The New Spirituality
and the Christ Expereience of the Twentieth Century
1st Lecture
Historical Symptomology, the Year 790, Alcuin, Greeks, Platonism,
Aristotelianism, East, West, Middle, Ego
Dornach,
17 October 1920
In the lectures given here during the course on
history
[1]
several things were mentioned which, particularly at the present
time, it is especially important to consider. With regard to the historical course of humanity's
development, the much-debated question mentioned to begin with was whether the outstanding and
leading individual personalities are the principal driving forces in this development or whether
the most important things are brought about by the masses. In many circles this has always been a
point of contention and the conclusions have been drawn, more from sympathy and antipathy than
from real knowledge. This is one fact which, in a certain sense, I should like to mention as
being very important.
Another fact which, from a look at history, I
should like to mention for its importance is the following. At the beginning of the nineteenth
century Wilhelm von Humboldt
[2]
appeared with a definite declaration,
stipulating that history should be treated in such a way that one would not only consider the
individual facts which can be outwardly observed in the physical world but, out of an
encompassing, synthesizing force, would see what is at work in the unfolding of history —
which can only be found by someone who knows how to get a total view of the facts in what in a
sense is a poetic way, but in fact produces a true picture. Attention was also drawn to how in
the course of the nineteenth century it was precisely the opposite historical mode of thought and
approach which was then particularly developed, and that it was not the ideas in history that
were pursued but only a sense that was developed for the external world of facts. Attention was
also drawn to the fact that, with regard to this last question, one can only come to clarity
through spiritual science, because spiritual science alone can uncover the real driving forces of
the historical evolution of humanity.
A spiritual science of this kind was not yet
accessible to Humboldt. He spoke of ideas, but ideas indeed have no driving force
[of their own].
Ideas as such are abstractions, as I mentioned here yesterday
[3]
And anyone who
might wish to find ideas as the driving forces of history would never be able to prove that ideas
really do anything because they are nothing of real substantiality, and only something of
substantiality can do something. Spiritual science points to real spiritual forces that are
behind the sensible-physical facts, and it is in real spiritual forces such as these that the
propelling forces of history lie, even though these spiritual forces will have to be expressed
for human beings through ideas.
But we come to clarity concerning these things only
when, from a spiritual-scientific standpoint, we look more deeply into the historical development
of humanity and we will do so today in such a way that, through our considerations, certain facts
come to us which, precisely for a discerning judgement of the situation of modern humanity, will
prove to be of importance.
I have often mentioned
[4]
that
spiritual science, if it looks at history, would actually have to pursue a symptomatology; a
symptomatology constituted from the fact that one is aware that behind what takes it course as
the stream of physical-sensible facts lie the driving spiritual forces. But everywhere in
historical development there are times when what has real being and essence
(das eigentlich Wesenhafte)
comes as a symptom to the surface and can be judged discerningly from the
phenomena only if one has the possibility to penetrate more deeply from one's awareness of these
phenomena into the depths of historical development.
I would like to clarify this by a simple diagram.
Let us suppose that this is a flow of historical facts (see diagram). The driving forces lie, for
ordinary observation, below the flow of these facts. And if the eye of the soul observes the flow
in this way, then the real activity of the driving forces would lie beneath it (red). But there
are significant points in this flow of facts. And these significant points are distinguished by
the fact that what is otherwise hidden comes here to the surface. Thus we can say: Here, in a
particular phenomenon, which must only be properly evaluated, it was possible to become aware of
something which otherwise is at work everywhere, but which does not show itself in such a
significant manifestation.
Let us assume that this (see diagram) took place in
some year of world history, let us say around 800 AD What was significant for Europe, let us
say for Western Europe, was of course at work before this and worked on afterwards, but it did
not manifest itself in such a significant way in the time before and after as it did here. If one
points to a way of looking at history like this, a way which looks to significant moments, such a
method would be in complete accord with Goetheanism. For
Goethe
wished in general that all
perception of the world should be directed to significant points and then, from what could be
seen from such points, the remaining content of world events be recognized. Goethe says of
this
[5]
that, within the abundance of facts, the important thing is to find a
significant point from which the neighbouring areas can be viewed and from which much can be
deciphered.
So let us take this year 800 AD We can point here
to a fact in the history of Western European humanity which, from the point of view of the usual
approach to history, might seem insignificant — which one would perhaps not find worthy of
attention for what is usually called history — but which, nevertheless, for a deeper view
of humanity's development, is indeed significant. Around this year there was a kind of learned
theological argument between the man who was a sort of court philosopher of the Frankish realm,
Alcuin
[6],
and a Greek also living at that time in the kingdom of the Franks. The
Greek, who was naturally at home in the particular soul-constitution of the Greek peoples which
he had inherited, had wanted to reach a discerning judgement of the principles of Christianity
and had come to the concept of redemption. He put the question: To whom, in the redemption
through Christ Jesus, was the ransom actually paid? He, the Greek thinker, came to the solution
that the ransom had been paid to Death. Thus, in a certain sense, it was a sort of redemption
theory that this Greek developed from his thoroughly Greek mode of thinking, which was now just
becoming acquainted with Christianity. The ransom was paid to Death by the cosmic powers.
Alcuin, who stood at that time in that theological
stream which then became the determining one for the development of the Roman Catholic Church of
the West, debated in the following way about what the Greek had argued. He said: Ransom can only
be paid to a being who really exists. But death has no reality, death is only the outer limit of
reality, death itself is not real and, therefore, the ransom money could not have been paid to
Death.
