Course III - Lecture I
Theosophical Teachings of the Soul.
Part I: Body and Soul
GA 52
Berlin
March 16, 1904
Self-knowledge is necessary to be able to tell the human beings
the heavenly wisdom. Plato revered his great teacher Socrates particularly because
Socrates could get the loftiest knowledge, the knowledge of God through self-knowledge
because he appreciated the knowledge of the own soul more than that of the external
nature or of that which refers to anything beyond our world. Socrates just became
one of the martyrs of knowledge and truth because he was misunderstood in his
knowledge of the soul. One has accused him that he denied the gods, while he
searched for them, nevertheless, only on another way than others, on the way
through the own soul. He was accused of this soul knowledge which does not only
aim at the knowledge of the own soul, but also at the jewel which holds this
human soul as knowledge, namely the knowledge of the divine very basis.
These three talks should deal with
this knowledge of the soul. The number of the talks was not arbitrarily determined
and also not by chance, but well-considered out of the developmental course
of the soul. For in the times in which the knowledge and the wisdom of soul
was in the centre of the whole human thinking and striving, one divided the
nature of the human being into three parts, in body, soul and mind. You can
find this view in the ancient Indian wisdom of the Vedanta, in the heydays of
Buddhism and of the Greek philosophy and in the first centuries of Christianity.
If you want to consider the soul correctly, you have to connect it with the
other members of the human being, with the body on one side and with the mind
on the other side. Hence, this first lecture has to deal with the relations
of the soul with the body. The second lecture deals with the real internal being
of the human soul, and the third lecture with the sight of the soul up to the
divine-spiritual very basis of the world existence.
By a strange chance of history this
threefold division of the human being has got lost to the western research,
because wherever you look for psychology today, you find that one confronts
psychology simply to the natural sciences or the science of the body, and everywhere
you can hear that one assumes that the human being is to be considered according
to two points of view: the first informs about the corporeality, the other point
of view informs about the soul. This means, popularly expressed, that the human
being consists of body and soul. This sentence on which basically our whole
psychology well-known to you is based and to which many mistakes are to be attributed
in psychology this sentence has a strange history. Until the first times of
Christianity everybody who thought and tried to explain the human being considered
him as consisting of body, soul and mind. Go to the first Christian church teachers,
go to the Gnostics, then everywhere you find this division. Up to the second,
third centuries you find the trichotomy of the human being acknowledged by the
Christian science and dogmatism. Later one regarded this teaching as dangerous
within Christianity. One thought that the human being would become too arrogant
if he ascended beyond his soul to the spirit that he would presume too much
to inform about the basis of the things about which only the revelation should
inform.
That is why one consulted and decided
on different councils that as a dogma is to be taught for the future: the human
being consists of body and soul. Respected theologians maintained the trichotomy
in certain respects, like John Scotus Eriugena and Thomas Aquinas. But the consciousness
of the trichotomy got lost more and more to the Christian science which cared
for psychology above all in the Middle Ages. At the appearance of science in
the 15th and 16th centuries one no longer had a consciousness of the old division.
Even Descartes made a distinction only between soul, which he calls mind, and
body. This remained that way. Those who speak of psychology today do not know
that they speak under the influence of a Christian dogma. One believes —
you can read it in the manuals — that the human being consists only of
body and soul. One has only reproduced an ancient prejudice, and one is based
on it still today. This will appear to us in the course of these talks.
We have to show above all which
relation between soul and body the unbiased psychologist has to assume; for
it seems to be a result of modern natural sciences that one should no longer
speak of the soul as one did it for thousands of years before our time. The
physical research which pressed its stamp onto the 19th century and its mental
development explained again and again that a science of the soul in the old
sense of the word — as for example that of Goethe and partially of Aristotle
— is not compatible with its views and is not tenable, therefore. You
can take manuals about psychology or The Riddles of the World by Haeckel.
You will find everywhere that the dogmatic prejudices exist and that one has
the opinion that the old points of view under which one tried to approach the
soul are overcome. Nobody can revere Haeckel — I say this for the scientists
and the admirers of Ernst Haeckel — as a great man of science more than
I myself. But great human beings also have big shortcomings, and thus it may
be my task to test a prejudice of our time quite impartially.
What is said to us from this side?
