Imaginative Cognition and Inspired Cognition
Dornach, 23rd December 1921
In
the course of these lectures I have often explained how a man
is not in a sleeping state only during ordinary sleep but that
this state also plays into his everyday conscious life. This
obliges us indeed to describe the state of complete wakefulness
as existing, even in everyday consciousness, for our conceptual
life alone. Compared to the conceptual life, what we bear
within us as our life of feeling is not so closely connected
with our waking state. To the unprejudiced observer our feeling
life shows affinity to dream-life; though dream-life runs on in
pictures and the life of feeling in the way we all know. Yet we
soon realise that, on the one hand, dream-life — which as
we know conjures up in pictures, into everyday life, facts
unknown to ordinary consciousness — can be judged only by
our conceptual faculty of discrimination. It is by means of
this same faculty alone that the whole range and significance
of our feeling life can be estimated. And what goes on in a
will-impulse, in the expression, the working, of the will, is
just as hidden from ordinary consciousness as what in dreamless
sleep happens to man, as a being of soul and spirit, from the
moment of falling asleep to that of waking.
What actually takes place when we perform the simplest act of
will, when, let us say, by merely having an impulse to do so we
raise an arm or a leg, is in fact just as great a mystery to us
as what goes on in sleep. It is only because we can see the
result of an act of will that the act itself enters our
consciousness.
Having thought of raising our arm — but that is merely a
thought — we see when this has taken place how the arm
has indeed been raised. It is by means of our conceptual life
that we learn the result of an act of will. But the actual
carrying out of the deed remains hidden from ordinary
consciousness, so that, even during our waking hours, what
arises in us as an impulse of will we have to attribute to a
sleeping state. And the whole of our life of feeling runs its
course just like a dream.
Now
what concerns us here is that, when taken as a whole, the facts
I have just mentioned can be quite clear to our ordinary
consciousness, although perhaps, when given an abstract
interpretation certain points may not seem so at once. But by
carefully following up the facts in question we shall find what
has been said to be correct.
Consciousness when developed is able to follow up these facts.
In particular it can observe in detail the conceptual life and
the life of the will. We know how through exercises described
in several of my works ordinary objective knowledge can be
raised to Imaginative knowledge. On being observed this
Imaginative knowledge or cognition shows, to begin with, its
true relation to the human being as a whole. It will be useful
for us, however, to recall certain facts about ordinary
consciousness, before going on to what this Imaginative
knowledge has chiefly to say about a man's conceptual power and
his will.
Let
us then look at the actual life of thought — the
conceptual life. You will have to admit; If this conceptual
life is experienced without prejudice, we shall not feel it to
be a reality. Conceptions arise in our life of soul and there
is no doubt the inner course of a man's conceptions is
something added to the outer course taken by the facts. The
outer course of events does not directly demand the
accompaniment of an inwardly experienced conception. The fact
of which we form an idea could take place without our
experiencing it as an idea. Sinking ourselves in these
conceptions, however, teaches us too that in them we live in
what, compared with the external world, is something unreal. On
the other hand, precisely in what concerns the life of will
— which seems to ordinary consciousness as if experience
in sleep — we become aware of our own reality and of the
truth about our relation to the world.
As
we form conceptions we find more and more that these
conceptions live in us just as the images of objects are there
in a mirror. And just as little as, in the case of what is
usually called the real world, we feel the mirror-images to be
a reality, do we — if our reason is sound — look
upon our conceptions as real.
But
there is another thing which prevents our ascribing reality to
erg conceptions, and that is our feeling of freedom. Just
imagine that while forming conceptions we lived in them so that
they ran on in us in the way nature works. The conceptual life
would be like something happening outside in nature, taking
place as a necessity. We should be caught up in a chain, of
necessities from which our thinking would be unable to free
itself. We should never have the sense of freedom which, as
such, is an actual fact. We experience ourselves as free human
beings only when free impulses living in us spring out of
pictures having no place in the chain of natural necessities.
Only because we live with; our conceptions in pictures outside
the necessary natural phenomena are we able, out of such
conceptions, to experience free impulses of will.
When observing our conceptual life thus, we perceive it to be
entirely unreal; whereas our life of will assures us of our own
reality. When the will is in action it brings about changes in
world outside — changes we are obliged to regard as real.
Through our will we make actual contact with the external
world. Therefore, it is only as beings of will that we can
perceive ourselves as realities in the external world.
