Lecture I
Stuttgart, January 1, 1921
My dear friends!
To-day I should like to make some
introductory remarks to what I am going to lay before you in
the coming days. My reason for doing this is that you may
know the purpose of these talks from the outset.
It will not
be my task during the following days to deal with any
narrowly defined, special branch of science, but to give
various wider viewpoints, having in mind a quite definite
goal in relation to science. I should therefore like to warn
people not to describe this as an ‘Astronomical
Course’. It is not meant to be that. But it will deal
with something that I feel is especially important for us to
consider at this time. I have therefore given it the title
“The relation of the diverse branches of Natural
Science to Astronomy,” and today in particular I shall
explain what I actually intend with the giving of this
title.
The fact is
that in a comparatively short time much will have to be
changed within what we call the sphere of science, if it is
not to enter upon a complete decline. Certain groups of
sciences which are now comprised under various headings and
are permitted to be represented under these headings, in our
ordinary schools, will have to be taken out their grooves and
be classified from quite other aspects. This will necessitate
a far reaching regrouping of our sciences. The grouping at
present employed is entirely inadequate for a
world-conception based upon reality, and yet our modern world
holds so firmly to such traditional classification that it is
on this basis that candidates are chosen to occupy the
professorial chairs in our Universities. People confine
themselves for the most part to dividing the existing,
circumscribed fields of Natural Science into yet further
special branches, and they then look to the specialists or
experts as they are called. But a change must come into the
whole scientific life by the advent of quite different
categories, within which will be united, as in a whole new
field of science, things that today are dealt with in Zoology
or Physiology, or again, let us say, in the Theory of
Knowledge. The older forms of scientific classification,
often extremely abstract, must die out, and quite new
scientific combinations must arise. This will meet with great
obstacles at first, because people today are trained in the
specialized branches of science and it will be difficult for
them to find an approach to what they will urgently need in
order to bring about a combination of scientific material in
accordance with reality.
To put in
concisely, I might say: We have today a science of astronomy,
of Physics, of Chemistry, of Philosophy, we have a science of
Biology, of Mathematics, and so on. Special branches have
been formed, almost, I might say, so that the various
specialists will not have such hard work in order to become
well grounded in their subject. They do not have too much to
do in mastering all the literature concerned, which, as we
know, exists in immense quantities. But it will be a matter
of creating new branches which will comprise quite different
things, including perhaps at the same time something from
Astronomy, something from Biology, and so on. For this, a
reshaping of our whole life of science will of course be
essential. Therefore, what we term Spiritual Science, which
does indeed aim to be of a universal nature, must work
precisely in this direction. It must make it its special
mission to work in this direction. For we simply cannot get
any further with the old grouping. Our Universities confront
the world today, my dear friends, in a way that is really
quite estranged from life. They turn out mathematicians,
physiologists, philosophers, but none of them have any real
relation to the world. They can do nothing but work in their
narrowly confined spheres, putting before us a picture of the
world that becomes more and more abstract, less and less
realistic.
It
is the change here indicated — a deep
necessity for our time — to which I want to do justice
in these lectures. I should like you to see how impossible it
will be to continue the older classifications indefinitely,
and I therefore want to show how other branches of science of
the most varied kinds, which, in their present way of
treatment, take no account of Astronomy, have indeed definite
connections with Astronomy, that is, with a true knowledge of
universal space. Certain astronomical facts must perforce be
taken into account in other branches of science too, so that
we may learn to master these other fields in a way
conformable to reality.
The
task of these lectures is therefore to
build a bridge from the different fields of scientific
thought to the field of Astronomy, that astronomical
understanding may appear in the right way in the various
fields of science.
In
order not to be misunderstood, I should like to
make one more remark about method. You see, the manner of
presenting scientific facts which is customary nowadays must
undergo considerable change, because it actually arises out
of the scientific structure which has to be overcome. When
today facts are referred to, which lie somewhat remote from
man's understanding, — remote, just because he does not
meet with them at all in his scientific knowledge, — it
is usual to say: “That is stated, but no proved.”
