|
|
|
Rudolf Steiner e.Lib
|
|
The Riddle of Humanity
Rudolf Steiner e.Lib Document
|
|
The Riddle of Humanity
Schmidt Number: S-3248
On-line since: 29th July, 2002
What I would like to give you today is a thoroughly undemanding
analysis of some recent directions in recent philosophical thinking. I
want to take some well-known currents of thought from the surface of
recent intellectual life as my point of departure. Later very
soon, if not in the next lecture we will have time to consider
some of the details and the special ramifications of contemporary
thought. I would like to describe a certain tendency that is
fundamental to some of the most recent of contemporary schools of
thought. The whole direction taken by certain schools of thought is
marked by the loss of a sense for how to orient oneself in reality,
and by the loss of a sense for truth in so far as the
truth refers to an agreement between our knowledge and something
that is objective. Just observe what difficulties the adherents of
some recent schools of thought find themselves in when they need to
decide whether a judgement about reality about some aspect of
reality or other is right or wrong. They have difficulty in
finding valid epistemological grounds, valid scientific or
philosophical grounds, for their decision. There is no trace of a
principle or to use a more scientific expression of a
criterion for deciding whether particular judgements are true
judgements; that is, there is no way of deciding whether they have
been made with regard for reality. Certain of the old criteria have
been lost and it is quite evident that nothing has come along to take
their place in recent times.
I would like to take as my point of departure a thinker who died very
recently. Initially, the physical sciences were his field. He turned
from them to a kind of inductive philosophy in which he attempted to
find something to replace the old concepts of truth, the feeling for
which has been lost. I am speaking of Ernst Mach. Today I can only
give you an outline of his ideas. Ernst Mach was sceptical about all
the concepts produced by the thinking that preceded his time-all the
thinking up to the last third of the nineteenth century. Although it
approached its concepts more or less critically, this earlier thinking
still spoke of the world and man under the assumption that man
perceives the world through his senses processes his sense
perceptions with the help of concepts, and thereby arrives at certain
pictures and ideas about the world. This assumes and, as I
said, I cannot go into all kinds of epistemological considerations
today that the impressions of colour, sound, warmth, pressure,
and so on, originate in something objective. It assumes that the
impressions are made on our senses by something objective, something
objectively out there in external space and, in general, external to
our soul life. It assumes that these impressions create sense
experiences which then are further digested. And it also assumes that
the human I is the true agent which is actively at
work in the whole process of knowledge, and forms the basis of the
entire life process. This I was acknowledged in one
form or another and there was much speculation about it. People said:
There exists something which one is justified in seeing as a kind of
I . It is active and it is what ultimately shapes
sense experiences into concepts and ideas.
Ernst Mach looked around our given world and said, more or less: None
of these concepts are justified neither the concept of
subjectivity and of the I which is the subject of
knowledge, nor the concept of the object that is the basis of sense
impressions. What are we really given? he asked. What does the world
really put before us? Fundamentally, all that is given are our
sensations. We perceive colours, we perceive sounds, we have
sensations of smell, and so on; but beyond these sensations, nothing
at all is given to us. If we review the whole world, everything is
some [form] of sensation, and beyond the sensations nothing objective is
to be found. The entire world around us actually resolves into
sensations. The multiplicity of sensations is all that there is. And
if we can say that nothing exists beyond sensations, then we
cannot say that there is some kind of I
active within us. For what is given to us in the sphere of the soul?
Again, only sensations. When we observe what is within us, the only
thing given is the succession of sensations. These are strung together
as on a thread: yesterday we had sensations; today we have sensations;
tomorrow we will have sensations. They connect like the links of a
chain. But everywhere, nothing is there but sensations; there is no
active I . An I only appears to
be there because groups of sensations are associated with one another
and thus are separated out from the total world of impressions. We
call this group of impressions I . They
belong to us and are a part of what we perceived yesterday and the day
before yesterday and half a year before that. We have found a group of
sensations that belong together, so we use the expression
I as a common designator to apply to
them all. Thus both the I and the object of
knowledge fall away; the manifold of sensations is all that a human
being can talk about. At first we relate to the world naively but, if
we observe reality, all that is really there is a multiplicity of
variously-grouped colours, variously-grouped sounds, variously-grouped
experiences of temperature, variously-grouped experiences of pressure,
and so on. And that is all.
Now along comes science. Science discovers laws. In other words it
does not simply describe sensations here I see this sensation,
there I see that sensation, and so on it discovers laws, laws
of nature. Why should men need to establish natural laws if all they
ever experience is a multiplicity of sensations? Merely watching the
multiplicity of sensations never leads to judgements. It is only when
we have more or less achieved laws that we arrive at judgements. What
have our Judgements to do with the world of experience, which is
really nothing more than a chaotic multiplicity? What guides one in
forming judgements? Sensations are all that one has to go on-and Mach
maintains that one sensation cannot even be measured against another.
If that is so, what is the source of criteria for passing judgements,
establishing laws and arriving at the laws of nature? To this Ernst
Mach replies that it is merely a matter of economy of thought. By
devising certain laws we are enabled to follow particular sensations
and hold them together in our thought. What we call a law of nature is
a method of associating sensations. It is the method we feel is the
most economical for our thinking, the one that requires the least
amount of thought.