Now criticism of Alcuin's way of thinking is not
what matters here. For to someone who, to a certain extent, can see through the interrelations of
the facts, the view that death is not something real resembles the view which says: Cold is not
something real, it is just a decrease in warmth, it is only a lesser warmth. Because the cold
isn't real I won't wear a winter coat in winter because I'm not going to protect myself against
something that isn't real. But we will leave that aside. We want rather to take the argument
between Alcuin and the Greek purely positively and will ask what was really happening there. For
it is indeed quite noticeable that it is not the concept of redemption itself that is discussed.
It is not discussed in such a way that in a certain sense both personalities, the Greek and the
Roman Catholic theologian, accept the same point of view, but in such a way that the Roman
Catholic theologian shifts the standpoint entirely before he takes it up at all. He does not go
on speaking in the way he had just done, but moves the whole problem into a completely different
direction. He asks: Is death something real or not? — and objects that, indeed, death is
not real.
This directs us at the outset to the fact that two
views are clashing here which arise out of completely different constitutions of soul. And,
indeed, this is the case. The Greek continued, as it were, the direction which, in the Greek
culture, had basically faded away between
Plato
and
Aristotle.
In Plato there was still something
alive of the ancient wisdom of humanity; that wisdom which takes us across to the ancient Orient
where, indeed, in ancient times a primal wisdom had lived but which had then fallen more and more
into decadence. In Plato, if we are able to understand him properly, we find the last offshoots,
if I can so call them, of this primal oriental wisdom. And then, like a rapidly developing
metamorphosis, Aristotelianism sets in which, fundamentally, presents a completely different
constitution of soul from the Platonic one. Aristotelianism represents a completely different
element in the development of humanity from Platonism. And, if we follow Aristotelianism further,
it, too, takes on different forms, different metamorphoses, but all of which have a recognizable
similarity. Thus we see how Platonism lives on like an ancient heritage in this Greek who has to
contend against Alcuin, and how in Alcuin, on the other hand, Aristotelianism is already present.
And we are directed, by looking at these two individuals, to that fluctuation which took place on
European soil between two — one cannot really say world-views — but two human
constitutions of soul, one of which has its origin in ancient times in the Orient, and another,
which we do not find in the Orient but which, entering in later, arose in the central regions of
civilization and was first grasped by Aristotle. In Aristotle, however, this only sounds a first
quiet note, for much of Greek culture was still alive in him. It develops then with particular
vehemence in the Roman culture within which it had been prepared long before Aristotle, and,
indeed, before Plato. So that we see how, since the eighth century BC on the Italian peninsula
a particular culture, or the first hints of it, was being prepared alongside that which lived on
the Greek peninsula as a sort of last offshoot of the oriental constitution of soul. And when we
go into the differences between these two modes of human thought we find important historical
impulses. For what is expressed in these ways of thinking went over later into the feeling life
of human beings; into the configuration of human actions and so on.
Now we can ask ourselves: So what was living in
that which developed in ancient times as a world-view in the Orient, and which then, like a
latecomer, found its
[last]
offshoots in Platonism — and, indeed, still in Neoplatonism? It
was a highly spiritual culture which arose from an inner perception living pre-eminently in
pictures, in imaginations; but pictures not permeated by full consciousness, not yet permeated by
the full I-consciousness of human beings. In the spiritual life of the ancient Orient, of which
the Veda and Vedanta are the last echoes, stupendous pictures opened up of what lives in the
human being as the spiritual. But it existed in a — I beg you not to misunderstand the word
and not to confuse it with usual dreaming — it existed in a dreamlike, dim way, so that
this soul-life was not permeated
(durchwellt)
and irradiated
(durchstrahlt)
by what lives in the human being when he becomes clearly conscious of his 'I' and his own being. The
oriental was well aware that his being existed before birth, that it returns through death to the
spiritual world in which it existed before birth or conception. The oriental gazed on that which
passed through births and deaths. But he did not see as such that inner feeling which lives in
the `I am'. It was as if it were dull and hazy, as though poured out in a broad perception of the
soul
(Gesamtseelenanschauung)
which did not concentrate to such a point as that of the I-experience. Into what, then, did the
oriental actually gaze when he possessed his instinctive perception?
One can still feel how this oriental
soul-constitution was completely different from that of later humanity when, for an understanding
of this and perhaps prepared through spiritual science, one sinks meditatively into those
remarkable writings which are ascribed to
Dionysius the Areopagite.
[7]
I will not go into the question of the authorship now, I have already spoken about it on a number
of occasions. 'Nothingness'
(das Nichts)
is still spoken of there as a reality, and the existence of the external world, in the way one
views it in ordinary consciousness, is simply contrasted against this
[nothingness]
as a different reality. This talk of nothingness then
continues. In Scotus Erigena,
[8]
who lived at the court of Charles the Bald, one
still finds echoes of it, and we find the last echo then in the fifteenth century in Nicolas of
Cusa
[9]
But what was meant by the nothingness one finds in Dionysius the
Areopagite and of that which the oriental spoke of as something self-evident to him? This fades
then completely. What was this nothingness for the oriental? It was something real for him. He
turned his gaze to the world of the senses around him, and said: This sense-world is spread out
in space, flows in time, and in ordinary life world, is spread out in space, one says that what
is extended in space and flows in time is
something.
But what the oriental saw — that which was a
reality for him, which passes through births and deaths — was not contained in the space in
which the minerals are to be found, in which the plants unfold, the animals move and the human
being as a physical being moves and acts. And it was also not contained in that time in which our
thoughts, feelings and will-impulses occur. The oriental was fully aware that one must go beyond
this space in which physical things are extended and move, and beyond this time in which our
soul-forces of ordinary life are active. One must enter a completely different world; that world
which, for the external existence of time and space, is a nothing but which, nevertheless, is
something real. The oriental sensed something in contrast to the phenomena of the world which the
European still senses at most in the realm of real numbers.
