LECTURE 2
Dornach, December 14, 1918
The Logic of Thought and the Logic of
Reality
My dear friends,
Today I would
like to bring before you a few important considerations
connected with the matters that we have now for a long time
regarded as our task. When we reflect on the way in which
spiritual science, as here intended, is able to consider and
to give answers to the questions of life, we must above all
take careful heed to the fact that this spiritual science,
and indeed for that matter the whole present and the future
time, makes new and different demands on man's powers of
comprehension and of thought. He has to think in a different
way from what he is accustomed to, in accordance with the
habits of thoughts of the immediate past and of the present
— especially the habits of thought arising from science
and its popularization. You are well aware that all that
spiritual science has to say concerning any sphere of life
and hence too what it has to say on the social question,
indeed especially what it has to say on the social question,
is the expression of the results of research — results
that have not been obtained on any merely rationalistic or
abstract path, but that have been sought and found in the
realm of spiritual reality. They can be understood, as we
know, with the help of a sound and healthy human intelligence
— they can, however, only be discovered when one rises
above the ordinary consciousness, such as is comprised within
rational thinking, abstract thinking, natural scientific
research and so forth — rises above this ordinary
consciousness to the Imaginative, Inspired, and Intuitive
consciousness. What comes to light on the path of
Imagination, Inspiration, and Intuition — this it is,
formulated in concepts and ideas that are capable of
expression, that fills the content of the science which
Anthroposophical research has to give.
We have to
accustom ourselves — and this is what makes it so hard
for many of our contemporaries to tread the necessary path
from the usual thinking of today to the Spiritual Science of
Anthroposophy — we have to accustom ourselves to quite
a new and different conception of wherein the finding of
truth consists. Today men ask so lightly: can this or
that be proven? The question is justified of course. But, my
dear friends, we have also to look at the question from the
standpoint of reality. If we mean: can what the spiritual
researcher brings forward be proved in accordance with the
conceptions and ideas that we have already acquired, in
accordance with the customary ideas which we have imbibed
through our education, through our everyday life? — If
we mean this, we are making a great mistake; for the results
of spiritual research are drawn from reality.
Let me make
clear to you by a quite trivial, simple comparison, how the
ordinary thinking that runs on purely abstract lines may fall
into error. One thought is supposed to follow from another.
The error is that if people see: As a thought it does not
follow — they concluded that it must be false, while
all the time from the point of view of reality it still may
be perfectly true. The consequences in reality are not always
the same as the consequences in mere thought; the Logic of
Reality is a different thing from the Logic of Thought.
In our time,
the metaphysical legalistic way of thinking has taken such
hold upon men that they are wont to think that everything
must be comprehended with the Logic of Thought. But that is
not the case. Listen to this, for example. Take a cube
measuring — let us say — 30 centimeters each way.
Now if someone were to say to you: “This cube,
measuring 30 centimeters each way, is raised up a meter and a
half above the floor”— if you were not yourself
in the room where the cube is, you would be able with your
pure thought-logic to say one thing: you would be able to
conclude from what was said to you: The cube must be standing
on something. There must be a table there of the
corresponding height, for the cube can certainly not hover in
the air. This, then, you can conclude even when you are not
present there, even when you have no experience of it.
But now let us
suppose: A ball is lying on the cube; something is lying upon
it. That you cannot conclude by thinking, that you must see.
You must behold it. And yet the ball, too, corresponds to
reality. The reality is thus filled with things and entities
that have of course a logic in themselves, a logic, however,
that does not coincide with the pure thought-logic; the logic
of sight is a different thinking from the logic of mere
thought.
This
necessitates, however, my dear friends, that we should at
length learn that we cannot only call proof the
so-called logical sequences to which modern thinking has
grown accustomed. Unless we learn this, we shall never arrive
at a true understanding of things. In the domain in which I
have been speaking to you now for some weeks — in the
domain of social life, of the structure of human society,
many new demands result simply from the fundamental premises
that I have set before you concerning the three-fold division
of society which will be necessary for the future. One such
result is, for example, a quite definite system of taxation.