When from these facts — easily substantiated in ordinary
consciousness — we go on to those of which Imagination
can tell us, we find the following. When we have acquired
Imaginative knowledge and, armed with this, try to arrive at a
knowledge of man himself, then actually in two respects he
appears a quite different being from what he is for ordinary
consciousness. To ordinary consciousness our physical body is a
self-contained entity at rest. We differentiate between its
separate organs and observing an organ in our usual state of
consciousness we have the impression of dealing with an
independent member of the body which, as something complete in
itself, can be drawn in definite outlines.
This ceases the moment we rise to Imaginative knowledge and
study from that point of view the life of the body. Then this
something at rest shows — if we don't want to be really
theoretical, which of course it is always possible to be in a
diagram — that it cannot be drawn in definite outline. This
cannot be done in the case of lungs, heart, liver and so on,
when we rise to Imaginative knowledge. For what this reveals
about the body is its never-ending movement. Our body is in a
state of continued motion — certainly not something at
rest; it is a process, a becoming, a flux, which imaginative
cognition brings to our notice. One might say that everything
is seething, inwardly on the move, not only in space but, in an
intensive way, one thing flows into another. We are no longer
confronted by organs at rest and complete; there is active
becoming, living, weaving. We cannot speak any more of lungs,
heart, liver, but of processes — of the lung-process,
heart-process, liver process. And these separate processes
together make up the whole process — man. It is
characteristic of our study of the human being from the point
of view of Imaginative knowledge, that he appears as something
moving, something enduring, in a state of perpetual
becoming.
Consider what it signifies to have this change in our view of a
man; when, that is, we first see the human body with its
definitely outlined members, and then direct the gaze of our
soul to the inner soul-life, finding there nothing to be drawn
thus definitely. In the life of soul, we see what is taking its
course in time, something always becoming, never at rest. The
soul-life shows itself indeed to be a process perceptible only
inwardly, a process of soul and spirit, yet clearly visible.
This process in the life of soul, which is there for ordinary
consciousness when a man's inner being is viewed without
prejudice, this state of becoming in the soul-life, has very
little resemblance to the life of the body at rest. It is true
that the life of the body also shows movement; breathing is a
movement, circulation is a movement. In relation to how a man
appears to Imaginative cognition, however, I would describe
this as merely a stage on the way to movement. Compared with
the delicate, subtle movements of the human physical body
revealed to Imaginative cognition, the circulation of the
blood, the breathing, and other bodily motions seem relatively
static.
In
short, the objective knowledge of the human body perceived it
ordinary consciousness is very different from what is perceived
as the life of soul, that is in a perpetual state of becoming
— always setting itself in motion and never resting.
When, however, with Imagination we observe the human body, it
becomes inwardly mobile and in appearance more like the soul
life. Thus, Imaginative cognition enables us to raise the
appearance of the physical body to a level with the soul. Soul
and body come nearer to each other. For Imaginative cognition
the body in its physical substance appears more like the
soul.
But
here I have brought two things to your notice which belong to
quite different spheres. First, I showed how the physical body
appears to Imaginative cognition as something always on the
move, always in a state of becoming. Then I pointed out how
indeed, for the, inner vision of our usual consciousness, the
ordinary life of soul is also ceaselessly becoming, running its
course tie — a life, in effect, to which it is impossible
to ascribe definite outlines.
When, however, we rise to Imaginative cognition, this life of
soul also changes for the inward vision, and changes over in an
opposite direction to the life of the body. It is noticeable
that when filled with Imaginative knowledge we no longer feel
any freedom of movement in our thoughts, in the combining of
them with one another. We also feel that by rising to
Imaginative cognition our thoughts gain certain mastery over
our life of soul. In ordinary consciousness we can add one
thought to another, with inner freedom either combine or not
combine a subject with a predicate — feel free in our
combining of conceptions.
This in not so when we acquire imaginative knowledge. Then in
the thought-world we feel as though in something which works
through powers of its own. We feel as if caught up in a web of
thought, in such a way that the thoughts combine themselves
through their own forces, independently of us. We can no longer
say I think — but are forced to change it to: It thinks.
In fact, we are not free to do otherwise. We begin to perceive
thinking as an actual process — feel it to be as real a
process in us as in everyday life we experience the gripping of
pain and then its passing off, or the coming and going of
something pleasant. By arising to Imaginative cognition, we
feel the reality of the thought-world — something in the
thought-world resembling experience in the physical body.