One says to us: what you called soul disappeared under our hands. We naturalists
have shown that any sensation, everything that develops as conceptual life,
any thinking, any willing, any feeling that everything is tied to particular
organs of our brain and our nervous system. Natural sciences of the 19th century
showed, one says, that certain parts of our cerebral cortex unless they are
completely intact make it impossible to us to accomplish certain mental manifestations.
From that one concludes that in these parts of our brain the mental manifestations
are located that they are dependent, as one says, on these parts of our brain.
One has expressed this drastically saying: a certain point of the brain is the
centre of speech, another part of this soul activity, another part of another
activity, so that one can tear down the soul bit by bit.
One has shown that the illness of
particular cerebral parts is connected with the loss of particular soul abilities
at the same time. What one imagined as soul since millennia, no naturalist can
find this; this is a concept with which the naturalist cannot do anything. We
find the body and its functions, but nowhere a soul. The great moralist of Darwinism,
Bartholomäus Carneri who has written an ethics of Darwinism expressed his
conviction clearly as it can never be given more clearly by these circles of
the naturalists. He says: we take a clock. The pointers advance, the clockwork
is in movement. All that happens because of the mechanism which is before us.
As we have in that which the clock accomplishes a manifestation of the clock
mechanism, in the same way we have in that which the human being feels, thinks
and wills a manifestation of the whole nervous mechanism before us.
Just as little one can assume that
a small soul-being is in the clock which moves the cog wheels, the pointers,
just as little we can suppose that a soul exists outside the organism which
causes thinking, feeling and willing. — This is the confession of a naturalist
in mental respect; it is that which the naturalists have made the basis of a
new faith, such a pure naturalistic religion. The naturalist believes that he
is forced to this confession by the results of science and he believes that
he is allowed to regard everybody as a childish mind who does not conclude this
way under the influence of science. Bartholomäus Carneri showed it without
any whitewash. As long as the human beings were children, they have spoken like
Aristotle; because they have grown up now and understand science, they must
leave the childish views. The view of the naturalists, which regards the human
being as nothing else than a mechanism, corresponds to the metaphor of the clock.
Drastically expressed, this view is considered as the only one which is worthy
of the present. It is shown in such a way that the scientific discoveries of
the age force us to these confessions.
However, we have to ask ourselves:
did the natural sciences, the precise investigation of our nervous system, the
precise investigation of our organs and their functions really force us to this
view? No, because in the 18th century everything that one gives as something
scientific and authoritative today was still in the germ. There was nothing
of modern psychology, nothing of the discoveries of the great Johannes Müller
and his school, nothing of the discoveries which the naturalists made in the
19th century.
At that time, in the 18th century,
these views were expressed in the most radical way in the French Enlightenment
which could not rely on natural sciences, the words sounded for the first time:
the human being is a machine. — A book by Holbach comes from this time,
entitled: Système de la nature, about which Goethe said that
he felt rejected by its superficiality and triviality. This as proof of the
fact that this view existed before the modern natural sciences. One is allowed
to say that on the contrary the materialism of the 18th century hovered over
the minds of the 19th century and that the materialistic creed was setting the
tone for the way of thinking which one then brought into the natural sciences.
That with regard to the historical truth. If it were not in such a way, one
would have to call the view a childish one which the modern natural sciences
has, namely that one cannot speak of the soul in the old sense because one can
tear down the soul in the same way as one can tear down the brain.
What did one gain especially with
this view? No soul-researcher who tries to recognise the soul according to Aristotle,
according to the old Greeks, or — we say in spite of all contradiction
which approach from some sides — according to the Christian Middle Ages
can take offence of the truths of modern natural sciences. Every reasonable
soul-researcher agrees to that which the natural sciences say about the nervous
system and the brain as the mediators of our soul functions. He is not surprised
that one can no longer speak if a certain part of the brain falls ill. The old
researcher is no longer surprised with that like with the fact that he can no
longer think after he has been killed.
Modern science does nothing else
than to determine in detail what the human beings have already understood on
the whole. Just as the human being knows that he cannot speak without certain
cerebral parts, cannot form ideas, it would be a proof that he has no soul if
he could be killed. Also the Vedantists, also Plato and others are clear to
themselves about the fact that the soul activity of the human being stops if
a big fieldstone falls on his head and smashes him. The old psychology did not
teach anything different. We can be aware of that. We can accept the whole natural
sciences and form psychology differently. During former centuries one realised
that the way which the natural sciences took does not lead to the knowledge
of the soul and can also not be taken, hence, to its disproof.