But this system of taxation, once more, can only be found by
calling to our help the logic of things seen. The mere logic
of thought is insufficient. It is this that makes it
necessary that men should listen to those who know
something of these things, for when the thing has once been
said, then the healthy human intelligence, my dear friends,
will always suffice; it can always corroborate and
“control” what the spiritual researcher says. The
healthy human understanding, however, is something very
different from the logic of thought, which is developed
especially through the way of thinking that is prevalent
today, soaked and steeped as it is in the natural-scientific
point of view. From all this you will understand that
spiritual science is not intended merely to make us receive a
certain collection of ideas and then think that we can handle
these ideas much as we would handle information we acquire
through natural science or the like. That is absolutely
impossible and is not to be imagined for a moment. If we
think that we are making a great mistake. Spiritual Science
makes a man think in an altogether new way. It makes
him comprehend the world in an altogether different way than
he has done before, it makes him learn not merely to perceive
other things than before, but to perceive in a new way. When
you enter into spiritual science you must always bear this in
mind, you must be able to ask yourself again and again: Am I
learning to look at the world in a new way through my
receiving of Spiritual Science — not clairvoyance but
Spiritual Science — am I learning to look at the world
in another way from what I have done hitherto? For indeed, my
dear friends, one who regards Spiritual Science as a
collection of facts, a compendium of knowledge, may well know
a great deal, but if he still only thinks in the same way as
he thought before, then he has not received Spiritual
Science. He has only taken up Spiritual Science if the
manner, the form, the structure of his thinking has changed,
if in a certain respect he has become another man than he was
before. And this can only come about through the might and
the power of the ideas which we receive through Spiritual
Science.
Now if we are
to think about the social question, it is absolutely
essential that this change, which can only come about through
Spiritual Science, should enter our thinking, for only in
this light can that be understood to which I directed your
attention yesterday. Yesterday I spoke to you of the
economists of the schools, the present-day exponents of the
theories of economists. I pointed out to you how utterly
helpless they are in the face of realities. Why are they so
helpless? Because they are bent on understanding with the
Natural-Scientific type of thinking something that cannot
thus be understood. We shall have to make up our minds to
conceive the social life, not with the kind of thinking that
is brought up on Natural Science but in an altogether
different way. Only then shall we be able to find fruitful
social ideas — fruitful in life, capable of
realization.
I have already
once drawn your attention to a thing that may well have
astonished one or another among you; yet it needs to be
deeply thought over. I said: The logical conclusion which one
will tend to draw from such and such ideas, maybe from a
whole “world-conception” are by no means always
identical with that which follows from such a
world-conception in real life. I mean the following: A man
may hold a certain number of ideas or even an entire
world-conception. You may envisage this world-conception
clearly according to the ideas it contains and you may then
perhaps draw further conclusions from it — conclusions
which you will quite rightly presume to be logical, you may
imagine that such conclusions, which you can logically draw
from a world-conception, must necessarily follow from it. But
that is by no means the case. Life itself may draw altogether
different conclusions. And you may be highly astonished to
see how life draws its different conclusions. What
do I mean by this? Let us assume a world-conception which
appears to you highly idealistic, and — we may assume
— rightly so. It contains wonderfully idealistic ideas.
You yourself will probably admit only the logical conclusions
of your world-conception but if you sink this into another
mind, if you take into account the reality of life even where
it leads you across the chasms that separate one human being
from another — the following may happen: and only
Spiritual Science can explain the necessity of such a
sequence. You instruct your son or daughter or your pupil in
your idealistic world-conception, and they afterwards become
thorough scamps and rascals. It may well happen in the
reality of life that rascality will follow as the consequence
from your idealistic philosophy!
That of course
is an extreme case, though one that might well happen in real
life. I only wish to bring it home to you that other
conclusions are drawn in real life than in mere thought.