Yet in scientific work is often quite inevitable that
statements must be made at first purely as results of
observation, which only afterwards can be verified as more
and more facts are brought to support them. So it would be
wrong to assume, for instance, that right at the beginning of
a discourse someone could break in and say, “That is
not proved.” It will be proved in the course of time,
but much will first have to be presented simply from
observation, so that the right concept, the right idea, may
be created.
And
so I beg of you to take these lectures as a
whole, and to look in the last lectures for the plain proof
of many things which seem in the first lectures to be mere
statements. Many things will then be verified which I shall
have to handle at first in such a way as to evoke the
necessary concepts and ideas.
Astronomy
as we know it today, even including the
domain of Astrophysics, is fundamentally a modern creation.
Before the time of Copernicus or Galileo men thought about
astronomical phenomena in a way which differed essentially
from the way we think today. It is even extraordinarily
difficult to indicate the way in which man still thought of
Astronomy in, say, the 13th and 14th centuries, because this
way of thinking has become completely foreign to modern man.
We only live in the ideas which have been formed since the
time of Galileo, Kepler, Copernicus; and from a certain point
of view that is perfectly right. They are ideas which treat
of the distant phenomena of universal space, in so far as
they are concerned with Astronomy, in a mathematical and
mechanical way. Men think of these phenomena in terms of
mathematics and mechanics. In observing the phenomena, men
base their ideas upon what they have acquired from an
abstract mathematical science, or an abstract science of
mechanics. They calculate distances, movements and forces.
But the qualitative outlook still in existence in the 13th
and 14th centuries, which distinguished Individualities in
the stars, an Individuality of Jupiter, of Saturn ... this
has become completely lost to modern man. I will make no
criticism of the things at the moment, but will only point
out that the mechanical and mathematical way of treating what
we call the domain of Astronomy has become the exclusive one.
Even if we acquaint ourselves with the stars in a popular
fashion without understanding mathematics or mechanics, we
still find it presented, even if in a manner suitable for the
lay-mind, entirely in ideas of space and time, of a
mathematical and mechanical kind. No doubts of any kind exist
in the minds of our contemporaries — who believe that
their judgment is authoritative — that this is the only
way in which to regard the starry heavens. Anything else,
they are convinced, would be merely amateurish.
Now,
if the question arises as to how it has
actually come about that this view of the starry heavens has
emerged in the evolution of civilization, the answer of those
who regard the modern scientific mode of thought as absolute,
will be different from the reply which we are able to give.
Those who regard the scientific thought of today as something
absolute and true, will say: Well, you know, among earlier
humanity there were not yet any strictly scientifically
formed ideas; man had first to struggle through to such
ideas, i. e., to the mathematical, mechanical mode of
regarding celestial phenomena of the Universe, a later
humanity has worked through to a strictly scientific
comprehension of what does actually correspond to
reality.
This
is an answer that we cannot give, my dear
friends. We must take up our position from the standpoint of
the evolution of humanity, which in the course of its
existence, has introduced various inner forces into its
consciousness. We must say to ourselves: The manner of
observing the celestial phenomena which existed among the
ancient Babylonians, the Egyptians, perhaps even the Indian
people, was due to the particular form which the
development of the human soul-forces was taking in those
times. Those human soul-forces had to be developed with the
same inner necessity with which a child between the 10th and
15th year must develop certain soul-forces, while in another
period it will developing other faculties, which lead it to
different conclusions about the world. Then came the
Ptolemaic system. That arose out of different soul-forces.
Then our Copernican system. That arose from yet other
soul-forces. The Copernican system did not develop because
humanity had happily struggled through to objectivity,
whereas before they had all been as children, but because
humanity since the middle of the 15th century needed
precisely the mathematical, mechanical faculties for its
development. That is why modern man sees the celestial
phenomena in the picture formed by the mathematical,
mechanical faculties. And he will some day see them again in
a different way, when in his development he has drawn up out
of the depths of the soul other forces, — to his own
healing and benefit. Thus it depends upon humanity what
form the world-concept takes. But it is not a question
of looking back in pride to earlier times when men were
“more childlike,” and then thinking that in
modern times we have at last struggled through to an
objective understanding which can now endure for all future
ages.