If those who try to disprove the
old psychology from the standpoint of science were well-versed in former lines
of thought, if people were not yet so prejudiced in the external life, then
they could realise that they tilt at windmills like once Don Quixote to combat
psychology in this scientific sense.
This whole fight is already shown
in a conversation which you find in the Buddhist literature, in a conversation
which does not belong to the sermons of Buddha himself which was written down
only some years before Christ. Somebody who investigates the conversation sees
that it concerns the oldest real views of Buddhism which find expression in
the discussion of the King Milinda equipped with Greek wisdom and dialectic
with the Buddhist sage Nagasena. This king steps to the Indian sage and asks:
who are you? — The sage Nagasena answers: one calls me Nagasena. But this
is only a name. No subject, no personality is contained in it. — How?
King Milinda said who held the Greek dialectic and the whole ability and power
of Greek thinking in himself — listen to me who you have come along, the
sage states that nothing is behind the name Nagasena. What is then that which
stands there before me? Are your hands, your legs Nagasena? No. Is your sensations,
feelings and ideas Nagasena? No, all this is not Nagasena. Then the connection
of that is Nagasena. But, because he states now that everything is not Nagasena
that only a name is there which holds together everything, who and what is Nagasena,
actually? Is that nothing which is behind the brain, behind the organs, behind
the body, behind the feelings and ideas? Is that nothing who does others a few
favours? Is somebody nothing who does the good and the bad? Is somebody nothing
who strives for holiness? Is nothing behind that all but the sheer name? —
There Nagasena answered using another metaphor: how have you come, great king,
on foot or carriage? — The king answered: on carriage. — Now, explain
the carriage to me. Is the shaft your carriage? Are the wheels your carriage?
Is the carriage box your carriage? — No, answers the king. — What
is then your carriage? It is a name which refers only to the connection of the
different parts.
What did the sage Nagasena want
to say who grew up in Buddhism? — O king, you who have gained an immense
ability in Greece, in the Greek philosophy you must understand that you come
to anything else than to a name if you consider the parts of the carriage in
their connection as little as if you hold together the parts of the human being.
Take this ancient teaching which
can be traced back to the oldest times of the Buddhist world view and ask yourselves
what is said in it? Nothing else than that the way of recognising the soul by
looking at the external organs or at the interplay of ideas is a wrong track.
By the way, the great anatomist Metchnikoff reckoned that
the ideas are a milliard. In terms of this correct saying of the sage Nagasena
we cannot find the soul that way. This is a wrong way. One never tried to approach
the soul that way in the times in which one knew on which way one has to find
the soul and to study it. It was a historical necessity that the fine, intimate
ways on which still the sages of the Christian Middle Ages looked for the soul
receded a little bit into the background when our natural sciences started to
take up the external world. Which methods and viewpoints did the natural sciences
develop in particular?
You can find in the posthumous works
of one of the most ingenious naturalists of our immediate present who has done
great discoveries in the field of the theory of electricity that the modern
natural sciences have taken up the cause of simplicity and usefulness. You can
find that a psychologist who also works for the purposes of natural sciences
still added descriptiveness to these two demands of simplicity and usefulness.
One can say that natural sciences really worked miracles by this three —
simplicity, usefulness and descriptiveness. But this is not applicable to the
soul being. Using descriptiveness with regard to the examination of the external
members, using usefulness with regard to the outer appearance the natural sciences
were induced to look for the connection of the parts, to calculate, to investigate
them. However, it was just that which can never lead to the soul according to
the sage Nagasena. Because the natural sciences have taken this way, it is only
too comprehensible that they have left the ways of the soul. Today one does
not even have a consciousness of that which soul researchers have for centuries
striven for.
Which fairy tales are told in this
regard and which sum of ignorance comes to light, if today one speaks in apparently
authoritative circles about the teaching of Aristotle or about that of the first
Christian researchers, about that of the Middle Ages. Nevertheless if anybody
wants to understand the being of the soul academically, there is no other access
than that of the careful inner work to learn the ideas of Aristotle, the ideas
which have led the first Christians and the great Christian Church Fathers to
the knowledge of the soul. There is no other method. It is as important for
this field as the method of the natural sciences for the external science. But
these methods of psychology have got lost to us to a large extent. Really inner
observations are not regarded as an academic field.