We see a stone fall to earth. This involves a collection of sensations
one here, one there, and so on nothing but sensations.
The law of weight, of gravitation, gives us a way of combining these
sensations. But there is no further reality in the law of gravitation;
the sensations are the real content.
But why should we ever think out the law of gravity in the first
place? Because we find it convenient: it is economical to have a
concise way of referring to a special group of sensations. It gives us
a kind of comfortable overview of the world of sensations. And the
ways of thinking that we find most comfortable these are the
ones we call laws. What we accept as valid laws are the thoughts that
give us the most convenient overview of some group of sensations. Laws
provide us with certain useful expressions. Through them we know
so to speak that when one set of conditions (that is,
some collection of sensations) is repeated, then others will again be
found to follow them. It is convenient for me to use the law of
gravity to gather together the sensations aroused by a falling stone,
for then I know: If this is a law, one thing will fall to earth like
another. Thus I can think about the future in terms of the past. That
is economy of thought. It is the law upon which Ernst Mach says the
whole business of science is founded the law of economy of
thought, the law of the application of the least energy, which says
that the greatest possible sum of sensations should be thought with
the least possible number of thoughts.
You can see that no one will ever arrive at reality in this way. For,
collecting together groups of sensations in the most comfortable
manner possible serves nothing beyond making one's life more
comfortable. The expressions to which one is led by the principle of
economy of thought tell one nothing about the real basis of the
sensations. The thoughts merely serve to give us a comfortable
orientation in the world. The only fundamental reason for a thought is
that we find it comfortable; that is why we connect certain sensations
as we do. Thus you see that we have here a criterion of truth that
quite deliberately tries to avoid establishing any sort of
objectivity. Its only purpose is to support man's capacity to orient
himself by means of sensations.
Richard Wahle
(see Note 16)
was a thinker who based his ideas on similar
considerations. Richard Wahle also said: People think that one thing
is a cause, that another thing is an effect; that an
I lives within us, that objects live outside us.
But that is all nonsense. (I use approximately the same expressions as
those he used.) In truth, the only things in the world that are known
to us are these: that here I see the occurrence of a colour, that
there a sound occurs. The world, says Wahle, consists in such
occurrences and nothing more. We have already gone too far if we name
these occurrences sensations, as Mach called them, for the
word sensation already contains the hidden implication
that there is someone present who is doing the sensing. But how could
one possibly know that the occurrence of which one is presently aware
is a sensation? Out there is an occurrence of colour, an occurrence of
sound, an occurrence of pressure, an occurrence of warmth; within is
an occurrence of pain, an occurrence of joy, an occurrence of
repletion, an occurrence of hunger. Or within is an occurrence in
which someone thinks, There is a God. But nothing more is
present there than the occurrence in which someone thinks, There
is a God. Having the idea that God exists is just like having a
pain. Both are only occurrences. Wahle believes, to be sure, that one
must distinguish between two kinds of occurrence, the primary ones,
and the so-called miniatures: Primary occurrences are those that come
with an original sharpness, such as occurrences of colour, occurrences
of sound, occurrences of pressure, occurrences of warmth, occurrences
of pain, occurrences of joy, occurrences of hunger, occurrences of
repletion, and so on. Miniatures are fantasies, intentions and, in
short, everything that appears as a shadowy picture of primary
occurrences. But when one takes the sum of all primary occurrences and
all miniatures, that is all the world has to offer us. Fundamentally,
everything else is poetry it has been written-in without
justification. Such is the case, Wahle believes, when, instead of
restricting themselves to saying, Three years ago there were
certain occurrences, then there were others, people are blinded
by the fact that these occurrences follow one another and make the
further assumption that the occurrences are collected together in an
I . But where is this I ? There is
nothing there but occurrences, occurrences that are arranged in
sequence, series of occurrences. Nowhere is an I to
be found. And then others come along and claim to have discovered laws
that connect occurrences, natural laws. But these laws, too, present
us with nothing more than series of occurrences. And it is absolutely
impossible to come to any decision as to why the series of occurrences
are as they are. When men think they know something because they have
strung together occurrences in a particular way, that knowledge is
just so much folderol. Such knowledge, according to Wahle, is neither
valid nor is it especially lofty it is just a sign that someone
has had to think something out because he has had difficulty in
relating to his own occurrences. The I is the most
curious of all mankind's inventions. For nowhere in the sum total of
occurrences is such a thing as an I to be found.
Some unknown factors seem to lurk behind the manner in which
occurrences follow one another, since it does not seem arbitrary. But
and I am using the words that Wahle would use it is
entirely beyond the capacities of human judgement to ascertain what
kind of unknown factors might be at work there. There is nothing one
can say about them. All that a human being can know is that
occurrences occur and that the factors directing them are unknown.