When a European has fifty francs he has something.
If he spends twenty-five francs of this he still has twenty-five francs; if he then spends
fifteen francs he still has ten; if he spends this he has nothing. If now he continues to spend
he has five, ten, fifteen, twenty-five francs in debts. He still has nothing; but, indeed, he has
something very real when, instead of simply an empty wallet, he has twenty-five or fifty francs
in debts. In the real world it also signifies something very real if one has debts. There is a
great difference in one's whole situation in life between having nothing and having fifty francs'
worth of debts. These debts of fifty francs are forces just as influential on one's situation in
life as, on the other side and in an opposite sense, are fifty francs of credit. In this area the
European will probably admit to the reality of debts for, in the real world, there always has to
be something there when one has debts. The debts that one has oneself may still seem a very
negative amount, but for the person to whom they are owed they are a very positive amount!
So, when it is not just a matter of the individual
but of the world, the opposite side of zero from the credit side is truly something very real.
The oriental felt — not because he somehow speculated about it but because his perception
necessitated it he felt: Here, on the one side, I experience that which cannot be observed in
space or in time; something which, for the things and events of space and time, is nothing but
which, nevertheless, is a reality — but a different reality.
It was only through misunderstanding that there
then arose what occidental civilization gave itself up to under the leadership of Rome —
the creation of the world out of nothing with `nothing' seen as absolute `zero'. In the Orient,
where these things were originally conceived, the world does not arise out of nothing but out of
the reality I have just indicated. And an echo of what vibrates through all the oriental way of
thinking right down to Plato — the impulse of eternity of an ancient world-view —
lived in the Greek who, at the court of Charlemagne, had to debate with Alcuin. And in this
theologian Alcuin there lived a rejection of the spiritual life for which, in the Orient, this
`nothing' was the outer form. And thus, when the Greek spoke of death, whose causes lie in the
spiritual world, as something real, Alcuin could only answer: But death is nothing and therefore
cannot receive ransom.
You see, the whole polarity between the ancient
oriental way of thinking, reaching to Plato, and what followed later is expressed in this
[one]
significant moment when Alcuin debated at the court of Charlemagne with the Greek. For, what was
it that had meanwhile entered in to European civilization since Plato, particularly through the
spread of Romanism? There had entered that way of thinking which one has to comprehend through
the fact that it is directed primarily to what the human being experiences between birth and
death. And the constitution of soul which occupies itself primarily with the human being's
experiences between birth and death is the logical, legal one — the
logical-dialectical-legal one. The Orient had nothing of a logical, dialectical nature and, least
of all, a legal one. The Occident brought logical, legal thinking so strongly into the oriental
way of thinking that we ourselves find religious feeling permeated with a legalistic element. In
the Sistine Chapel in Rome, painted by the master-hand of
Michelangelo,
we see looming towards us, Christ as judge giving judgment on the good and the evil.
A legal, dialectical element has entered into the
thoughts concerning the course of the world. This was completely alien to the oriental way of
thinking. There was nothing there like guilt and atonement or redemptinn. For
[in this oriental way of thinking]
was precisely that view of the metamorphosis through which the eternal element
[in the human being]
transforms itself through births and deaths. There was that which lives in
the concept of karma. Later, however, everything was fixed into a way of looking at things which
is actually only valid for, and can only encompass, life between birth and death. But this life
between birth and death was just what had evaded the oriental. He looked far more to the core of
man's being. He had little understanding for what took place between birth and death. And now,
within this occidental culture, the way of thinking which comprehends primarily what takes place
within the span between birth and death increased
[and did so]
through those forces possessed by
the human being by virtue of having clothed his soul-and-spirit nature with a physical and
etheric body. In this constitution, in the inner experience of the soul-and-spirit element and in
the nature of this experience, which arises through the fact that one is submerged with one's
soul-and-spirit nature in a physical body, comes the inner comprehension of the 'I'. This is why
it happens in the Occident that the human being feels an inner urge to lay hold of his 'I' as
something divine. We see this urge, to comprehend the 'I' as something divine, arise in the
medieval mystics; in
Eckhart,
in
Tauler
and in others. The comprehension of the 'I' crystallizes
out with full force in the Middle (or Central) culture. Thus we can distinguish between the
Eastern culture — the time in which the 'I' is first experienced, but dimly — and the
Middle (or Central) culture — primarily that in which the 'I' is experienced. And we see
how this 'I' is experienced in the most manifold metamorphoses. First of all in that dim, dawning
way in which it arises in Eckhart, Tauler and other mystics, and then more and more distinctly
during the development of all that can originate out of this I-culture.
We then see how, within the I-culture of the
Centre, another aspect arises. At the end of the eighteenth century something comes to the fore
in Kant
[10]
which, fundamentally, cannot be explained out of the onward flow of
this I-culture. For what is it that arises through Kant? Kant looks at our perception, our
apprehension
(Erkennen),
of nature and cannot come to terms with it. Knowledge of
nature, for him, breaks down into subjective views
( Subjektivitäten);
he does not
penetrate as far as the 'I' despite the fact that he continually speaks of it and even, in some
categories, in his perceptions of time and space, would like to encompass all nature through the
'I'. Yet he does not push through to a true experience of the 'I'. He also constructs a practical
philosophy with the categorical imperative which is supposed to manifest itself out of
unfathomable regions of the human soul. Here again the 'I' does not appear.