The theosophical movement has made
it its job to investigate the ways of the soul again. In the most different
kind the access to the soul can be found. In other talks I tried, on purely
spiritual-scientific way, to give the knowledge of the soul by means of purely
theosophical method. Here, however, should be spoken at first how Aristotle
founded his psychology at the end of the great Greek philosophical epoch. For
in former times the wisdom of the soul was cultivated unlike by Aristotle. We
understand how the wisdom of the soul was cultivated in the ancient Egyptian
wisdom, was cultivated in the ancient Veda wisdom. This, however, for later.
Today you allow me to speak of the psychology of Aristotle who completed as
a scholar centuries before Christ what has been found on quite different ways.
We may say that we have something in the of Aristotle’s doctrine of the
soul that the best in the fields of psychology were able to give. Because Aristotle
gives the best, one has to speak about Aristotle above all. Nevertheless, this
gigantic mind of his time — his writings is a treasury with regard to
the knowledge of the ancient time, and somebody who becomes engrossed in Aristotle
knows what was performed before his time — this gigantic mind was not
clairvoyant like Plato, he was a scientist. Somebody who wants to get closer
to the soul academically has to do it on the way of Aristotle. Aristotle is
a personality who gives satisfaction to the demands of scientific thinking in
every respect — if one takes the epoch into consideration. As we will
see, in one single point he does not. This only point in which we find Aristotle’s
doctrine of the soul dissatisfactory became the big disaster of all scientific
psychology of the West.
Aristotle was a scientific teacher
of development. He stood completely on the standpoint of the theory of evolution.
He supposed that all beings have developed in strictly scientific necessity.
He let the most imperfect beings still arise from abiogenesis, by mere meeting
of lifeless physical substances, in purely natural way. This is a hypothesis
which is an important scientific bone of contention, but a hypothesis which
Haeckel has in common with Aristotle. Haeckel also shares the conviction of
Aristotle that a direct ladder leads up to the human being. Aristotle also encloses
any soul development in this development and is convinced that there is not
a radical, but only a gradual difference between soul and body. That means that
Aristotle is convinced that during the development of the imperfect to the perfect
the moment happens when the level is reached that everything lifeless has found
its creation, and then the possibility is there that the soul element comes
into being from the lifeless by itself. He gradually distinguishes a so-called
plant soul which lives in the whole plant world, an animal soul which lives
in the animal realm, and, finally, a higher level of this animal soul which
lives in the human being. You see that the really understood Aristotle agrees
completely with everything that modern natural sciences teach. Now, take The
Riddles of the World by Haeckel, the first pages where he stands on the
ground of the right physical laws, and compare that with the natural sciences
and the psychology of Aristotle, you will find that a real difference does not
exist if you subtract the difference given by the time.
But now this comes where Aristotle
goes beyond the psychology to which the modern natural sciences believe to have
come. There Aristotle shows that he is able to observe real inner life. If anybody
follows with deep understanding what Aristotle now builds up on this physical-lawful
theory of knowledge sees that all people have simply not understood this view
in the true sense of the word who argue anything against this view of Aristotle.
It is infinitely easy to realise that we have to do an immense step from the
animal soul to the human soul. It is infinitely easy to understand that. Nothing
else prevents one from doing this step together with Aristotle than the ways
of thinking which formed in the course of modern mental development. For Aristotle
is clear to himself about the fact that something appears within the human soul
that differs substantially from everything that is found as a soul element outside.
Already the old Pythagoreans said, by the way, that somebody who realises the
truth that the human being is the only being which can learn to count knows
in which respect the human being differs from the animal. But it is not so easy
to see what it means, actually, that only the human being can learn to count.
The Greek sage Plato did not admit
anybody to his philosophers’ school who had not learnt mathematics first,
at least the elements, the ABC. That means: Plato wanted nothing else than that
those whom he introduced in the science of the soul know something about the
nature of the mathematical, know something about the nature of this peculiar
mental activity which the human being exercises if he does mathematics. However,
this is clear also to Aristotle that it does not depend on doing mathematics
rather than on understanding: the human being is able to do mathematics.