Physics, physiology, biology, sociology they all falter about
in the dark, seeking for the director-in-charge. But this faltering
about merely helps us to live with the occurrences. It will never lead
us to knowledge about the unknown factors at play in the succession of
occurrences. It is human folly, therefore, when people believe they
can arrive at a philosophy which teaches us something about why the
occurrences are as they are. Humanity has devoted itself to this folly
for a time; it is high time they gave it up. One of Wahle's most
important books bore the title The End of all Philosophy. Its
Legacy to Theology, Physiology, Aesthetics and National Policy (Das
Ganze der Philosophie und ihr Ende. Ihre Vermachtnisse an die
Theologie, Physiologie. Aesthetik und Staatspedagogik). In order
to teach about this end of philosophy, and in order to
teach that philosophy is nonsense, Richard Wahle became a professor of
philosophy!
Above all else, we can see that a total helplessness regarding the
criteria of truth lies at the root of such an approach. All impulse to
come to any decisions regarding knowledge has been lost. What this is
based on could be characterised in the following way. Imagine someone
who has a book which he has been reading for a long time. He has read
it again and again and certain information contained in the book has
become a part of the way he lives. Then one day he thinks to himself:
Yes, here I have this book before me and I have always assumed that it
gives me information about certain things. But when I take a really
good look at it, the pages contain nothing but letters, letters, and
more letters. I have really been an ass to believe that information
about things that are not even in the book could somehow flow to me
from it. For nothing is there but letters. I have been living in the
mad expectation that if I let these letters affect me and if I enter
into a relationship with them, they could give me something. But
nothing is there but rows of the letters of the alphabet just
letters. So I must finally release myself from the insane notion that
these letters describe something, or that they could somehow relate to
one another, or that they could group into meaningful words, or such
like. That really is a picture of the kind of thinking on which
Wahle's non-philosophy, his un-philosophy, is based. For his great
discovery consists in this: Men have been foolish asses, he says, to
believe that they could read in the book of nature and explain how
occurrences are connected! They witness occurrences, but there is
nothing there beyond the unconnected occurrences. At the very most,
there might be some further, unknown factors at work which are
responsible for the special groupings of the letters.
This is how Wahle fails to identify with the impulse to decide about
the truth of judgements and to make discoveries about the nature of
the world. Human knowledge has lost the power to formulate any
criterion of truth. In earlier times one believed in the human
capacity to arrive at truths by means of judgements based on inner
experience.
This belief has slipped from one's grasp. Hence the way philosophers
wander about in this area, philosophising. By way of these two
examples I wanted to demonstrate how a criterion of truth and a
feeling for one's capacity to produce the truth have been lost.
A contemporary school of thought called Pragmatism demonstrates the
loss of the older understanding for a criterion of truth. In
Pragmatism you have a large-scale, calculated version of this loss.
William James
(see Note 17)
is the most prominent, if not the most significant,
proponent of Pragmatism. The following is a brief characterisation of
the principle of Pragmatism as it has recently appeared.
Men pass judgements and they want them to express something about
reality. But no human being can possibly generate anything within
himself that will enable him to pass a true judgement about reality.
There is nothing in man that, in and of itself, leads to the decision:
that is true and the other is false. In other words, there is a
feeling that one is powerless to find any original, self-sufficient
criterion for whether something is true or false. And yet, because
they live in a real world, men feel it is necessary to make
judgements. And the sciences are full of judgements. But if one
reviews the entire spectrum of the sciences with all their judgements,
do they contain anything about anything that is in a higher sense
true, true in the sense in which the old schools of philosophy spoke
of truth and falsehood? No! According to what William James says, for
example, any line of thought which asks whether something is true or
false is a totally impossible way of thinking. One makes judgements.
If certain judgements are passed, then one can use them to get along
in life. They prove to be useful and applicable to living they
enhance one's life. If other judgements were passed, one would soon
cease to come to terms with life, one's life would cease to progress.
They would not be useful, they would harm life. This applies to even
the most unsophisticated judgements. One cannot even say, reasonably,
that the sun will rise again in the morning, for no criterion of truth
is available. But we have formed the judgement: The sun rises every
morning. If someone came along, maintaining that the sun would only
rise for the first two thirds of the month, but not during the last
third, this judgement would not bring him forward in life; he would
run into trouble in the last third of the month. The judgements we
form are useful. But there can be no talk of whether they are true or
false. All that can be said is that one judgement helps us to get on
in the world, enhances life, and that the contrary is the case with
another, which gets in the way of life. There is no independent
criterion of truth and falsehood: what enhances life we call true, and
what hinders life, false. Thus everything to do with the question of
whether or not we should pass a certain judgement is reduced to
external matters of practical living. None of the impulses one once
believed one possessed are valid.
Now, this line of thought is not the arbitrary product of one or the
other school. One of the most extraordinary things about the line of
thinking I have just described is that it has spread to practically
the whole of our earth's intellectual community. It makes its
appearance, independently, in one place and then in another, because
present-day humanity is organised so as to fall into this way of
thinking. The following interesting example demonstrates this. In the
1870s, in America, Pierce
(see Note 18)
wrote the first book about Pragmatic
Philosophy. This was taken up by William James and, in England, by
Schiller
(see Note 19),
and these and others continued to develop it. Now, at
the very same time that Pierce was publishing his initial treatment of
the ideas of pragmatic philosophy in America, a German thinker
published the book The Philosophy of As If (Philosophie des Als
Ob). It was a parallel occurrence. The philosopher in question was
Hans Vaihinger
(see Note 20).