Hence it is that the men of today are so far removed from
reality, because they do not see through such things as
these; they are not really willing to bring to consciousness
what was formerly done instinctively. The instincts of past
ages felt clearly enough that this or that would arise from
one thing or another in real life. They were by no means
inclined only to presume the consequences that follow by the
logical thought. The instincts themselves worked with a logic
of their own. But today men have come into a kind of
uncertainty, and this uncertainty will naturally grow ever
greater in the age of the evolution of the Spiritual Soul
unless we make the counterbalance, which is: consciously to
receive into ourselves the Logic of Reality. And we do
receive it the moment we earnestly consider in its own
essence and process the Spiritual that lives and moves behind
the realities of sense.
I will tell you
a practical case to illustrate what I have just explained in
a more theoretic way. It will serve at the same time to
illustrate another thing, namely how far we can go wrong, if
we merely look at the external symptoms. In my lecture this
week, I spoke of the symptomatic method in the study of
history. Altogether, the symptomatic method is a thing that
we must make our own, if we would pass from the outer
phenomena to the underlying Reality.
A Russian
author and philosopher of the name of Berdiayeff recently
wrote an interesting article on the philosophical evolution
in the Russian people in the second half of the nineteenth
century and until the present day. There are two remarkable
things in this essay of Berdiayeff's. One is that the author
takes his start from a peculiar prejudice, proving that he
has no insight into those truths, with which you must by now
be thoroughly familiar — I mean the truth that in the
Russian East, preparing for the Sixth Post-Atlantean Age (the
age of the evolution of the Spiritual Life), altogether new
elements are on the point of emerging, though today they are
only there in embryo. Berdiayeff being ignorant of this fact,
his judgment on one point is quite incorrect. He says to
himself (and as a Russian philosopher he must surely know the
facts), he says: It is strange that in Russia as against the
Western European civilizations we have no real sense
(especially in philosophy) for what in the West they call the
Truth. Russians have been much interested in the philosophy
of the West, yet they have no real feeling for it inasmuch as
it strives towards “The Truth.” They only take up
the truths of philosophy inasmuch as they are serviceable for
life, inasmuch as they are directly useful to some conception
of life. The Socialist, e.g., is interested in philosophy
because he imagines that this or that philosophy will provide
him with a justification for his socialism. Similarly the
orthodox Believer will interest himself in some philosophy,
not, like a Western man because it is the Truth, but because
it gives him a justification or a basis for his Orthodox
Belief. And so on. Berdiayeff regards this as a great failing
in the Folk-Soul of modern Russia. He says: In the West they
are far in advance of us. They do not imagine that Truth must
follow life; they really believe that Truth is
Truth; the Truth is there, and life must take its
direction from it. And Berdiayeff actually adds the
extraordinary statement (albeit not extraordinary for the men
of the present day, who will take it quite as a matter of
course, but extraordinary for the Spiritual Scientists) he
adds the statement: The Russian socialist has no right to use
the expression “bourgeois science,” for bourgeois
science contains the truth; it has at last established the
concept of Truth, and that is a thing that cannot be
refitted. It is therefore a failing on the part of the
Russian Folk-Soul to believe that this Truth too can be
transcended!
Berdiayeff
shares this curious opinion, not only with the whole world of
professors, but with all their faithful followers, to wit,
the whole bourgeois of Western and Middle Europe, the
aristocracy especially so, and the rest. Berdiayeff simply
does not know what is now germinating in the Russian Folk
Soul, which comes to expression for this very reason in a
frequently tumultuous and distorted form. He does not know
that in this conception of Truth from the standpoint of life,
crooked as it may be today, there lies a real seed for the
conception of the future. In the future it will right itself,
of that we may be sure. When once what is preparing today as
a germinating seed will have unfolded, I mean the directing
of all human evolution towards the spiritual life, then
indeed will that which men call the “Truth” today
have an altogether different form. Today I have drawn your
attention to some peculiar facts in this respect. This Truth,
my dear friends, will among other things bring to man's
consciousness what the men of today cannot realize, that the
logic of facts, the logic of reality, the logic of things
seen is a very different thing from the mere logic of
concepts. And this transformed conception of the Truth will
have some other interesting qualities. That is the one thing
which you see emerging in Berdiayeff's essay. It is
remarkable enough, for it shows how little such a learned
author lives in the real trend and meaning of the evolution
of our time, which he might well perceive in his own nation
above all, but cannot recognize, laboring as he does under
this prejudice.