From his it can be seen how, through Imaginative knowledge, the
conceptual life of the soul becomes more like the life of the
body, than is the soul-life — as seen through the inner
vision of ordinary consciousness. In short, the body grows
soul-like. And the soul becomes more like the body,
particularly like those bodily processes which to Imaginative
consciousness disclose themselves in their becoming.
Thus, for Imaginative cognition the qualities of the soul
approach those of the body, and the qualities of the body those
of the soul. And we see the soul and spirit interweaving with
the bodily-physical the two becoming more alike. It is as
though our experience of what is of the soul acquired a
materialistic character while our view of the bodily life,
physical life generally, were spiritualised
This is an important fact which reveals itself to Imaginative
cognition. And when further progress is made to Inspired
Cognition, we find another secret about the human being
unveiled. Having acquired Inspired knowledge we learn more of
the material nature of thinking, of the conceptual faculty; we
learn see more deeply into what actually happens when we
think.
Now, as I have said, we no longer have freedom in our life of
thought. "It thinks,” and we are caught up in the web of
this "It thinks.” In certain circumstances the thoughts
are the same as those which in ordinary consciousness we
combine or separate in freedom, but which in Imaginative
experience we perceive to take place as if from inner
necessity.
From this we see that it is not in the thought-life, as such,
that freedom and necessity are to be found, but in our own
attitude, our own relation, to the thought-life of ordinary
consciousness. We learn to recognise the actual situation with
regard to our experience, in ordinary consciousness, of the
unreality of thoughts. We gradually come to understand the
reason for this experience, and then the following becomes
clear.
By
means of the organic process our organism both takes in and
excretes substances. But it is not only a matter of these
substances separating themselves from the organic process of
the body and being thrown out by the excretory organs —
certain of these substances become stored up in us. Having been
thrown out of the life-process these remain, to some extent, in
the nerve-tract, and in other places in the organism. In our
life-process we are continuously engaged in detaching lifeless
matter. People able to follow minutely the process of human
life can observe this storing up of lifeless matter everywhere
in the organism. A great part of this is excreted but there is
a general storing up of a certain amount in a more tenuous
form. The life of the human organism is such that it is always
engaged on the organic process — like this (a drawing was
made) But everywhere within the organic process we see
inorganic, lifeless matter, not being excreted but stored up
(which I indicated here with red chalk): I have drawn these red
dots rather heavily because it is chiefly the unexcreted,
lifeless matter which withdraws to the organ of the human head,
where it remains.
Now
the human organism is permeated throughout by the ego (I
indicate this with green chalk). Within the organism the ego
comes in contact with the lifeless substances which have been
separated off and permeates them. So that our organism appears
as having, on the one hand, its organic processes permeated by
the ego, the process, that is, containing the living substance,
and of having also what is lifeless — or shall we say
mineralised — in the organism permeated by the ego.
This, then, is what is always going on when we think. Aroused
by sense-perceptions outside, or inwardly by memory, the ego
gets the upper hand over the lifeless substances, and —
in accordance with the stimulation of the senses or of the
memories — swings these lifeless substances to and fro in
us, we might almost say makes drawings in us with them. For
this is no figurative conception; this use of inorganic matter
by the ego is absolute reality It might be compared to reducing
chalk to a powder and then with a chalky finger drawing all
kinds of figures. It is an actual fact that the ego sets this
lifeless matter oscillating, masters it, and with it draws
figures in us, though the figures are certainly unlike those
usually drawn outside. Yet the ego with the help of this
lifeless substance does really make drawings and form crystals
in us — though not crystals like those found in the
mineral kingdom (see red in drawing).
What goes on in this way between the ego and the mineralized
substance in us that has detached itself as in a fine but solid
state — it is this which provides the material basis of
our thinking. In fact, to Inspired cognition the thinking
process, the conceptual process, shows itself to be the use
them ego makes of the mineralised substance in the human
organism.
This, I would point out, gives a more accurate picture of what
I have frequently described in the abstract when saying: In
that we think we are always dying, — What within us is in
a constant state of decay, detaching itself from the living and
becoming mineralised, with this the ego makes drawings, actual
drawings, of all our thoughts. It is the working and weaving of
the ego in mineral kingdom, in that kingdom which alone makes
it possible for us to possess the faculty of thinking.
You
see it is what I have been describing here which dawned on the
materialists of the 19th century, though they misconstrued it.