What is this Philosophy of As If all
about? It begins with the thought that human beings are actually
incapable of forming true or false concepts in the way they used to
do, although they still persist in forming them. The atom is a
well-known example of this. The concept of the atom is, of course,
wholly absurd. For our thinking attributes all sorts of qualities to
the atom, qualities that will not stand up when, they are put to the
test of the senses. And yet sense impressions are thought of as the
effects of atomic activity. So the concept is contradictory. It is a
concept of something that is totally unobservable. The atom, as
Vaihinger says, is a fiction. We create many such fictions. All the
higher concepts we form about reality are, fundamentally, fictions of
this sort. Since there is no criterion of truth or falsehood, the
reasonable man of the present needs to be clear that he is dealing in
fictions. One must be fully conscious about making fictions. One must
be clear that the atom is nothing but a fiction and that it cannot
really exist. But one can observe the various things that are manifest
in the world as if they were ruled by the life and movements of atoms
as if. For this fiction is useful. Establishing such
fictions makes it possible to connect the appearances in certain ways.
The I is also a fiction, but it is a fiction one
has to create. For it is much more comfortable to treat the
appearances that come together as if an I were
active within them than it is to get along without the fiction of the
I ... even though one can rest assured that it is a
fiction. Thus we live according to fictions. There is no philosophy of
reality, only a Philosophy of As If. The world humours us
by appearing as if it agreed with the fictions we have made about it.
As a whole, in its tendencies and also in the way it presents
individual arguments, the philosophy of Pragmatism is very similar to
the Philosophy of As If. As I said, it was written down
during the same period, the 1870s, when Pierce was writing his
treatise on Pragmatic Philosophy. But an objective
criterion of truth was still possible for the humanity of the 1870s.
They still possessed enough rudiments of the old beliefs for their
science not to have to consist of fictions. The 1870s were an awkward
time for someone who wanted to become a professor of philosophy to
publish a Philosophy of As If. It was not yet possible to
get away with it. So Vaihinger looked for a way out. At first he acted
as one has to act (has one not?). He left the Philosophy of As
If lying in his desk while he went about his teaching. When the
time came, he accepted his pension. Then he published the
Philosophy of As If, which has now appeared in numerous
editions. I simply tell the story; I am not pointing my finger, I am
not judging, I am only telling the story.
So we see that there was a tendency for the old criteria of truth to
break down and for truth to be measured against life. Formerly it was
believed that life should be shaped in accordance with the truth, so
life was put in the service of truth. What one meant by truth in the
old sense did not include fictions, not even useful fictions. But,
according to the extraordinary definition of the Philosophy of As
If, truth is the most comfortable form of error. For, although
there is nothing else but error, some errors are more agreeable and
others less agreeable. The fact that what we call truths are simply
the more agreeable errors is something we must clearly understand.
Thus, an impulse to do away with the concept of truth as it had been
understood in older theories of knowledge really has been developing
in the more recent schools of thought. One must ask oneself,
What is this all about? Naturally, there would be much to
tell if I were to give you a comprehensive account of the matter. But
to begin with we will take only one from among the many possible
examples. In recent times, a boundless flood of empirical knowledge
has become available to mankind. At the same time, men's thinking has
become increasingly powerless. Thinking has lost its sovereignty over
this inexhaustible richness of empirical observation and empirical
knowledge; it cannot hold them together.
The way in which people have become more and more accustomed to
abstract thinking is another factor. One did not think so much in
earlier times, but one tried to keep one's thinking connected to the
external world and to actual experience. It was felt that thinking
needed to be connected with something and that it could not progress
if it were wholly isolated. But along with the extensive cultivation
of thinking, one has also learned to think abstractly has
become accustomed to abstract thinking and has become fond of it. To
this must be added other harmful characteristics of our age, above
all, the view that anyone who wants to become even so much as a
lecturer must produce some kind of elevated thinking or research, and
that those who want to become professors must do something quite
immense! A kind of hypertrophy of thinking, so to speak, has been thus
created. Thinking is set loose on its own; it begins to arrive at
forms of thought that, as such, are merely internally logical. I will
show you one of these internally logical thought-forms.
Just picture the following: Here is a mountain. On this mountain (A) a
shot is fired. After a while, say two minutes, two more shots are
fired. Then, after a further two minutes, three shots are fired.
And now, over here (B) there is someone who is listening. I will not
say that he is wounded, but he is listening. What he hears would be,
first a single shot, then after a certain period, two shots, and then,
after another pause, three shots. But now let us assume that matters
are not so simple, with one, two, and then three shots being fired
here, and over here someone who hears the shots first one, then
two, then three. Let us assume that someone (C) moves from this
mountain (left) towards this other one (right). Assume that he flies
at a certain speed and that he moves very fast. You know from
elementary physics that sound requires a certain time to get from here
(see drawing) to there. Therefore, when a shot is fired here (A), a
certain period of time will elapse before it will be heard by a person
who is listening over here (B) ... then the sound of the single shot
will arrive. Two minutes later, the pair of shots will arrive and,
after a further two minutes, the three shots. But let us assume that
this other person (C) moves faster than the speed of sound. As he
passes this mountain, moving towards the other, he is already moving
faster than the speed of sound. The first shot is fired ... then two
shots ... then three ... After the three shots have been fired, he
arrives at this other mountain and flies on at the same speed until he
overtakes the three shots that is, he flies past the sound of
the three shots flying quickly past them, for he is moving
faster. Eventually, the sound of the three shots will arrive here (D).