The other thing
must be considered in quite a different direction.
Berdiayeff, as the whole spirit of his essay shows, witnesses
the rise of Bolshevism with great discomfort. Well, in that
respect, the one man or the other, according as he is a
Bolshevist or the reverse, will say that Berdiayeff is right
or wrong. I do not propose to dilate just now upon this
question. I will describe the facts, I will not criticize.
But this is the important thing: In the sixties, so says
Berdiayeff, there was already the tendency to regard Truth
and Philosophy as dependent on life, and at that time
materialism found entry into Russia. Men believed in
Materialism, because they found it useful and profitable for
life. Then, in the seventies, Positivism, such as is held by
Auguste Comte for example, came into vogue. And after that,
other points of view, for example that of Nietzsche, found
entry into Russia among the people known as the
Intelligentsia. And now Berdiayeff asks the question: What
kind of philosophy do we find among the Intelligentsia of the
Bolsheviks? For, indeed, a certain philosophy is prevalent
among them. But how this particular philosophy can go with
Bolshevism, that Berdiayeff is quite at a loss to explain. He
simply cannot understand how Bolshevism can regard as its own
philosophy — curiously enough — the doctrine of
Avenarius and Mach.
And, truth to
tell, my dear friends, if you had told Avenarius and Mach
that their philosophy was to be accepted by such people as
the Bolsheviks, they themselves would have been still more
astonished and angry than Berdiayeff. They would have been
most indignant (both of them, as you know, are now dead) if
they had lived to see themselves as the official philosophers
of Bolshevism. Imagine Avenarius, the worthy bourgeois, who
of course had always assumed that he could only be understood
by people who — well, who wore at any rate decent
clothes, people who would never do violence to anyone in the
Bolshevist manner, in short, good “respectable”
people, in the sense in which one used the expression in the
sixties, seventies and eighties. And it is true, if we
consider only the content of the philosophy of Avenarius, we
are still more at a loss to understand how it happened. For
what does Avenarius think? Avenarius says: Men labor under a
prejudice. They think: within, in my head, or in my soul or
wherever it is, are the ideas, the perceptions, they are
there subjectively; outside are the objects. But, says
Avenarius, this is not correct. If I were all alone in the
world, I should never arrive at the distinction between
subject and object. I am led to make the distinction only
through the fact that other people are there too. I alone
beheld a table, I should never come to the idea that the
table is out there in space and a picture of it here in my
brain. I would simply have the table, and would not
distinguish between subject and object. I only distinguish
between them because, when I look at the table with another
man, I say to myself: He sees the table, and I too perceive
it. The perception is in my head too. I reflect that what he
senses I am also sensing. Such are partly theoretical
considerations (I will not go into them more fully, you would
say: All these things do not interest us) within which
Avenarius' thought lives and moves. In 1876 he wrote his book
Conception of the World According to the Principle of Least Action.
For on such premises as I have here
explained to you, he shows how the concepts we have as human
beings have no real value, but that we only create them for
the sake of mental economy. According to Avenarius, the
concept “Lion,” for example, or the concept that
finds expression in a “Natural Law” is nothing
real, nor does it refer to anything real. It is only
uneconomical if in the course of my life I have seen five or
six or even thirty lions and am now to conceive them each and
severally. I therefore proceed in a more economical way, and
make myself a single concept “Lion,” embracing
all the thirty. Thus all our forming of concepts is a mere
matter of subjective mental economy.