In Kant's philosophy it is strange. The full weight
of dialectics, of logical-dialectical-legal thinking is there, in which everything is tending
towards the 'I', but he cannot reach the point of really understanding the 'I' philosophically.
There must be something preventing him here. Then comes Fichte, a pupil of Kant's, who with full
force wishes his whole philosophy to well up out of the 'I' and who, through its simplicity,
presents as the highest tenet of his philosophy the sentence: `I am'. And everything that is
truly scientific must follow from this `I am'. One should be able, as it were, to deduce, to read
from this 'I am' an entire picture of the world. Kant cannot reach the 'I am'. Fichte immediately
afterwards, while still a pupil of Kant's, hurls the `I am' at him. And everyone is amazed
— this is a pupil of Kant's speaking like this! And Fichte says:
[11]
As
far as he can understand it, Kant, if he could really think to the end, would have to think the
same as me. It is so inexplicable to Fichte that Kant thinks differently from him, that he says:
If Kant would only take things to their full conclusion, he would have to think
[as I do];
he
too, would have to come to the 'I am'. And Fichte expresses this even more clearly by saying: I
would rather take the whole of Kant's critique for a random game of ideas haphazardly thrown
together than to consider it the work of a human mind, if my philosophy did not logically follow
from Kant's. Kant, of course, rejects this. He wants nothing to do with the conclusions drawn by
Fichte.
We now see how there follows on from Fichte what
then flowered as German idealistic philosophy in
Schelling
and
Hegel,
and which provoked all the
battles of which I spoke, in part, in my lectures on the limits to a knowledge of
nature.
[12]
But we find something curious. We see how Hegel lives in a
crystal-clear
[mental]
framework of the logical-dialectical-legal element and draws from it a
world-view — but a world-view that is interested only in what occurs between birth and
death. You can go through the whole of Hegel's philosophy and you will find nothing that goes
beyond birth and death. It confines everything in world history, religion, art and science solely
to experiences occurring between birth and death.
What then is the strange thing that happened here?
Now, what came out in Fichte, Schelling and Hegel — this strongest development of the
Central culture in which the 'I' came to full consciousness, to an inner experience — was
still only a reaction, a last reaction to something else. For one can understand Kant only when
one bears the following properly in mind. (I am coming now to yet another significant point to
which a great deal can be traced). You see, Kant was still — this is clearly evident from
his earlier writings — a pupil of the rationalism of the eighteenth century, which lived
with genius in Leibnitz and pedantically in Wolff. One can see that for this rationalism the
important thing was not to come truly to a spiritual reality. Kant therefore rejected it —
this `thing in itself' as he called it — but the important thing for him was to prove. Sure
proof! Kant's writings are remarkable also in this respect. He wrote his
Critique of Pure Reason
in which he is actually asking: `How must the world be so that things can be proved
in it?' Not 'What are the realities in it?' But he actually asks: 'How must I imagine the world
so that logically, dialectically, I can give proofs in it?' This is the only point he is
concerned with and thus he tries in his
Prologomena
to give every future metaphysics
which has a claim to being truly scientific, a metaphysics for what in his way of thinking can be
proven: `Away with everything else! The devil take the reality of the world — just let me
have the art of proving! What's it to me what reality is; if I can't prove it I shan't trouble
myself over it!'
Those individuals did not, of course, think in this
way who wrote books like, for example, Christian Wolff's
[13]
Vernünftige Gedanken von Gott, der Welt und der Seele des Menschen, auch allen Dingen
überhaupt (Reasoned Thoughts an God, the World, and the Soul of Man, and All Things
Generally).
What mattered for them was to have a clean, self-contained system of proof, in
the way that they see proof. Kant lived in this sphere, but there was still something there
which, although an excrescence squeezed out of the world-view of the Centre, nevertheless fitted
into it. But Kant had something else which makes it inexplicable how he could become Fichte's
teacher. And yet he gives Fichte a stimulus, and Fichte comes back at him with the strong
emphasis of the 'I am'; comes back, indeed, not with proofs — one would not look for these
in Fichte — but with a fully developed inner life of soul. In Fichte there emerges, with
all the force of the inner life of soul, that which, in the Wolffians and Leibnitzites, can seem
insipid. Fichte constructs his philosophy, in a wealth of pure concepts, out of the 'I am'; but
in him they are filled with life. So, too, are they in Schelling and in Hegel. So what then had
happened with Kant who was the bridge? Now, one comes to the significant point when one traces
how Kant developed. Something else became of this pupil of Wolff by virtue of the fact that the
English philosopher, David Hume,
[14]
awoke him, as Kant himself says, out of
his dull dogmatic slumber. What is it that entered Kant here, which Fichte could no longer
understand? There entered into Kant here — it fitted badly in his case because he was too
involved with the culture of Central Europe — that which is now the culture of the West.
This came to meet him in the person of David Hume and it was here that the culture of the West
entered Kant. And in what does the peculiarity
[of this culture]
lie? In the oriental culture we
find that the 'I' still lives below, dimly, in a dream-like state in the soul-experiences which
express themselves, spread out, in imaginative pictures. In the Western culture we find that, in
a certain sense, the 'I' is smothered
(erdrückt)
by the purely external phenomena
(Tatsachen).
The 'I' is indeed present, and is present not dimly, but bores itself into
the phenomena. And here, for example, people develop a strange psychology. They do not talk here
about the soul-life in the way Fichte did, who wanted to work out everything from the one point
of the 'I', but they talk about thoughts which come together by association. People talk about
feelings, mental pictures and sensations, and say these associate — and also will-impulses
associate. One talks about the inner soul-life in terms of thoughts which associate.