That is nothing else than that the
human being is able to discover strictly self-contained laws which no external
world can give him. Only those who are not trained in thinking, only those who
do not know to achieve introspection only do not realise that even the simplest
mathematical theorem could never be gained by mere observation. In nature nowhere
is a real circle, in nature nowhere is a real straight line, nowhere an ellipse,
but in mathematics we investigate these, and we apply the world which we have
gained from our inside to the outside. Unless we think this fact through, we
can never come to a true view of the being of the soul.
That is why theosophy requires a
strict training of thinking from its students who want to get involved deeper;
not the will-o’-the-wisp thinking of the everyday life, not the will-o’-the-wisp
thinking of the western philosophy, but the thinking which practices introspection
in inner thoroughness. This thinking reveals the far-reaching scope of this
sentence. Those who had the biggest conquests in astronomy by their mathematical
training realise the far-reaching scope and express it. Read the writings by
Kepler, this great astronomer, read through what he says about this basic phenomenon
of human introspection, then you see what this personality expresses about that.
He knew which far-reaching scope mathematical thinking has up to the most distant
galaxies. He says: the correspondence is miraculous which we find only from
our thinking when we sat in our lonesome study room and pondered over circles
and ellipses, and then look up at the sky and find their correspondence with
the heavenly spheres. — Such teaching is not a matter of external research,
but it concerns a deepening of such knowledge. Already in the vestibule it should
appear with those who wanted to be accepted in the philosophers’ school
who of them could be admitted. For one knew then that — like those who
have their five senses can investigate the outer world — they can investigate
also the being of the soul by thinking. This was not sooner possible.
But one demanded something else.
The mathematical thinking does not suffice. It is the first step where we completely
live in ourselves where the spirit of the world develops from our inside. It
is the most trivial, the most subordinate step which we must climb up first
above which we have to go, however. Just the soul researcher of olden times
demanded to get the highest levels of human knowledge out of the depths of the
soul in the same way as mathematics gets out the truth of the starry heaven
out of the depths of the soul. This was the demand which Plato hid in the sentence:
everybody who wants to enter into my school must have gone through a mathematical
course first. — Not mathematics is necessary, but a knowledge which has
the independence of the mathematical thinking. If one sees that the human being
has a life in himself which is independent of the external physical life that
he must get the highest truth out of himself, then one also sees that the best
effectiveness of the human being reaches to something that is beyond any physical
activity.
Have a look at the animal. Its activity
runs purely according to its type. Any animal does what countless of its ancestors
have also done. The type controls the animal completely. Tomorrow it does the
same what it did yesterday. The ant builds its miracle construction, the beaver
its lodge, in ten, hundred, thousand years as well as today. Development is
also in it, but not history. Who realises that the human development is not
only a development, but history, is able to become clear to himself about the
method of soul observation in similar way as somebody who has realised what
mathematical truth is. There are still savage people. Indeed, they become extinct,
but there are still those who can recognise no connection between today and
tomorrow. There are those who cover themselves with leaves of trees if it gets
cold in the evening. In the morning they throw them away and in the evening
they have to look for them again. They are not able to transfer the experience
of yesterday to today and tomorrow. What is necessary if we want to transfer
the experience of yesterday to today and tomorrow? We cannot say if today we
know what we have done yesterday, then tomorrow we will also do what we have
done yesterday. This is a characteristic of the animal soul. It can progress,
it can become something else in the course of times, but then this transformation
is not something historical. History consists in the fact that the individual
human being uses that which he has experienced in such a way that he can conclude
on something non-experienced, on a tomorrow.
I learn the sense, the spirit of
yesterday and rely on the fact that the laws which my soul gains from observation
are also valid in that which I have not yet observed, in future. Travellers
tell us that it happened that any travellers made fires for themselves in regions
where monkeys lived. They went away, let the fire burn and left the wood. The
monkeys approached and warmed themselves up at the fire. But they could not
poke the fire. They cannot make themselves independent of the observations and
experiences, they cannot conclude. The human being infers from his observations
and experiences and becomes the authoritarian determiner of his future. He sends
his experiences to tomorrow, he transforms development into history. As well
as he transforms experience into theory, as well as he gets the truth of the
spirit out of nature, he gets the rules of the future out of the past and becomes
the creator of the future that way. Somebody who thinks through these two things
thoroughly — that the human being can make himself independent in double
way that he can not only observe, but also put up theories that he does not
have development like the animal soul but also history — gets these two
things clear in his mind and understands what I meant when I said that in the
human being lives not only the animal soul, but the animal soul develops so
far that it can take up the so-called nous (Greek), the universal spirit.