Mach holds a
similar view. It was Mach of whom I told you how he once got
into an omnibus where there was a mirror. As he got in, he
saw a man coming in from the other side. Now the appearance
of this man was highly antipathetic to him, and he said to
himself: “What a weedy-looking
schoolmaster.”— only then did he perceive that
there was a mirror hanging there and that he had simply seen
himself. Mach tells the story to indicate how little one
knows oneself, even in one's external human form how little
self-knowledge man has. He even tells of another occasion
when he passed a shop window which acted as a mirror and thus
again met himself and was quite annoyed to come across such
an ugly-looking pedant.
Mach proceeded
in a rather more popular fashion, but his idea is the same as
that of Avenarius. He says: there are not subjective ideas on
the one hand, and objective things on the other. All that
exists in reality is the content of our sensations. I, to
myself, am only a content of sensation, the table outside me
is a content of sensation, my brain is a content of
sensation. Everything is a content of sensation, and the
concepts men make for themselves only exist for the purpose
of economy. It was about the year 1881; I was present at a
meeting of the Academy of Sciences in Vienna where Mach gave
his lecture on the Economy of Thought, entitled:
“Thought as a Principle of the Least Action.” I
must say, it made quite a terrible impression upon me, who
was then a mere boy, at the very beginning of the twenties.
It made a terrible impression on me when I saw that there
were men so radical in their ideas, without an inkling of the
fact that on the paths of thought there enters into the human
soul the first beginning of a manifestation of the
super-sensible, the spiritual. Here was a man who denied the
reality of concepts to such an extent as to see in them the
mere results of a mental activity bent upon economy.
But in Mach and
Avenarius — you will not misunderstand my words —
all this takes place entirely within the limit of thoroughly
“respectable” thinking. We should naturally
assume that these two men and all their followers are worthy
folk of sound middle-class opinion, utterly removed from any
even moderately radical, let alone revolutionary ideas, in
practice. And now all of a sudden they have become the
official Philosophers of the Bolsheviks! No one could have
dreamt of such a thing. Perhaps you may read Avenarius'
booklet on the “Principle of Least Action.” It
may interest you, it is quite well written. But if you were
to tackle his “Philosophy of Experience,” I fancy
you would not get very far, you would find it appallingly
dull. Written as it is in an absolutely professorial style,
there is not the slightest possibility of your drawing even
the least vestige of Bolshevism as a conclusion from it. You
would not even derive from it a practical
world-conception of the most gentle radicalism.
I am well
aware, my dear friends, of the objection which those who take
symptoms for realities might now bring forward against me. An
easy-going, hard-and-fast Positivist, for instance, would
say: The explanation is as simple as can be! The Bolshevists
took their Intellectuals from Zurich. Avenarius was a
professor in Zurich, and those who are now working as
intellectual leaders among the Bolsheviks were his pupils.
Moreover there was a University lecturer there, a pupil of
Mach's Adler, the man who afterwards shot the Austrian
statesman Count Stügh. Many followers of Lenin, perhaps
even Lenin himself, were well-acquainted with Adler. They
absorbed these ideas and carried them to Russia. It is
therefore a pure coincidence.
Needless to say
I am well aware that a cock-sure hard-and-fast Positivist can
explain the whole thing in this way. But did I not tell you
the other day how the whole poetic character of Robert
Hamerling can be shown to have arisen from the unreliability
of the worthy Rector Kaltenbrunner, who forgot to forward
Hamerling's application for a post in Budapest, as a result
of which someone else got the post instead. If only
Kaltenbrunner had not been so slack, Hamerling would
certainly have gone as a schoolmaster to Budapest in the
1860's instead of to Trieste. Now if you consider all that
Hamerling became through spending ten years of his life on
the shores of the Adriatic at Trieste, you will see that his
whole poetic life was a result. This was the external fact.
The worthy Rector Kaltenbrunner, headmaster of the Grammar
School at Graz, forgot to forward his application and was
therefore the occasion of Hamerling's going to Trieste. You
see, these things must not be taken as realities but as
symptomatic of inner things which come to expression through
them.