Fichte speaks of the 'I'; this radiates out
thoughts. In the West the 'I' is completely omitted because it is absorbed — soaked up by
the thoughts and feelings which one treats as though they were independent of it, associating and
separating again. And one follows the life of the soul as though mental pictures linked up and
separated. Read Spencer,
[15]
read John Stuart Mill
[16]
read
the American philosophers. When they come to talk of psychology there is this curious view that
does not exclude the 'I' as in the Orient, because it is developed dimly there, but which makes
full demand of the 'I'; letting it, however, sink down into the thinking, feeling and willing
life of the soul. One could say: In the oriental the 'I' is still above thinking,
feeling and willing; it has not yet descended to the level of thinking, feeling and willing. In
the human being of the Western culture the 'I' is already below this sphere. It is below
the surface of thinking, feeling and willing so that it is no longer noticed, and thinking,
feeling and willing are then spoken of as independent forces.
This is what came to Kant in the form of the philosophy of David Hume. Then
the Central region of the earth's culture still set itself against this with all force in Fichte,
Schelling, and Hegel. After them the culture of the West overwhelms everything that is there,
with Darwinism and Spencerism.
One will only be able to come to an understanding
of what is living in humanity's development if one investigates these deeper forces. One then
finds that something developed in a natural way in the Orient which actually was purely a
spiritual life. In the Central areas something developed which was dialectical-legal, which
actually brought forth the idea of the State, because it is to this that it can be applied. It is
such thinkers as Fichte, Schelling and Hegel who, with enormous sympathy, construct a unified
image (Gebilde) of the State. But then a culture emerges in the West which proceeds from
a constitution of soul in which the 'I' is absorbed, takes its course below the level of
thinking, feeling and willing; and where, in the mental and feeling life, people speak of
associations. If only one would apply this thinking to the economic life! That is its proper
place. People went completely amiss when they started applying
[this thinking]
to something other
than the economic life. There it is great, is of genius. And had Spencer, John Stuart
Mill and David Hume applied to the institutions of the economic life what they wasted on
philosophy it would have been magnificent. If the human beings living in Central Europe had
limited to the State what is given them as their natural endowment, and if they had not, at the
same time, also wanted thereby to include the spiritual life and the economic life, something
magnificent could have come out of it. For, with what Hegel was able to think, with what Fichte
was able to think, one would have been able — had one remained within the legal-political
configuration which, in the threefold organism, we wish to separate out as the structure of the
State
[17]
— to attain something truly great. But, because there hovered
before these minds the idea that they had to create a structure for the State which included the
economic life and the spiritual life, there arose only caricatures in the place of a true form
for the State. And the spiritual life was anyway only a heritage of the ancient Orient. It was
just that people did not know that they were still living from this heritage of the ancient East.
The useful statements, for example, of Christian theology — indeed, the useful statements
still within our materialistic sciences — are either the heritage of the ancient East, or a
changeling of dialectical-legal thinking, or are already adopted, as was done by Spencer and
Mill, from the Western culture which is particularly suited for the economic life.
Thus the spiritual thinking of the ancient Orient
had been distributed over the earth, but in an instinctive way that is no longer of any use
today. Because today it is decadent, it is dialectical-political thinking which was rendered
obsolete by the world catastrophe
[World War I].
For there was no one less suited to thinking
economically than the pupils of Fichte, Schelling and Hegel. When they began to create a State
which, above all, was to become great through its economy, they had of necessity
(selbstverständlich)
to fail, for this was not what, by nature, was, endowed to
them. In accordance with the historical development of humanity, spiritual thinking, political
thinking and economic thinking were apportioned to the East, the Centre, and the West
respectively. But we have arrived at a point of humanity's development when understanding, a
common understanding, must spread equally over all humanity. How can this come about?
This can only happen out of the initiation-culture,
out of the new spiritual science, which does not develop one-sidedly, but considers everything
that appears in all areas as a three-foldness that has evolved of its own accord. This science
must really consider the threefold aspect also in social life; in this case (as a three-foldness)
encompassing the whole earth. Spiritual science, however, cannot be extended through natural
abilities; it can only be spread by people accepting those who see into these things, who can
really experience the spiritual sphere, the political sphere and the economic sphere as three
separate areas. The unity of human beings all over the earth is due to the fact that they combine
in themselves what was divided between three spheres. They themselves organize it in the social
organism in such a way that it can exist in harmony before their eyes. This, however, can only
follow from spiritual-scientific training. And we stand here at a point where we must say: In
ancient times we see individual personalities, we see them expressing in their words what was the
spirit of the time. But when we examine it closely — in the oriental culture, for example
— we find that, fundamentally, there lives instinctively in the masses a constitution of
soul which in a remarkable; quite natural way was in accord with what these individuals
spoke.
This correspondence, however, became less and less.
In our times we see the development of the opposite extreme. We see instincts arising in the
masses which are the opposite of what is beneficial for humanity. We see things arising that
absolutely call for the qualities that may arise in individuals who are able to penetrate the
depths of spiritual science. No good will come from instincts, but only from the understanding
(that Dr. Unger also spoke of here
[18])
which, as is often stressed, every
human being can bring towards the spiritual investigator if he really opens himself to healthy
human reason. Thus there will come a culture in which the single individual, with his ever-deeper
penetration into the depths of the spiritual world, will be of particular importance, and in
which die one who penetrates in this way will be valued, just as someone who works in some craft
is valued. One does not go to the tailor to have boots made or to the shoemaker to be shaved, so
why should people go to someone else for what one needs as a world-view other than to the person
who is initiated into it? And it is, indeed, just this that, particularly today and in the most
intense sense, is necessary for the good of human beings even though there is a reaction against
it, which shows how humanity still resists what is beneficial for it. This is the terrible battle
— the grave situation —in which we find ourselves.