There
is something which has become a real
necessity to later humanity and has given color to the
requirements of the scientific mind. It is this: Men strive
on the one hand for ideas that are clear and easy to control
— namely, mathematical ideas — , and on the other
hand they strive for ideas through which they can surrender
most strongly to an inner compulsion. The modern man at once
becomes uncertain and nervous when he does not feel the strong
inner compulsion presented, for instance, by the argument of
the Pythagorean theorem, but realizes, let us say, that the
figure which is drawn does not decide for him, but that he
must develop an activity of soul and decide for himself. Then
he at once becomes uncertain and nervous and is no longer
willing to continue the line of thought. So he says: That is
not exact science; subjectivity comes into it. Modern man is
really dreadfully passive; he would like to be led everywhere
by a chain of infallible arguments and conclusions.
Mathematics satisfies this requirement, at least in most
cases; and where it does not, where man have interposed their
own opinion in recent times, — well, my dear friends,
the results are according! Men still believe that they are
being exact, while they hit upon the most incredible
ideas.
Thus
in mathematics and mechanics men think they
are being led forward by leading-strings of concepts which
are linked together through their own inherent logic. They
feel then as if they had ground under their feet, but the
moment they step off it they do not want to go on any
further. Concepts which are easy to grasp on the one hand,
and the element of inner compulsion on the other: this is
what modern man needs for his “safety.”
Fundamentally, it is on this basis that the particular form
of world-conception, supplied by the modern science of
Astronomy, has been built up. I am not at the moment speaking
of the single facts, but merely of the world-conception as a
whole.
This
attitude towards a mathematical, mechanical
conception of the world has so penetrated the consciousness
of humanity, my dear friends, that people have come to regard
everything that cannot be treated in this way as more or less
unscientific. From this feeling proceeded such a phrase as
that of Kant, who said: In every domain of science there is
only so much real science as there is mathematics in
it; one ought really to bring Arithmetic or Geometry into all
the sciences. But this idea, as we know, breaks down when we
think how remote the simplest mathematical ideas are to
those, for instance, who study Medicine. Our present division
of the sciences gives to a medical student practically
nothing in the way of mathematical ideas.
And
so it comes about that on the one hand what is
called astronomical knowledge has been set up as an ideal.
DuBois-Raymond has defined this in his address on the limits
of the knowledge of Nature by saying: We only grasp truths in
Nature and satisfy our need of causality inasmuch as we can
apply the astronomical type of knowledge. That is to say, we
regard the celestial phenomena in such a way that we draw
the stars upon the chart of the sky and calculate with the
material which is there given us. We can state exactly: There
is a star, it exercises a force of attraction upon other
stars. We begin to calculate, having the different things, to
which our calculations apply, visibly before us. This is what
we have brought into Astronomy in the first place. Now we
observe, let us say, the molecule. Within the complex
molecule we have the atoms, exercising a force of attraction
on one another, moving around each other, — forming, as
it were, a little universe. We observe this molecule as a
small cosmic system and are satisfied if it all seems to fit.
But then there is the great difference that when we look out
into the starry sky all the details are given to us. We can
at most ask whether we understand them rightly, whether after
all, there might not be some other explanation than the one
given by Newton. We have the given details and then we spin a
mathematical, mechanical web over them. This web of thought
is actually added to the given facts, but from a scientific
point of view it satisfies the modern need of man. And now we
carry the system, which we have first thought out and
devised, into the world of the molecule and atom. Here we add
in thought what in the other case was given to us. But we
satisfy our so-called need of causality by saying: What we
think of as the smallest particle, moves in such and such a
way, and it is the objective counterpart of what we
experience subjectively as light, sound, warmth etc. We carry
the astronomic form of knowledge into every phenomenon of the
world and thus satisfy our demand for causality. Du-Bois
Raymond has expressed it quite bluntly: “When one
cannot do that, there is no scientific explanation at
all.”
Yes,
my dear friends, what is here claimed should
actually imply that if, for example, we wished to come to a
rational form of therapy, that is to say, to understand the
activity of a remedy, we should have to be able to follow the
atoms in the substance of the remedy as we follow the
movements of the Moon, the Sun, the planets and the fixed
stars. They would all have to become little cosmic systems.
We should have to be able to calculate how this or that
remedy would work. This was actually an ideal for some people
not so very long ago. Now they have given up such ideals.