Thus what
Berdiayeff conceives in this way — that the Bolsheviks
chose as their idols the worthy middle-class philosophers
Avenarius and Mach — does indeed take us back to what I
said at the beginning of the present lecture: The reality of
life, the reality of things seen is very different from the
merely logical reality. Of course you cannot deduce
from Avenarius and Mach that they could have become the
official philosophers of the Bolsheviks. But, my dear
friends, even what you can deduce by logic is only of
importance as an external symptom. In effect, we only get at
Reality by a research which goes straight for it. And in the
Reality the Spiritual Beings work.
I might tell
you many things which would indeed enable you to perceive it
as a necessity, in reality of life, that such philosophies as
that of Avenarius and Mach lead to the conclusion of the most
revolutionary socialism of our time. For behind the scenes of
existence it is the very same spirits who instill into men's
consciousness philosophies after the style of Avenarius or
Mach, and who instill once more into men's consciousness that
which leads on to Bolshevism for example. Only in Logic you
cannot derive the one thing from the other. But the Reality
of Life performs this derivation. I beg you inscribe this
deep into your hearts, for here too you will have something
of what I am constantly emphasizing. It is needful to us to
find the transition from the mere tangle of logical ideas,
within which the people of today in their illusions imagine
the realities of life to be imbued, to the true reality. If
we look at the symptoms, and know how to value them, the
thing does indeed become far more earnest. Here I will draw
your attention to something to which another who is not a
Spiritual Scientist will not pay so much attention; for he
will take it more as a phrase, as something more or less
indifferent. Mach, you see, who is a Positivist, and a
radical one at that, comes to the idea that all things are
really sensations. This doctrine, which young Adler also
expounded in his lectures at Zurich, whereby he will
undoubtedly have gained many adherents for himself, and for
Mach and for Avenarius — this doctrine declares that
everything is sensation, and that we are quite unjustified in
distinguishing the physical from the psychical. The table
outside us is physical and psychical in precisely the same
sense as my ideas are physical and psychical: and we only
have concepts for the sake of mental economy.
Now the
peculiar thing in Mach was that instinctively, every now and
then, he withdrew from his own world-conception — from
his radical, positivist world-conception. He withdrew a
little, saying to himself: These then are the results of
truly modern thought. It is meaningless to say that anything
exists beyond my sensation or that I should distinguish the
physical and the psychical. And yet I am impelled again and
again whenever I have the table before me, to speak not
merely of the sensation, but to believe that there is
something out there, quite physically. And again when I have
an idea, a sensation or a feeling, I have not merely the
perception of the phenomenon which takes place, but though by
my scientific insight I realize that it is quite unjustified
— still I believe that here within me is the soul, and
out there is the object. I feel myself impelled again and
again to make this distinction how does it come about? Mach
said to himself: however does it come about that I am
suddenly impelled to assume; in here is something of the
soul, and out there is something external to the soul. I know
that it is no true distinction, yet am I continually
compelled to think something different from what my
scientific insight tells me.
This is what
Mach says to himself, every now and then when he withdraws a
little from these things and considers them again. You will
find it in his books. And he then makes a peculiar remark; he
says: sometimes one has a feeling that makes one ask: —
Can it be that we human beings are just being led round and
round in a circle by some evil spirit? And he answers:
Sometimes I really think so.
I know, my dear
friends, how many people will read just such a passage,
taking it as an empty phrase. Yet it is truly symptomatic.
For here, every now and then, there peers over the shoulder
of the human soul something that is real fact. It is indeed
the Ahrimanic spirit who leads men round and round in a
circle, making them think in the way of Avenarius and Mach.
And at such moments Mach suddenly becomes aware of it. And it
is the same Ahrimanic spirit who is working now, in the
Bolshevist way of thought. Hence it is no wonder, my dear
friends, that the logic of realities has produced this
result. You see, however, that if we would understand the
things of life, we must look into them more deeply. Truly
this is of no small importance, especially for the domain of
social life, today and in the near future. For the
conclusions that must be drawn are not such as were drawn by
Schmoller or Brentano, Wagner, Spencer, John Stuart Mill or
whoever it may be. No, in the domain of social life,
real conclusions must be drawn, i.e., conclusions
according to the logic of realities. This is the bad thing,
that in the social agitations and movements of today, and in
all that they have produced, merely logical deductions
— i.e., illusions — are living. Illusions have
become external reality. I will give you two examples. The
one is already well-known to you, you will only need to see
it in the light in which I shall now place it.