He is flying after them. He hears them as he overtakes them and
continues onward, flying towards the two shots that had been fired
earlier. These he also hears as he overtakes them. Then he overtakes
the single shot and hears it. Therefore, someone who is flying faster
than sound would hear the shots in reverse order: three shots ... two
shots ... one shot. If one is living in circumstances usual for an
ordinary human being on the ordinary earth, and thus has the usual
relationship to the speed of sound, one would hear one shot at this
point, two shots here, three here. But if one does not behave like an
ordinary human being on the ordinary earth, but instead is a being who
can fly faster than the speed of sound, one would hear the events in
reverse order: three shots, two shots, one shot. All that is required
is that one practise the minor skill of chasing after the sounds while
flying faster than the sounds of the shots are moving.
Now, this is unquestionably as logical as it could be. There is not
the slightest logical objection to be brought against it. Thanks to
certain things that have emerged recently in the sciences, the example
I have just been describing to you in which someone flies in
pursuit of sounds and hears them in reverse order has been used
to introduce countless lectures. Again and yet again, lectures begin
with this so-called example. For this is supposed to demonstrate that
the way in which one perceives things is a result of the situation in
which one is living. The only reason that we hear as we do, rather
than in reverse, is that we move at a snail's pace in comparison with
the speed of sound. I cannot describe here all that is derived from
this train of thought, but I wanted to acquaint you with it, since for
many it is the basis of a widespread, acutely discerning theory, the
so-called theory of relativity.
I have only described the most obvious parts to you. But you can see
from what I have described that everything here is logical
very, very logical. Now, these days one finds countless judgements
the philosophical literature is teeming with them all of
which are derived from the same assumptions about thought. It is as
though thinking has been torn away from reality. One thinks only about
certain isolated conditions of reality and then constructs further
thoughts from them.
It is scarcely possible to reply to such things, for the naturally
expected reply would be a logical reply. But there can be no logical
reply. It was for this reason that I introduced a certain idea in my
last book, On the Riddles of Humanity (Vom Menschenratsel).
This is the idea that if one wants to arrive at the truth, it is not
sufficient just to form a logical concept, or a logical idea. There is
the further requirement that the concept or idea must be in accordance
with reality. Now, a very lengthy discussion would be required if I
were to show you that the whole of the theory of relativity does not
agree with reality, even though it is logical wonderfully
logical. We could show how the concept that is constructed regarding
the series of one, two and three shots is completely logical and that,
nevertheless, it is not a concept that would be formed by someone who
thinks in accordance with reality. One cannot disprove the theory, one
can only refrain from using it! And someone who has understood the
criterion of being in accord with reality would refrain from using
such concepts.
The empirical phenomena that Lorentz
(see Note 21),
Einstein, and others are
trying to understand by means of this theory of relativity must be
approached in an entirely different manner, not along the lines in
which they and the others are thinking.
What I have been describing to you here is only one current in the
ongoing stream of recent thought. Naturally, remnants of earlier
thought are always being intermixed with the more recent thinking. But
the ultimate and radical consequences of the assumptions on which
almost all recent thinking is based are already contained in what I
have been describing to you. We can see one distinctive peculiarity. A
self-sufficient criterion of truth and falsehood has been lost
or, better said, the feeling for such a criterion has been lost. The
resulting emancipation of abstract thinking has led to the formation
of concepts which, being logical, are indisputable. In a certain sense
they even accord with reality. But they remain merely formal concepts,
for they are not suitable for saying something real about reality.
They swim on the surface of reality without penetrating to the actual
impulses at work in reality.
The following is an example of a theory that stays on the surface of
reality and does not want to submerge in reality: Consider how, within
the sphere of human reality one can distinguish the mineral realm, the
plant realm, the animal realm and the human realm. And men live within
a social order, as well one could call it a sociological order.
Perhaps other, higher, orders could be found, but we are not presently
concerned with those. Now, in the middle of the nineteenth century,
when a materialistic concept of reality held sway, the fashion in
which people pictured these superimposed realms was one that must seem
simplistic to us. Basically, only the mineral realm was taken into
account. One said to oneself: Now, plants consist of the same things
that are to be found in the mineral realm; they are simply organised
in a more complicated way. The animal realm is again just a matter of
further complication, and the human realm is more complicated still
... and so we reach the higher levels. Mind you, when one proceeds
further, to the social order, it is no longer possible to discover
more complicated atomic movements. Certain patterns of movement
correspond to the mineral realm that is how people pictured
things. The movements become more complicated in the plant realm
this one knew, although it was not possible to observe the
atoms. Still more complicated movements correspond to the animal
realm, and even more complicated ones to the human realm. All was
built up in this way. But, of course, when one comes to the social
order it is not so easy to continue thinking in terms of atoms, for no
atomic movements are there to be observed.
It was left to a thinker of the final third of the nineteenth century
to at last accomplish the wonder of reducing sociology to biological
concepts. He treated social structures, such as families, like cells.