Such an idea collapses not only in reference to such a far
off sphere as a rational therapy, but in those lying more
within reach, simply because our sciences are divided as they
are today. You see, the modern doctor is educated in such a
way that he masters extraordinarily little of pure
mathematics. We may talk to him perhaps of the need for a
knowledge of astronomy but it would be of no use to speak of
introducing mathematical ideas into his field of work. But as
we have seen, everything outside mathematics, mechanics and
astronomy should be described, according to the modern
notion, as being unscientific in the strict sense of the
word. Naturally that is not done. People regard these other
sciences too as exact, but this is most inconsistent. It is,
however, characteristic of the present time that the demand
should have been made at all for everything to be understood
on the model of mathematical Astronomy.
It
is hard today to talk to people in a serious way
about such thing; how hard this is I should like to make
clear to you by an example.
You
know of course that the question of the form of
the human skull has played a great role in modern biology. I
have also spoken of this matter may times in the course of
our anthroposophical lectures. Goethe and Oken put forward
magnificent thoughts on this question of the human
skull-bones. The school of Gegenbauer also carried out
classical researches upon it. But something that could
satisfy the urge for a deeper knowledge in this direction
does not in fact exist today.
People
discuss, to what extent Goethe was right in
saying that the skull-bones are metamorphosed vertebrae,
bones of the spine. But it is impossible to arrive at any
really penetrating view of this matter today, because in the
circles where these things are discussed one would scarcely
be understood, and where an understanding might be
forthcoming these things are not talked of because they are
not of interest. You see, it is practically impossible today
to bring together in close working association a thoroughly
modern doctor, a thoroughly modern mathematician, —
i.e., one who is master of higher mathematics —, and a
man who could understand both of them passably well. These
three men could scarcely understand one another. The one who
would sit in the middle, understanding both of them slightly,
would be able at a pinch to talk a little with the
mathematician and also with the doctor. But the mathematician
and the doctor would not be able to understand each other
upon important questions, because what the doctor would have
to say about them would not interest the mathematician, and
what the mathematician would have to say — or would
say, if he found words at all, — would not be
understood by the doctor, who would be lacking the necessary
mathematical background. This is what would happen in an
attempt to solve the problem I have just put before you.
People imagine: If the skull-bones are metamorphosed
vertebra, then we ought to be able to proceed directly,
through a transformation which it is possible to picture
spatially, from the vertebra to the skull. To extend the idea
still further to the limb-bones would, on the basis of the
accepted premises, be quite out of the question. The modern
mathematician will be able, from his mathematical studies, to
form an idea of what it really means when I turn a glove
inside out, when I turn the inside to the outside. One must
have in mind a certain mathematical handling of the process
by which what was formerly outside is turned inward, and what
was inside is turned to the outside. I will make a sketch of it
(Fig. 1)
— a structure of some
sort that is first white on the outside and red inside. We
will treat this structure as we did the glove, so that it is
now red outside and white inside
(Fig. 2).
But
let us go further, my dear friends, and picture
to ourselves that we have something endowed with a force of
its own that does not admit of being turned inside out in
such a simple way as a glove which still looks like a glove
after being inverted. Suppose that we invert something which
has different stresses of force on the outer surface from
those on the inner. We shall then find that simply through
the inversion quite a new form arises. The form may appear
thus before we have reversed it
(Fig. 1):
we turn it inside out and now different forces come into
consideration on the red surface and on the white, so that
perhaps, purely through the inversion, this form arises
(Fig. 3).
Such a form might
arise merely in the process of inversion. When the red side
faced inward, forces remained dominant which are developed
differently when it is turned outward. And so with the white
side; only when turned towards the inside can it develop its
inherent forces.
It
is of course quite conceivable to give a
mathematical presentation of such a subject, but people are
thoroughly disinclined nowadays to apply to reality what is
arrived at conceptually in such a way. The moment, however,
we learn to apply this to reality, we become able to see in
our long bones or tubular bones (that is, in the limb bones),
a form which, when inverted, becomes our skull bones! In the
drawing, let the inside of the bone, as far as the marrow, be
depicted by the red, the outside by the white
(Fig. 4).
Certain forms and forces, which can of
course be investigated, are turned inward, and what we see
when we draw away the muscle from the long bone is turned
outward. But now imagine these hollow bones turned inside out
by the same principle as I have just given you, in which
other conditions of stress and strain are brought into play;
then you may easily obtain this form
(Fig. 5).