The Marxian
Socialists (and as I have often told you, this includes
almost the whole of the proletariat today), the Marxian
Socialists declare, under the influence of Marx: Economic
life, economic oppositions, and the class oppositions that
arise from them — these things are the true reality.
Everything else is an ideological superstructure. What man
thinks, what he creates in poetry and art, what he thinks
about the State or about life in general, all this is a mere
result of his economic mode of life. And for this reason the
proletariat of today declares: — We need no National
Assemblies to bring about a new social order. For in the
National Assemblies there will be the bourgeois folk once
more and they will have their say out of their
economically-determined bourgeois minds. We have no use for
that. We can only do with those who will voice the thoughts
of Proletarian minds. It is they who must re-mold the world
today. To this end we do not first need to summon National
Assemblies. Let the few Proletarians who happen to be on top
exercise a dictatorship. They have proletarian ideas, they
will think the right thoughts. Not only Lenin and Trotsky in
Russia, Karl Liebknecht in Berlin repudiates the National
Assembly. He says: After all, it will be no more than a
reassembly of the talk-shop — meaning the Reichstag,
the Houses of Parliament.
What is the
underlying reason, my dear friends? It is the same reason on
account of which, in the main, I was driven out of the
Socialist Working Men's College in Berlin sixteen years ago,
as I told you recently when giving you the history of my
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity.
In that College I
had to lecture among other things on scientific matters; I
conducted practical lessons in public speaking. But I also
had to teach History. And I taught it in the way in which I
assumed, objectively, that it should be taught. This was
certainly satisfying to those who were my pupils, and if it
could have been continued — if it had not been brought
to an artificial end — I know it would have borne good
fruit. But the Social-Democratic leaders discovered that I
was not teaching Marxism or the Marxian conception of
history. Nay more, they discovered that I even did such
curious wild things as I will now relate (which incidentally
were very well-received by the workers who were my pupils).
I said, for instance, on one occasion: The ordinary historian
cannot make anything of the story of the seven Roman kings,
they even regard it as a myth. For the succession of the
seven kings, as described by Livy, shows a kind of rise and
decline. Up to Marcius, the fourth, it rises to a kind of
climax. Then it declines to decadence in the seventh,
Tarquinius Superbus. And I explained to my pupils that we
were here going back to the most ancient period in Roman
evolution, the period before the Republic, and that the
change to the Republic had in fact consisted in this: that
the ancient atavistic spiritual regularities had passed into
a kind of popular chaos; whereas, in the more ancient period,
as we can see quite tangible in the history of the Egyptian
Pharaohs, the social institutions contained a certain wisdom,
discoverable by Spiritual Science. It is not for nothing that
we are told how Numa Pompilius received influences from the
Nymph Egeria, to order the social life. Then I explained how
men did indeed receive Inspirations for the social
institutions which they were to make; and how in truth it was
not merely the one monarch following the other as in later
times, but these things were determined according to the laws
received from the Spiritual World. Hence the regularity in
the succession of the Egyptian Pharaohs and even of the Roman
kings, Romulus, Numa Pompilius, and so on down to Tarquinius
Superbus.
Now you may
take the seven principles of man which I summed up in my
Theosophy
and regard them one after another from a
certain point of view. You will find these seven principles
in the succession of the Roman kings. Here, at this present
moment, I am only hinting at the fact, and among you I need
do no more. Nevertheless it is a thing which, rightly
expressed, can well be described as an objective truth,
throwing real light on the peculiar circumstances which the
ordinary materialistic historian cannot understand. Today
indeed, the “genuinely scientific” historians
simply regard the seven kings as non-existent, and describe
them as a myth.