At no other time has there been a greater need to
listen carefully to what individuals know concerning one thing or another. Nor has there been a
greater need for people with knowledge of specific subject areas to be active in social life
— not from a belief in authority but out of common sense and out of agreement based on
common sense. But, to begin with, the instincts oppose this and people believe that some sort of
good can be achieved from levelling everything. This is the serious battle in which we stand.
Sympathy and antipathy are of no help here, nor is living in slogans. Only a clear observation of
the facts can help. For today great questions are being decided — the questions as to
whether the individual or the masses have significance. In other times this was not important
because the masses and the individual were in accord with one another; individuals were, in a
certain sense, simply speaking for the masses. We are approaching more and more that time when
the individual must find completely within himself the source of what he has to find and which he
has then to put into the social life; and
[what we are now seeing]
is only the last resistance
against this validity of the individual and an ever larger and larger number of individuals. One
can see plainly how that which spiritual science shows is also proved everywhere in these
significant points. We talk of associations which are necessary in the economic life, and use a
particular thinking for this. This has developed in the culture of the West from letting thoughts
associate. If one could take what
John Stuart Mill
does with logic, if one could remove those
thoughts from that sphere and apply them to the economic life, they would fit there. The
associations which would then come in there would be exactly those which do not fit into
psychology. Even in what appears in the area of human development, spiritual science follows
reality.
Thus spiritual science, if fully aware of the
seriousness of the present world situation, knows what a great battle is taking place between the
threefold social impulse that can come from spiritual science and that which throws itself
against this threefoldness as the wave of Bolshevism, which would lead to great harm (Unheil)
amongst humanity. And there is no third element other than these two. The battle has to take
place between these two. People must see this! Everything else is already decadent. Whoever looks
with an open mind at the conditions in which we are placed, must conclude that it is essential
today to gather all our forces together so that this whole terrible Ahrimanic affair can be
repulsed.
This building stands here,
[19]
incomplete though it is for the time being. Today we cannot get from the Central countries that
which for the most part, and in addition to what has come to us from the neutral states, has
brought this building to this stage. We must have contributions from the countries of the former
Entente. Understanding must be developed here for what is to become a unified culture containing
spirit, politics and economics. For people must get away from a one:sided tendency and must
follow those who also understand something of politics and economics, who do not work only in
dialectics, but, also being engaged with economic impulses, have insight into the spiritual, and
do not want to create states in which the State itself can run the economy. The Western peoples
will have to realize that something else must evolve in addition to the special gift they will
have in the future with regard to forming economic associations. The skill in forming
associations has so far been applied at the wrong end, i.e. in the field of Psychology. What must
evolve is understanding of the political-state element, which has other sources than the economic
life, and also of the spiritual element. But at present the Central countries lie powerless, so
people in the Western regions — one could not expect this of the Orient — will have
to see what the Purpose of this building is! It is necessary for us to consider What must be done
so that real provision is made for a new culture that should be presented everywhere in the
university education of the future — here we have to show the way. In the foundation of the
Waldorf Schools the culture has proved to be capable of bringing light into primary education.
But for this we need the understanding support of the widest circles.
Above all we need the means. For everything which,
in a higher or lower sense, is called a school, we need the frame of mind I have already tried to
awaken at the opening of the Waldorf School in Stuttgart.
[20]
I said in my
opening speech there: `This is one Waldorf school. It is well and good that we have it,
but for itself it is nothing; it is only something if, in the next quarter of a year, we build
ten such Waldorf schools and then others'. The world did not understand this, it had no money for
such a thing. For it rests on the standpoint: Oh, the ideals are too lofty, too pure for us to
bring dirty money to them; better to keep it in our pockets; that's the proper place for dirty
money. The ideals, oh, they're too pure, one can't contaminate them with money! Of course, with
purity of this kind the embodiment of ideals cannot be attained, if dirty money is not brought to
them. And thus we have to consider that, up to now, we have stopped at one Waldorf school which
cannot progress properly because in the autumn we found ourselves in great money difficulties.
These have been obviated for the time being, but at Easter we shall be faced with them again. And
then, after a comparatively short time, we will ask: Should we give up? And we shall have to give
up if, before then, an understanding is not forthcoming which dips vigorously into its
pockets.
It is thus a matter of awakening understanding in
this respect. I don't believe that much understanding would arise if we were to say that we
wanted something for the building in Dornach, or some such thing — as has been shown
already. But — and one still finds understanding for this today — if one wants to
create sanatoria or the like, one gets money, and as much as one wants! This is not exactly what
we want — we don't want to build a host of sanatoria — we agree fully with creating
them as far as they are necessary; but here it is a matter, above all, of nurturing that
spiritual culture whose necessity will indeed prove itself through what this course
[21]
I has attempted to accomplish. This is what I tried to suggest, to give a stimulus
to what I expressed here a few days ago, in the words 'World Fellowship of Schools'
(Weltschulverein).
[22]
Our German friends have departed but it is not a
question of depending on them for this 'World Fellowship'. It depends on those who, as friends,
have come here, for the most part from all possible regions of the non-German world — and
who are still sitting here now — that they understand these words 'World Fellowship of
Schools' because it is vital that we found school upon school in all areas of the world out of
the pedagogical spirit which rules in the Waldorf School. We have to be able to extend this
school until we are able to move into higher education of the kind we are hoping for here. For
this, however, we have to be in a position to complete this building and everything that belongs
to it, and be constantly able to support that which is necessary in order to work here; to be
productive, to work on the further extension of all the separate sciences in the spirit of
spiritual science.