Now it has the white within, and
what I depicted by the red comes to the outside. This is
in fact the relationship of a skull-bone to a limb-bone,
and in between lies the typical bone of the back — the
vertebra of the spinal column. You must turn the tubular bone
inside out like a glove according to its indwelling forces;
then you obtain the skull-bone. The metamorphosis of the
bones of the limbs into the skull-bones is only to be
understood when keeping in mind the process of inversion, or
‘turning inside-out’. The important thing to
realizes is that what is turned outward in the limb-bones is
turned inward in the skull. The skull-bones turn towards a
world of their own in the interior of the skull. That is one
world. The skull-bone is orientated to the world, just as the
limb-bone is orientated outward, towards the external world.
This can be clearly seen in the case of the bones. Moreover,
the human organism as a whole is so organized that it has on
the one hand a skull organization, and on the other a
limb-organization, the skull-organization being oriented
inward, the limb-organization outward. The skull contains an
inner world, the limb-man an outer world, and between the two
is a kind of balancing system which preserves the rhythm.
My
dear friends, take any literature dealing with
the theory of functions, or, say, with non-Euclidean
geometry, and see what countless ideas of every kind are
brought forward in order to get beyond the ordinary
geometrical conception of three-dimensional space; — to
extend the domain — widen out the concept of geometry.
You will see what industry and ingenuity are employed. But
now suppose that you have become an expert at mathematics,
who knows the theory of functions well and understands all
that can be understood today of non-Euclidean geometry. I
should like now to put a question concerning much that tends
in this direction (Forgive me if it seems as if one did not
value them highly, speaking of these things in such trivial
terms. And yet I must do so, and I beg the audience,
especially trained mathematicians, to turn it over in their
minds and see if there is not truth in what I say.) The
question could be put as follows: What is the use of all this
spinning of purely mathematical thoughts? What is it worth to
me, so to speak, in pounds, shillings and pence? No one is
interested in the spheres in which it might perhaps find
concrete application. Yet if we were to apply to the
structure of the human organism all that has been thought out
in non-Euclidean geometry, then we should be in the realm of
reality, and applying immeasurably important ideas to
reality, not wandering about in mere speculations. If the
mathematician were so trained as to be interested also in
what is real, — in the appearance of the heart, for
example, so that he could form an idea of how through a
mathematical process he could turn the heart inside out, and
how thereby the whole human form would arise, — if he
were taught to use his mathematics in actual life, then he
could be working in the realm of the real. It would then be
impossible to have the trained mathematician on the one hand,
not interested in what the doctor learns, and on the other,
the physician, understanding nothing of of how the
mathematician — though in a purely abstract element
— is able to change and metamorphose forms. This is the
situation we must alter. If not, our sciences will fall into
decay. They grow estranged from one another; people no longer
understand each other's language.
How
then is science to be transformed into a social
science, as is implied in all that I shall be telling you in
these lectures? A science which leads over into social
science is not yet in existence.
On
the one hand we have Astronomy, tending more and
more to be clothed in mathematical forms of thought. It has
become so great in its present form just because it is a
purely mathematical and mechanical science. But there is
another branch of science which stands, as it were, at the
opposite pole to Astronomy, and which cannot be studied in
its real nature without Astronomy. It is however, impossible,
as science is today, to build a bridge between Astronomy and
this other pole of science, namely, Embryology. He alone is
studying reality, who on the one hand studies the starry
skies and on the other hand the development of the human
embryo. How is the human embryo generally studied today?
Well, it is stated: The human embryo arises from the
interaction of two cells, the sex-cells or gametes, male and
female. These cells develop in the parent organism in such a
way as to attain a certain state of independence before they
are able to interact. They then present a certain contract,
the one cell, the male, calling forth new and different
possibilities of development in the other, the female. The
question is put: What is a cell? As you know, since about the
middle of the 19th century, Biology has largely been built
upon the cell theory. The cell is described as a larger or
smaller, spherule, consisting of albuminous or protein-like
substances. It has a nucleus within it of a somewhat
different structure and around the whole is an enclosing
membrane. As such, it is the building-stone for all that
arising by way of living organisms. The sex-cells are of a
similar nature but are formed differently according to
whether they are male or female, and from such cells every
more complicated organism is built up.
