Figure 1b
|
Figure 2
Figure 3
|