These then group themselves, do they not, into regional communities
or whatever we shall call them? which are the beginnings
of tissues. Then the theory goes further countries are complete
organs ... and so on. The person who created this way of thinking
about the social organism was named Schaffle
(see Note 22).
Schaffle then wrote
a book Social Democracy's Empty Future. (Die Aussichtslosigkeit
der, Sozialdemokratie), which drew on these theories for support.
Hermann Bahr
(see Note 23),
the Viennese writer, was still a young, but very
talented, whipper-snapper in those days. He wrote a reply to
Schaffle's Social Democracy's Empty Future and called it,
Herr Schaffle's Empty lnsights (Die Einsichtslosigkeit des Herm
Schaffle). This outstandingly-written book has since been
forgotten.
Thus, as I was saying, the old materialists conceived of reality in
terms of ever more complicated structures. In doing so, they naturally
had to introduce certain concepts, concepts, say, about how the
movements of the atoms, which in a mineral are fixed, become more
labile and seek to achieve a balanced form in plants, and so on. In
short, various theories were constructed in which it was attempted to
derive one thing from another. Once materialism had been active for
long enough, it was possible to think back and see how little fruit it
had borne and how poorly its idea of reality had stood up to exacting
tests. And so people came to the idea: Yes, to be sure, there is the
mineral realm, and after that comes the plant realm. Mineral substance
is contained within the plant, and the laws applying to minerals even
apply there; the salts and other substances contained in the plant
function in accordance with their own physiological-chemical laws. But
the plant realm can never arise out of the mineral realm. Something
further is required, some creative element. When one proceeds from the
mineral realm to the plant realm, something creative has to be added
to it. This creative element the first creative element
works creatively in the realm of the minerals. Then a second creative
element manifests itself in the mineral realm and the animal realm
arises. So the animal sphere must take hold of the plant and mineral
realms. Then a fourth creative element appears and takes hold of the
three lower realms takes them into the human sphere. Then, when
we come to the social order, a further creative element again takes
hold of the subordinate realms. A veritable hierarchy of creative
elements! Of course there is nothing objectionable in the logic of
this thinking. As thought, it is correct thought. But you will
certainly have to think differently about these matters if you call to
mind some of the concepts of spiritual science concepts which
we shall not be discussing today. These reflections remain stuck in
abstractions; they never arrive at a concrete picture. Some details
are mentioned, of course, but when one sets about thinking in this
fashion one is stuck with an abstract concept of creativity. All the
thinking remains stuck at the level of abstractions. And yet it is an
attempt to use clear, formal thinking to overcome an unadorned
materialism. One arrives at something higher, but only as an abstract
concept.
Boutroux's
(see Note 24)
philosophy is an attempt to overcome unadorned
materialism. He makes use of a formal thinking derived from the
unprejudiced observation of the hierarchy of the realms of nature. He
seeks the concept of an ascending creative scale in what could be
called the hierarchy of the sciences. This leads to interesting
conclusions. But the whole attempt remains stuck in abstractions. It
is easy to show this by examining the details of Boutroux's
philosophy. To begin with, I will only describe the line of thought he
takes; perhaps the rest can be introduced later. Here we have an
attempt to capture reality by applying abstractions to a more or less
superficial observation of reality. But it is not thus to be captured.
He does not want a mere Philosophy of As If, nor does he
want to found some sort of mere pragmatism, or to restrict himself to
an unreal enumeration of occurrences. But he cannot arrive at the sort
of concreteness needed for reading the external world and for
discovering what lies behind it. He cannot help us to look at the
external world as one looks at the letters in a book to discover what
is behind them; he only shows us some abstractions. These are supposed
to express what it is that lives in the realms of reality. Whereas it
was the criterion of reality that was missing in the other
philosophical lines of thought I have been describing, what has been
lost here is the power to take hold of reality concretely. One is no
longer able to submerge in the inner impulses that are at work in
reality, but only to skim along the top.
This shows us another fundamental tendency of modern life. I mentioned
that thinking has emancipated itself in a particular way Torn from
reality. Once emancipated from reality, it proceeds in abstractions.
If you will observe all the various recent schools of thought, you
will perceive how the ability to plunge into reality has been lost.
The ability to grasp reality in its true shape is becoming weaker and
weaker. For a classic example of this follow the development of
thought that leads from Maine de Biran
(see Note 25)
to Bergson
(see Note 26).
Whereas Biran, living in the first third of the nineteenth century, still
pursued a line of thought whose important psychological concepts
enabled him to submerge in the real sphere of the human being, Bergson
strikes out on a curious path that is wholly characteristic of the
particular tendencies at work in recent thought. Bergson notices, on
the one hand, that it is not possible to submerge in an immediate,
living reality by means of the usual abstract thinking nor with the
help of anything offered by scientific thinking as it is currently
practised and as it is embodied in various scientific conclusions. He
saw that this thinking is fundamentally unable to connect with reality
that it will always remain more or less on the surface of
reality. For this reason he wishes to grasp reality by means of a kind
of intuition. At present, I can only give you the broadest outlines of
this intuition at the moment. It is an inner mode of experience; it
contrasts with an approach which tries to capture reality in external
structures of its own devising. This leads Bergson to some odd
conclusions regarding the theory of knowledge and psychology. I will
omit the intermediate steps and proceed to the summit from whence he
points to the materialistic view that memories and other higher
manifestations of soul life manifestations involving
complicated inner forms or movements are dependent on
structures in the brain. He says, to the contrary, that the shaping of
these complicated forms has nothing at all to do with the purpose of
the brain. What happens, rather, is that the soul acts and comes into
relationships with reality which are then expressed in sensations,
perceptions, in practical engagement with life, and in the way we move
our body. These things are beyond the reach of abstract thinking and
must be grasped by intuition, by inner experience. The function of the
inner structures that are dependent on the brain extends no further
than to their effects on perception and on the promotion and
arrangement of life. Memory is not the result of formations in the
brain; memory functions with an intensity that is independent of the
brain.