But
now, what is actually meant when it is said
that an organism builds itself up from these cells? The idea
is that substances which are otherwise in Nature are taken up
into these cells and then no longer work in quite the same
way as before. If oxygen, nitrogen or carbon are contained in
the cells, the carbon, for instance, does not have the effect
upon some other substance outside, that it would have had
before; such power of direct influence is lost to it. It is
taken up into the organism of the cell and can only work
there as conditions in the cell allow. That is to say, the
influence is exerted not so much by the carbon, but by the
cell, which makes use of the particular characteristics of
carbon, having incorporated a certain amount of it into
itself. For example, what man has within him in the form of
metal — iron for instance — only works in a
circuitous way, via the cell. The cell is the building-stone.
So in studying the organism, everything is traced to the
cell. Considering at first only the main bulk of the cell,
without the nucleus and membrane, we distinguish two parts: a
transparent part composed of this fluid, and another part
forming sort of framework. Describing it schematically, we
may say that there is the framework of the cell, and this is
embedded, as it were, in the other substance which, unlike
the framework, is quite unformed.
(Fig. 6)
Thus we must think of the cell
as consisting of a mass which remains
fluid and unformed and a skeleton or framework which takes on
a great variety of forms. This then is studied. The method of
studying cells in this way has been pretty well perfected;
certain parts in the cell can be stained with color, others
do not take the stain. Thus with carmine or saffron, or
whatever coloring matter is used, we are able to distinguish
the form of the cell and can thus acquire certain ideas about
its inner structure. We note, for instance, how the inner
structure changes when the female germ-cell is fructified. We
follow the different stages in which the cell's inner
structure alters; how it divides; and how the parts become
attached to one another, cell upon cell, so that the whole
becomes a complicated structure. All this is studied. But it
occurs to no-one to ask: With what is this whole life in the
cell connected? What is really happening? It does not occur
to anyone to ask this.
What
happens in the cell is to be conceived, my
dear friends, in the following way, — though to be
sure, it is still a rather abstract way. There is the cell.
For the moment let us consider it in its most usual form,
namely the spherical form. This spherical form is partially
determined by the thin fluid substance, and enclosed within
it is the delicate framework. But what is the spherical form?
The thin fluid mass is as yet left entirely to itself and
therefore behaves according to the impulses it receives from
its surroundings. What does it do? Well, my dear friends, it
mirrors the universe around it! It takes on the form of the
sphere because it mirrors in miniature the whole cosmos,
which we indeed also picture to ourselves ideally as a
sphere. Every cell in its spherical form is no less than
an image of the form of the whole universe. And the
framework inside, every line of the form, is conditioned by
its relationship to the structure of the whole cosmos. To
express myself abstractly to begin with, think of the sphere
of the universe with its imaginary boundary
(Fig. 7).
In it, you have here a planet, and there
a planet (a,a1). They work in such a way as to
exert an influence upon one another in the direction of the
line which joins them. Here (m) let us say —
diagrammatically, of course, — a cell is formed; its
outline mirrors the sphere. Here, within the framework it has
a solid part which is due to the working of the one planet on
the other. And suppose that here there were another
constellation of planets, working upon each other along the
line joining them (b,b1).
And here again there might be yet another
planet (c), this one having no counterpart; — it throws
the whole construction, which might otherwise have been
rectangular, out of shape, and the structure takes on a
somewhat different form. And so you have in the whole
formation of the framework of the cell a reflection of the
relationships existing in the planetary system, —
altogether in the whole starry system. You can enter quite
concretely into the formation of the cell and you will reach
an understanding of this concrete form only if you see in the
cell an image of the entire cosmos.
And
now take the female ovum, and picture to
yourselves that this ovum has brought the cosmic forces to a
certain inner balance. They have taken on form in the
framework of the cell, and are in a certain way at rest
within it, supported by the female organism as a whole. Then
comes the influence of the male sex-cell. This has not
brought the macrocosmic forces to rest, but works in the
sense of a very specialized force. It is as though the male
sex-cell works precisely along this line of force (indicated
by Dr. Steiner on the blackboard) upon the female ovum which
has come to a condition of rest. The cell, which is an image
of the whole cosmos, is thereby caused to relinquish its
microcosmic form once more to a changing play of forces. At
first, in the female ovum, the macrocosm comes to rest in a
peaceful image. Then through the male sex-cell the female is
torn out of this state of rest, and is drawn again into a
region of specialized activity and brought into movement.