Aristotle regards that as necessary,
so that the human being can form history, that the universal spirit sinks into
the animal soul. The soul of the human being differs in the sense of Aristotle
from the animal soul because it was raised from that for what it rose within
the animal development up to the functions and activities by which it has acquired
the spirit. The saying of the great Kepler that the laws won in a lonesome study
room are applicable to the external natural phenomena can be explained through
the fact that the universal spirit, the nous, the Mahat, sinks into the human
soul and raises it up to a higher level. The human soul is lifted out of the
animal being as it were. It is the spirit which lifts it out. The spirit lives
in the soul. It develops from the soul. It develops in such a way as the soul
lifts itself out of the body gradually.
However, Aristotle did not or not
clearly say this. Indeed, he says repeatedly: the soul develops gradually up
to the human soul in a quite natural way — but now the spirit comes from
without into this naturally developed human soul. Nous is something in the sense
of Aristotle that is put into the human soul from without by creative activity.
This became the disaster of the western science of the soul. It is a disaster
of Aristotle that he is not able to make his right view that the human soul
is lifted up while the nous sinks into it a theory of the historical course.
He cannot understand this development as natural as the development of the soul
is to be understood. Already Greek and Indian sages did this. They understood
body, soul and mind developing naturally to the human mind. There is a break
with Aristotle. He adds the idea of creation to the view. We will see how the
theosophical psychology overcomes this idea of creation how it draws the last
consequences of the scientific world view, indeed, from the spiritual standpoint
in the true sense.
But only while we get clear in our
mind that we must return to the old division in body, soul and mind we really
understand this natural development of the human being. However, we must not
believe that we can find access to the soul one day on the apparently irrefutable
ways cultivated by modern natural sciences, by observing the single parts of
the brain. We have to realise that the objections of the Indian sage Nagasena
also apply to the modern naturalistic psychology. We have to realise above all
that a deeper, internal introspection, a deeper spiritual research is necessary
to find access to soul and mind. One would form a wrong idea of those who believe
that the different religions and the different sages who came from the different
religions have said what the modern natural sciences try to disprove. They have
never said this, have never tried this. Who follows the development of psychology
can see clearly that those who have known something of the methods of psychology
have never applied the methods of natural sciences, so that they had to disprove
them. These cannot find to the soul. O no, on this way the soul researchers
who have still known what a soul is have never sought for the soul.
I want to mention somebody, the
most scorned of enlighteners whom one also knows least. I want to speak with
a few words about the psychology of the 13th century, about the psychology of
Thomas Aquinas. It belongs to the typical qualities of this doctrine of the
soul that the author says: what the human mind takes when it leaves this body,
what the human mind takes into the purely spiritual world this can no longer
be compared with everything that the human being experiences within his body.
Yes, Thomas Aquinas says that the task of the religion in its most ideal sense
consists in educating the human being, so that he can take something from this
body that is not sensory that is not tied to investigation, to consideration
and experience of the outer nature. As long as we live in this body, we see
through our eyes and hear through our ears something sensory. We perceive everything
sensory by means of our senses. But the spirit processes this sensory. The spirit
is the actually active. The spirit is the eternal. Now take into consideration
the deep view which was won there on account of the thousands of years old teaching
of the soul which expresses itself in the words: that spirit which has collected
a little during this life which is independent of external sensory observation,
independent of external sensory life is not happy when it is disembodied. Thomas
Aquinas says: what we see in our sensory surroundings is filled perpetually
with sensory phantasms.
However, the spirit — I have
described it as the spirit of mathematics as nous which results easily like
tomorrow results from yesterday and today — this spirit freeing itself
collects fruits for eternity. The spirit feels endlessly isolated and void —
this is the teaching of Thomas Aquinas — if it enters the spiritland without
having advanced so far that it is free of any phantasm of the sensory world.