People ask one how much money one needs for all
this. One cannot say how much, because there never is an uppermost limit. And, of course, we will
not be able to found a World Fellowship of Schools simply by creating a committee of twelve or
fifteen or thirty people who work out nice statutes as to how a World Fellowship of Schools of
this kind should work. That is all pointless. I attach no value to programmes or to statutes but
only to the work of active people who work with understanding. It will be possible to establish
this World Fellowship — well, we shall not be able to go to London for some time — in
the Hague or some such place, if a basis can be created, and by other means if the friends who
are about to go to Norway or Sweden or Holland, or any other country — England, France,
America and so on — awaken in every human being whom they can reach the well-founded
conviction that there has to be a World Fellowship of Schools. It ought to go through the world
like wildfire that a World Fellowship must arise to provide the material means for the spiritual
culture that is intended here.
If one is able in other matters, as a single
individual, to convince possibly hundreds and hundreds of people, why should one not be able in a
short time — for the decline is happening so quickly that we only have a short time —
to have an effect on many people as a single individual, so that if one came to the Hague a few
weeks later one would see how widespread was the thought that: 'The creation of a World
Fellowship of Schools is necessary, it is just that there are no means for it.' What we are
trying to do from Dornach is an historical necessity. One will only be able to talk of the
inauguration of this World Fellowship of Schools when the idea of it already exists. It is simply
utopian to set up committees and found a World Fellowship — this is pointless! But to work
from person to person, and to spread quickly the realization, the well-founded realization, that
it is so necessary — this is what must precede the founding. Spiritual science lives in
realities. This is why it does not get involved with proposals of schemes for a founding but
points to what has to happen in reality — and human beings are indeed realities — so
that such a thing has some prospects.
So what is important here is that we finally learn
from spiritual science how to stand in real life. I would never get involved with a simply
utopian founding of the World Fellowship of Schools, but would always be of the opinion that this
World Fellowship can only come about when a sufficiently large number of people are convinced of
its necessity. It must be created so that what is necessary for humanity — it has already
proved to be so from our course here — can happen. This World Fellowship of Schools must be
created.
Please see what is meant by this Fellowship in all
international life, in the right sense! I would like, in this request, to round off today what,
in a very different way in our course, has spoken to humanity through those who were here and of
whom we have the hope and the wish that they carry it out into the world. The World Fellowship of
Schools can be the answer of the world to what was put before it like a question; a question
taken from the real forces of human evolution, that is, human history. So let what can happen for
the World Fellowship of Schools, in accordance with the conviction you have been able to gain
here, happen! In this there rings out what I wanted to say today.
Notes:
1. These were the lectures given by Dr Karl Heyer on 14, 15 and 16 October
1920, during the first course of the School of Anthroposophy at the
Goetheanum
with the theme:
'The Science of History and History from the Viewpoint of Anthroposophy'
('Anthroposophische Betrachtungen Ober die Geschichtswissenschaft und aus der Geschichte').
These are printed in
Kultur und Erziehung
(the third volume of the Courses of the School of Anthroposophy),
Stuttgart, 1921. Return
2. See Wilhelm von Humboldt (1767–1835):
Über die Aufgabe des Geschiclztsschreibens
(The Task of the Historian)
in Volume IV of Humboldt's Works published by Leitzman, Berlin 1905 (see pages 35-56).
Some relevant passages taken from these are as follows:
"The business of the historian, in the last but simplest analysis, is to
portray the striving of an idea to attain existence in reality. For it is not always that it
succeeds in this at the first attempt; and it is not so rare that the idea degenerates
because it is unable to master in a pure way the matter counteracting it."
"The truth of everything that happens lies in the addition of the
above-mentioned invisible part of every fact, and thus the history writer must add this to
the events. Seen from this angle he is self-acting and even creative — not, indeed, by
producing what does not already exist, but by forming out of his own inner strength that
which, as it is in reality, he could not perceive through mere receptivity. In different
ways, but just like the poet, he must in himself transform the scattered fragments into a
whole."
"It may seem dubious to allow the realm of the history writer and that of
the poet to meet, even at only one point. But the activity of both is undeniably related. For
if the historian, like the poet, can achieve truth in his presentation of past events only by
completing and linking the incomplete and disjointed elements of direct observation, then he
does so, like the poet, only through imagination. Because, however, he places imagination
subordinate to experience and the fathoming of reality, there is a difference here which
cancels out all danger. Imagination does not work, at this lower position, as pure
imagination, and is therefore more properly called an intuitive faculty and a talent for
finding links."
"Of necessity, therefore, the historian too, must strive; not, like the
poet, to give his material over to the dominion of the form of necessity but to hold steadily
in consciousness the ideas which are its laws, because, permeated only by, these, he can then
find their trace in the pure research of the real in its reality."
"The historian encompasses all the threads of earthly activity and all
varieties of supersensible ideas; the sum-total of existence, more or less, is the object of
his work and he must therefore also follow all avenues of the mind and spirit. Speculation,
experience and poetry, however, are not separate, opposed and mutually-limiting activities of
the mind, but different planes of its radiance."
"Apart from the fact that history, like every scientific activity, serves
many subsidiary purposes, work on history is no less a free art, complete in itself, than
philosophy and poetry."
"Just as philosophy strives for the first foundation of things, and art
for the ideal of beauty, so history strives for a picture of human destiny in faithful truth,
living abundance and pure clarity that are perceived by the warm inner-being
[of the historian]
in such a way that his personal views, feelings and demands are lost and dissolved
away. It is the final purpose of the history-writer to awaken and nourish this mood, which,
however, he only attains when he pursues for his fellow human beings the simple presentation
of past events with conscientious faithfulness."