This is an attempt to overcome a materialistic concept of knowledge.
It is a curious attempt in that what it brings to light is the
opposite of reality. For memory depends precisely upon the support of
the physical body, the physical brain and the whole physical system.
Memory could never be established in the soul life if the soul were
not able to extend its development into the physical body and
establish within it the things necessary for exercising the faculty
the ability to remember. So here we have a theory in
which the drive to overcome materialism leads to conclusions that are
precisely the opposite of the right ones. The truth of the matter is
that memory needs to be annexed to the soul it is among the
capacities that the human soul needs to acquire. Therefore, memory,
with the help of the physical body, needs to be annexed to the soul.
But Bergson arrives at a contrary view the view that the
physical body does not participate in the development of memory. I am
not describing these things in order to say something in particular
about Bergsonian philosophy, but merely to show you this curious
manifestation in contemporary thinking. Proceeding in an entirely
logical fashion, one arrives at the opposite of what is correct.
We could start, therefore, with those more epistemologically
orientated philosophies which speak of the inability to arrive at a
criterion of truth and falsehood, and then proceed to the philosophies
that are more concerned to arrive at the truth. What we would find,
throughout, is that they all arrive at exactly the wrong conclusions
because of their helplessness in dealing with the truth. Thus does
contemporary thinking lean towards the very things that are incorrect
and false. This phenomenon is connected with the way in which mankind
has developed a tendency towards abstractions and an ability to work
with abstractions, for this has made man a stranger to reality.
Mankind is detached from reality and cannot finds its way back into
reality. You can read about this in detail in my book, The Riddles
of Philosophy (Die Ratsel der Philosophie). If one separates
oneself from reality and lives in abstractions, the way back to
reality is not to be found. But a counter-tendency is beginning to
make itself felt. People are beginning to discover in themselves a
kind of longing for spiritual concepts. But the helplessness persists;
there is still an inability to arrive at the spirit. Significant and
instructive things are to be observed happening in contemporary
attempts to find a path that leads out of this absolute helplessness,
a path leading to spiritual truths. And we have just looked at an
example in which thinking that has been emancipated from reality seeks
for the truth and arrives at the opposite of the truth.
The philosophy of Eucken
(see Note 27)
is a characteristic example of someone
who is seeking for the spirit without having the slightest ability to
grasp even so much as the shirt-tail of anything spiritual. Although
Eucken speaks of nothing but the spirit, he does so only in words. He
never actually says anything about the spirit. Because his words are
wholly incapable of capturing anything truly spiritual, he speaks
unceasingly of the spirit. He has already written countless books. To
read through his books is a genuine torture, for they all say the same
thing. There you will always find ... that one must discover how to
grasp one's own being with thinking that exists in itself, that takes
hold of itself without any dependence on anything external or on any
external resistance, that beholds itself within itself, that proceeds
entirely within itself and in so doing enters into itself and then
recreates itself from out of itself. If you hear Eucken deliver a
series of lectures about Greek philosophy, or read one of his books
about it, you will find the development of Greek philosophy presented
in this manner: At first thinking tries a little to take hold of
itself, but it cannot yet do so ... Or you can hear how Paracelsus is
gradually beginning to take hold of the inner world ... Or you can
read a book about the development of Christianity-everywhere you will
find the same things; everywhere the same! Yet our modern philistines
find this philosophy so infinitely important; they rejoice to hear
someone speaking about the spirit and theorising about the spirit as
long as they are not required to know anything about the spirit or to
actually enter into anything spiritual. This is why many say that
Eucken's philosophy is the reawakening of Idealism, the reawakening of
the life of the spirit, and is the right philosophy for creating a
cultural ferment that will again enliven today's deathly, exhausted
spiritual life, and so on. And yet anyone who has a feeling for what
pulses, or ought to pulse, through a philosophy, and who reads or
listens to Eucken, will have the lively impression that he is supposed
to take hold of his own hair and drag himself into the heights, and
then drag himself higher still, and higher still again. For such is
the self-consistent logic of Eucken's philosophy. I have tried to give
a totally objective account of these things in my Riddles of
Philosophy. Anyone is capable of saying what I have just said, for
it is not necessary to embark on critical analysis merely
acquainting oneself with the concepts as they are is enough.
Thus we see how certain contemporary streams of thought flow from a
helplessness in the face of truth; we see how it is even possible to
construct philosophies out of such helplessness in the face of
reality. If one were not concerned about life, this might not seem so
terrible. But terrible it is. And now and again it is necessary to
enter into what lives and weaves in contemporary intellectual life in
order to develop a feeling for what might overcome these things.