The best advocates of materialism — and one of the best
was Czolbe — had a vague notion that while thoughts are
flitting through us physical processes are at work. These
materialists forget, however, — and this is where error
crept in — that it is the purely spiritual ego making
drawings in us inwardly with what in mineralized. And on this
inward drawing depends what we know of the actual awakening of
ordinary consciousness.
Let
us now consider the opposite side at the human being, the side
of the will-impulses. If you recall what I have been
describing, you will perhaps perceive how the ego becomes
imprisoned in what has been mineralized within us. But it is
able to make use of this mineralised substance to draw with it
inwardly. The ego is able to sink right down into what is thus
mineralised.
If,
on the other hand, we study the life-processes, where the
non-mineralised substances are to be found, we come to the
material basis of the will. In sleep the ego leaves the
physical body, whereas in willing the ego is only driven out of
certain parts of the organism. Because of this, at certain
moments when this is so, there is nothing mineralised in that
region, everything there is full of life. Out of these parts of
the organism, where all is alive and from which at that moment
nothing mineralised is being detached, the impulses will
unfold. But the ego is then driven out; it withdraws into what
is mineral. The ego can work on the mineralised substances but
not on what is living, from which it is thrust out just us when
we are asleep at night our ego is driven out of the whole
physical body.
But
then the ego is outside the body whereas on mineralisation
taking place it is driven inside. It is the life-giving process
which thrust the ego out of certain parts of the body; then the
ego is as much outside those parts as in sleep it is driven out
of the whole body. Hence, we can say that when the will is in
action parts of the ego are outside the regions of the physical
body to which they are assigned. And those parts of the ego
— where are they then? They are outside in the
surrounding space and become one with the forces weaving there.
By setting our will in action we go outside ourselves with part
of our ego, and we take into us forces which have their place
in the world outside. When I move an arm, this is not done by
anything coming from within the organism but through a force
outside, into which the ego enters only by being partly driven
out of the arm. In willing go out of my body and move myself by
means of outside forces. We do not lift our leg by means of
forces within us, but through those actually working from
outside. It is the same when an arm is moved. Whereas in
thinking, through the relation of the ego to the mineralised
part of the organism, we are driven within, in willing just as
in sleep we are driven outside. No one understands the will who
has not a conception of man as a cosmic being; no one
understands the will who is bounded by the human body and does
not realise that in willing he takes into him forces lying
beyond it.
In
willing we sink ourselves into the world, surrender ourselves
to it. So that we can say: The material phenomenon that
accompanies thinking is a mineral process in us, something
drawn by the ego in the mineralised parts of the human
organism. The will represents in us a vitalising, a widening of
the ego, which then becomes a member of the spiritual world
outside, and from there works back upon the body.
If
we want to make a diagram of the relation between think and
willing, it must be done in this way (a drawing was made). You
see it is quite possible to pass over from an inward view of
the soul-life to its physical counterpart, without being
tempted to fall one-sidedly into materialism. We learn to
recognise what takes place in a material way in thinking and in
willing. But once we know how in thinking the ego plays an
actual part with the inorganic, and how, on the other hand,
through the organic life-giving process in the body it is
driven out into the spirit, then we never lose the ego.
In
that the ego is driven out of the body it is united with forces
of the cosmos; and working in from outside, from the spiritual
regions of the cosmos, the ego unfolds the will.
Materialism is therefore justified on the one hand, whereas on
the other it no longer holds good. Simply to attack materialism
betrays a superficial attitude. For what in a positive sense
the materialist has to say is warranted. He is at fault only
when he would approach man's whole wide conception of the world
from one side.
In
general, when the world and all that happens in it is followed
inwardly, spiritually, it is found more and more that the
positive standpoints of individual men are warranted, but not
those that are negative. And in this connection spiritualism is
often just as narrow as materialism. In what he affirms
positively the materialist has right on his side, as the
spiritualist has on his, when positive. It is only on becoming
negative that they stray from the path and fall into error. And
it is indeed no trifling error when, in an amateurish fashion,
people imagine they have succeeded in their striving for a
spiritual world-conception without having any understanding of
material processes, and then look down on materialism. The
material world is indeed permeated by spirit. But we must not
be one-sided; we must learn about its material characteristics
as well, recognising that reality has to be approached from
various sides if we are to arrive at its full significance.
And
that is a lesson best taught by a world-conception such as that
offered by Anthroposophy.
|