Previously it had drawn itself together in the resting form
of the image of the cosmos, but the form is drawn into
movement again by the male forces which are, so to speak,
images of movement. Through them the female forces, which are
images of the form of the cosmos and have come to rest, are
brought out of this state of rest and balance.
Here
we may have some idea, from the aspect of
Astronomy, of the forming and shaping of something which is
minute and cellular. Embryology cannot be studied at all
without Astronomy, for what Embryology has to show is only
the other pole of what is seen in Astronomy. We must, in a
way, follow the starry heavens on the one hand, seeing how
they reveal successive stages, and we must then follow the
process of development of a fructified cell. The two belong
together, for the one is only the image of the other. if you
understand nothing of Astronomy, you will never understand
the forces which are at work in Embryology, and if you
understand nothing of Embryology, you will never understand
the meaning of the activities with which Astronomy has to deal.
For these activities appear in miniature in the processes of
Embryology.
It
is conceivable that a science should be formed,
in which, on the one hand, astronomical events are calculated
and described, and on the other hand all that belongs to them
in Embryology, which is only the other aspect of the same
thing.
Now
look at the position as it is today: you find
that Embryology is studied on its own. It would be regarded
as madness if you were to demand of a modern embryologist
that he should study Astronomy in order to understand the
phenomena in his own sphere of work. And yet it should be so.
This is why a complete regrouping of the sciences is
necessary. It will be impossible to become a real
embryologist without studying Astronomy. It will no longer be
possible to educate specialists who merely turn their eyes
and their telescopes to the stars, for to study the stars in
that way has no further meaning unless one knows that it is
out of the great universe that the minute and microscopical
is fashioned.
All
this, — which is quite real and concrete,
— has in scientific circles been changed into the
utmost abstraction. It is reality to say: We must strive for
astronomical knowledge in cellular theory, especially in
Embryology. If DuBois-Raymond had said that the detailed
astronomical facts should be applied to the cell-theory, he
would have spoken out of the sphere of reality. But what he
wanted corresponds to no reality, namely that something
thought-out and devised — the atoms and molecules — should be
examined with astronomical precision. He wanted the
astronomical type of mathematical thoughts, which have been
added to the world of the stars, to be sought for again in
the molecule.
Thus
you see, upon the one hand lies reality:
movement, the active forces of the stars and the embryonic
development in which there lives, in all reality, what lives
in the starry heavens. That is where the reality lies and
that is where we must look for it. On the other hand lies
abstraction. The mathematician, the mechanist, calculates the
movements and forces of the heavenly bodies and then invents
the molecular structure to which to apply this kind of
astronomical knowledge. Here he is withdrawn from life,
living in pure abstractions.
These
are the things about which we must think,
remembering that now we must renew, in full consciousness,
something which was in a certain sense present in earlier
times. Looking back to the Egyptian Mysteries, we find
astronomical observations such as were made at that time.
These observations, my dear friends, were not used merely to
calculate when an eclipse of the Sun or Moon would take
place, but rather to arrive at what should come about in
social evolution. Men were guided by what they saw in the
heavens, as to what must be said to the people, what
instructions should be given, so that the development of the
whole social life should take its right course. Astronomy
and Sociology were dealt with as one. We too, though in
a different way from the Egyptians, must again learn how to
connect what happens in social life with the phenomena of the
great universe. We do not understand what came about in the
middle of the 15th century, if we cannot relate the events of
that time to the phenomena which then prevailed in the
universe. It is like a blind man talking about color to speak
of the changes in the civilized world in the middle of the
15th century without taking all this into account.
Spiritual
Science is already a starting point. But
we shall not succeed in bring together the complicated domain
of Sociology — social science — with the
observations of natural phenomena, unless we first begin by
connecting Astronomy with Embryology, linking the embryonic
facts with astronomical phenomena.
|