I have only described to you a few of the currents of thought that
have been important to the intellectual life in the most varied
places, places where philosophical views of the world are presented in
lectures and are taught. Over the last years, the various streams of
thought have been developing similar tendencies, so that a common
structure of thought exists overall. I touched on this when I showed
you how the Philosophy of As If and Pragmatism arose at
the same time, independently of one another.
But the thinkers have also borrowed various things from one another.
The exchange of thoughts is always an active business. Vaihinger was
wholly independent of Pierce; the two, one in Germany, the other over
there in America, arrived at this approach to life independently of
one another. Indeed, one finds many such echoes between personalities
in one culture and personalities in another. Only by observing these
in detail does one obtain a true picture of what is really going on in
the spiritual life. And an unbelievable amount is written and thought
and considered along these lines today, but the speculations pay no
attention, to some of the simplest of things. Certain connections are
ignored because the present day has not preserved a sense for reality.
And this sense for reality is something that must be learned. As a
sort of appendix to today's lecture let me state: This sense for
reality is a thing that has to be learned.
If I may be allowed to mention something personal, I should like to
say that I have always attempted even in external scientific
matters to develop the sense for reality, the sense for how to
keep on the trail of reality. This consists not only in being able to
judge what is really there, but also in being able to find ways of
applying real measures and real comparisons to reality. Perhaps you
are acquainted with the so-called doctrine of the eternal return
the return of the same things that is to be found in
Nietzsche. According to this doctrine, we have already sat together
countless times before in just the way we are sitting now. And we will
sit together in this way countless times again. This is not a doctrine
of reincarnation, but a doctrine about the repetition of the same
things. At the moment I am not concerned to criticise the doctrine of
the eternal return. This doctrine of eternal return is derived from a
quite definite picture of how the world was formed. Out of this other,
prior, view of the world Nietzsche developed some impossible ideas.
I was once present with other scholars at the Nietzsche Archive. The
doctrine of the eternal return was being discussed and people were
interested to know how Nietzsche might have arrived at this idea. Now,
just think of the marvellous possibilities there! Anyone who is
acquainted with academic circumstances will see what beautiful
opportunities there are for writing the greatest possible number of
dissertations and books about how Nietzsche originally came upon the
idea of the doctrine of the eternal return. Naturally, one can come up
with the boldest of theories to explain it. One can find all kinds of
things; one only has to look for them. After the discussion had gone
on for a while, I said to the gathering: Nietzsche often arrived at an
idea by formulating the contradictory of some idea he encountered in
another person. Thus I was trying to approach his ideas realistically.
To my knowledge, I said, the contrary of this idea of his is to be
found in another philosopher, Duhring, who said that the original
configuration of the earth made it impossible that anything should
ever repeat itself. And I said that, to the best of my knowledge,
Nietzsche had read Duhring. So I suggested that the simplest thing
would be to go into Nietzsche's library, which has been preserved,
take down the books by Duhring, and look at the passages where the
counter-theory is to be found. We then went to his library and located
the books. We found them the relevant passages with which I was
quite familiar and found heavy markings in Nietzsche's own hand
and some characteristic words. When he came to passages where he
intended to formulate a contradictory idea I am no longer sure
exactly which word he used in this particular case Nietzsche
would write something like ass or nonsense or
meaningless. There was such a characteristic word written
in the margin at this place. Thus the idea for the doctrine of
the eternal return was born in Nietzsche's spirit when he read
this passage and formulated the contradictory idea! Here it was just a
matter of looking in the right place. For when he met certain ideas,
Nietzsche really did tend to formulate the contradictory idea.
Here we have another characteristic manifestation of the powerlessness
of the modern criterion of reality. I have been showing you some of
the things that originate in this powerlessness. We have another
example in this use of contradiction to confront a stated truth or a
pre-existing judgement when one is unable to arrive at any independent
criterion of truth of one's own. But one must not generalise about
such things. It would naturally be absurd to take this example and
come to the abstract judgement that Nietzsche arrived at his entire
philosophy in this manner, for at times he was entirely positive and
simply extended an idea while remaining completely faithful to its
original spirit. This, for example, is how the whole of what we
encounter in Nietzsche's Beyond Good and Evil (Jenseits von Gut und
Bose) came into being. This can be demonstrated in all
particulars. Once again, all one has to do is go to Nietzsche's
library. There one will find a book on morality by Guyau
(see Note 28).
Read all the passages where Nietzsche has made notes in the margins
you can then find them again, summarised, in Beyond Good and
Evil. Beyond Good and Evil is already contained in Guyau's
treatment of morality. These days it is necessary to pay attention to
such connections. Otherwise one can arrive at entirely false
impressions about what kind of person this or that thinker was.
Today I wanted to share with you some perspectives on the modern
intellectual life. I have restricted myself to what is most familiar
and straightforward. If circumstances permit, we can return to these
matters in the near future and examine them in greater detail.
|
Last Modified: 23-Nov-2024
|
The Rudolf Steiner e.Lib is maintained by:
The e.Librarian:
elibrarian@elib.com
|
|
|
|
|