Return
3. See the final words of Rudolf Steiner, on 16 October 1920, after the
close of the first course of the Anthroposophical School, in
Die Kunst der Rezitation and Deklamation
(First Edition) Dornach, 1928, page 118. Return
4. See
i>Geschictliche Symptomatologie
(GA 185), nine lectures given in Dornach in 1918, only two of which are translated in
From Symptom to Reality in Modern History. Return
5. See
Bedeutende Fordnis durch ein einziges geistreiches Wort
in Goethes
Naturwissenschaftliche Schriften,
edited and with a commentary by Rudolf
Steiner in Kürschner's
Deutsche National-Literatur,
Volume II, page 34 (GA lb). Goethe says here:
"I do not rest until I find a significant point from which a great deal
can be deduced or, rather, which of its own will brings forth a great deal and presents this
to me, and which I then, with attention and receptivity, work on further faithfully and
carefully. If, in my experience, I find some phenomenon which I cannot deduce, I simply let
it lie as a problem; and I have found, in my long life, this way of doing things to be very
beneficial. For when I was not able for a long time to unravel the origin or connection of
some phenomenon but had to put it to one side, I found that, years later, it all suddenly
became clear in the most beautiful way."
Return
6. Alcuin (also Alhuin or Alchwin, i.e. 'Friend of the Temple') was rector
of the monastery school at York around 735 to 804. In 782 he followed the summons of
Charlemagne and took on the headship of the court school. He encouraged the sciences in the
monasteries and raised to the central seat of the sciences the monastery school of St Martin at
Tours, which he founded and whose Abbot he became in 796.
The debate with the Greek is described in Karl Werner's book
Alcuin and sein Jahrhundert
(Alcuin and His Century)
Vienna 1881, Chapter 11. page 166, as follows:
Thus Charlemagne once wanted to know from Alcuin what should be made of
the view of a Greek scholar, who presumably was a member of a Byzantine legation at
Charlemagne's court, who had expressed the opinion to the emperor that Christ had paid the
expiation for our sins to death. Alcuin found this manner of expression and the idea behind
it to be inadmissible, for Christ was not — death's debtor and could not become so
— the price of our redemption was paid by Christ to our divine Father, to whom, in
dying, He commended His soul. Death
[so Alcuin argued]
is in no way a reality of being and
substance but, to his way of thinking, was something purely negative, the mere absence or
'Carence' (Church Latin: the interval before benefits become available) of life; it is
nothing existing in itself, and thus cannot receive anything, no payment can be paid to it.
On the contrary, in the person of Christ, death itself, which God did not create, became the
ransom for our debt and won life for us thereby, which He Himself gives us in His saviour
power.'
Return
7. Rudolf Steiner drew attention at different times to the fact that the
content of the writings of 533 AD, attributed to Dionysius the Areopagite, do indeed stem
from the person of this name mentioned in
The Acts of the Apostles 17, 34.
See the lectures on 17 and 25 March 1907 in
Christianity Began as a Religion and
Festivals of the Seasons
respectively. Return
8. Johannes Scotus Erigena (c. 810–877) translator of the writings of
Dionysius the Areopagite into Latin (see Return
9. Nicolaus of Cusa (or Kures) (1401–1464), cardinal. Return
10.
Immanuel Kant
(1724–1804):
Critique of Pure Reason,
1781;
Prolegemena,
1783. Return
11. See
Johann Gottlieb Fichte
(1762–1814)
Erste und zweite Einleitung in die Wissenschaftslehre und Verstwh einer neuen Darstellung der
Wiyenschaftslehre
(First and Second Introduction into the Doctrine of Knowledge and an Attempt at a New
Presentation of the doctrine of Knowledge). Return
12.
Grenzen der Naturerkenntnis
(Limits to a Knowledge of Nature
(GA 322) — eight lectures given during the first course
(Hochschulkurs)
of the School of Spiritual Science in Dornach, 27 September to 3
October 1920 (GA 322). Return
13. Baron Christian von Wolff, philosopher and mathematician,
Vernünftige Gedanken von Gott, der Welt und der Seele des Menschen, auch allen Dingen
überhaupt,
1719. Return
14. David Hume (1711–1776), philosopher. Return
15.
Herbert Spencer
(1820–1903), philosopher. Return
16. John Stuart Mill (1806–1873), philosopher. Return
17. See Rudolf Steiner,
Towards Social Renewal,
1919, (GA 23). Return
18. In the third week of the first course (of the School of Spiritual
Science), Dr Carl Unger (1822–1929) gave lectures under the title of 'Rudolf Steiner's
Works'. These six lectures, edited by Unger, can be found in Volume I of
Carl Unger's Writings,
Stuttgart, 1964. Return
19. The first Goetheanum building, begun in 1913, was already put into use
in 1920, although still under construction supervised by Rudolf Steiner and with the interior
not yet finished. On New Year's Eve 1922–3 it was destroyed by fire. Return
20. The Free Waldorf School was founded in Stuttgart in the spring of 1919 by Dr
Emil Molt
for the children, to begin with, of the employees of the Waldorf-Astoria
cigarette factory. The school was under the supervision of Rudolf Steiner who appointed the
teachers and gave the preparatory seminar courses. Return
21. The first anthroposophical course of the Free School for Spiritual
Science took place at the Goetheanum from 26 September to 16 October 1920. See also notes
1,3,12, and 18. Return
22. I.e., a form of international support body for Waldorf Schools. Rudolf
Steiner suggested the founding of a World Fellowship of Schools during an assembly of teachers
on 16 October 1920. There is no available transcript of this talk. Return
|