The deep sense of the Greek myth of drinking from the Lethe River reveals itself
to us as a thought: the spirit in its purely spiritual existence progresses
higher and higher, the more it frees itself of any sensory phantasm. Who searches
the spirit as something sense-perceptible cannot find it; for the spirit if
it has become free of sensuality has no longer anything to do with sensuality.
Thomas Aquinas considered the methods as totally unacceptable with which it
is searched for sensually. This church teacher is an adversary of any experiment
and attempt to get contact with the dead sensually. The spirit must be purest
if it is free of sensual phantasms and sticking to sensuality. Otherwise, it
feels in the spiritual world endlessly isolated. The spirit which depends on
the sensory observation, which is wrapped up in sensory observations, lives
in the spiritual world like in an unknown world. This isolation is its destiny
because it has not learnt to be free of sensual phantasms. We completely penetrate
that when we come to the second talk.
You see that one searched for the
soul just in the opposite way in the times in which the inner observation, the
observation of that which lives inside the human being was the decisive factor
for the soul science. This fundamental error lives in the modern psychology
and has led to broadcast the catchword of the psychology without soul as a naturalistic
creed of the 19th century. This science which strives only for the external
views believes to be able to disprove the old views. But this science knows
nothing about the ways on which the soul was searched for. Nothing, not the
slightest objection should be said against modern science. On the contrary,
we want to explore the realm of the soul even as theosophists in terms of this
modern science in such a way as this explores the realm of the purely spatial
nature. However, we want to search for the soul not in the outer nature but
in our inside. We want to search for the spirit where it reveals itself, while
we walk on the ways of the soul and get spirit knowledge from soul knowledge.
This is the way prescribed by teachings thousands of years old which one only
has to understand in its truth and validity.
However, this also becomes clear
to us and becomes clearer and clearer what the deeper human being if he wants
to recognise the soul also misses just in the modern cold science like Goethe
missed it when he met this cold science in the Système de la nature
by Holbach. Indeed, we can observe in the outer nature how the human being has
developed concerning his external appearance how he has become how the monad
works in the finer structures how the middle organ system can be regarded as
an expression of the soul, but all that leads us only to the knowledge of the
external appearance. The big question of the human destiny still remains. No
matter how well we have understood a human being with regard to his external
appearance, we have not understood him in so far as he has this or that destiny
in this or that way, we have not understood which role the good and the bad,
the perfect and imperfect play. What the human being experiences inside, about
that the external science can give us no explanation; about that only the soul
science which is based on introspection can give us a reasonable answer. Then
the big questions arise: where do we come from, where do we go, what is our
goal? — These biggest questions of all religions. These questions, which
can raise the human being to sublime mood, will transport us from the soul-world
to the spirit, to the divine spirit flowing through the world. The contents
of the next lecture must be: through the soul to the spirit. This will show
us that it is absolutely true — not only a pictorial expression —
that also the perfect animal soul, which originated through solely external
development, became only the human soul because it constitutes something even
higher, more perfect, and that it is entitled to bear the germ of something
still higher, of something unlimitedly perfect in itself. This human soul has
to be regarded as something that does not produce the spirit and the phenomena
of the soul from the animal realm, but that the animal in the human being must
develop to higher levels to receive its vocation, its task and also its destiny.
The medieval teaching of the soul
expresses that with the words that only he recognises the truth in the real
sense who considers it not as it appears to him if he hears with external ears,
looks with external eyes, but in such a way as it appears if we see it in the
reflection of the highest spirit. That is why I may close the first lecture
with the words which Thomas Aquinas used in his lecture: the human soul is just
like the moon which shines, but receives its light from the sun. — The
human soul is just like the water which is not cold and not warm in itself,
but receives its heat from the fire. — The human soul is just like a higher
animal soul only, but it is a human soul because it receives its light from
the human mind.
In accordance with this medieval
conviction Goethe says:
The human soul
Resembles the water:
It comes from the heaven,
It rises to the heaven,
And again down
To the earth it has to go,
Forever changing.
Then one understands the human soul if one conceives it in this sense that
it is understood as a reflection of the highest being which we can find everywhere
in the cosmos, as a reflection of the world spirit flowing through the universe.
Notes:
Élie
Metchnikoff (1845–1916), Russian biologist
|