So you see, I
really went so far as this. And in other matters, too, I
spoke to them in this way. If it is done rightly, it gives
the impression of answering to the realities. Still it is not
the “Materialistic Conception of History.” For
that would mean that we should have to investigate what were
the economic conditions in ancient Roman times, what was the
relation of the tillage of the soil to the breeding of cattle
and to trade and the life; and how the cities were founded,
and what was the economic life of the Etruscans, and how the
Etruscans traded with the young Roman people; and how under
the influence of these economic elements, conditions took
shape under Romulus, Numa Pompilius, Tullus Hostilius, and so
on, in succession.
You see, even
this would not have been effected quite so simply. But here
again the true Reality came to my assistance. Of course, such
an audience did not consist merely of young people. There
were many among them who had already absorbed the Proletarian
thought to a considerable extent and who were well-equipped,
well-armed with all these prejudices. Such people are by no
means easy to convince, even when one is speaking of things
remote from their domain of knowledge. On one occasion I was
speaking about Art. I had described what Art is, and its
influence, and suddenly from the back of the hall a lady
cried out, interrupting: “Well, and Verism, isn't that
Art?”
So you see,
these people were not prone to take things simply on
authority. It was a question of finding a way to them; not of
finding the way to them by all manner of sly devices, but out
of a sense of Reality and Truthfulness. And so it came about
that one had to say — not only could, but had to say
— “You folk are primed with ideas of the
‘Materialist Conception of History,’ which
believes that all things depend on the economic conditions,
and that the spiritual life is but an ideology, spreading
itself out on the basis of the economic conditions, and
indeed, Marx expounded these things with clear and sharp
insight. But why did all this come about? Why did he describe
and believe all this? Because Marx only saw the immediate and
present age in which he lived. He did not go back to former
ages. Marx only based himself on the historic evolution of
man since the sixteenth century, and here in deed and truth
there came into the evolution of mankind an epoch during
which over a large part of the world the spiritual life
became an expression of the economic conditions, though not
exactly as Marx describes it. True, Goetheanism is not to be
derived from the economic life; but Goethe was regarded even
by these people as a man remote from the economic life.
Thus we might
say that this was the mistake, that which held true only for
a certain space of time, notably for the most recent time of
all, was generalized. Indeed, only the last four centuries
could be truly understood by describing them in the sense of
the Materialist Conception of History.
Now this is the
important thing: We must not proceed by the mere logic of
concepts; for by the logic of concepts very little can be
said against the carefully and strictly guarded propositions
of Karl Marx. We must proceed by the logic of life, the logic
of realities, the logic of things seen. If we do so, the
following will be revealed. Beneath this evolution which has
taken place since the 16th century in a way that can well be
interpreted through the materialist conception of history
— beneath this Evolution there is a deeply
significant Involution. That is to say, there is
something that takes its course invisibly, supersensibly,
beneath what is visible to the outer senses. This is seeking
to come forth to the surface, to work its way forth out of
the souls of men; and it is the very opposite of Materialism.
Materialism only becomes so great and works so in order that
man may rear himself up against it, in order that he may find
the possibility to seek the Spiritual out of the depths of
his own Being during this age of the Spiritual Soul, and thus
attain Self-consciousness in the Spirit. Thus the task is
not, as Karl Marx believes, simply to look at the outer
reality and read from it the proposition that economic life
is the real basis of ideology; but the task is rather this:
We must say to ourselves, the outer reality since the 16th
century does not reveal the true reality. The true reality
must be sought for in the spirit; we must find, above all,
that social order which will counter-balance and overcome
what appears outwardly or is outwardly observable since the
16th century. The age itself compels us, not merely to
observe the outer processes but to discover something that
can work into them as a corrective. What Marxism has turned
upside down must be set right again.
It is
extraordinarily important for us to know this. In this
instance the logic of realities actually reverses the mere
sharp-witted dialectics of Karl Marx. Alas, much water will
have yet to flow down the Rhine before a sufficient number of
people will realize this necessity, to find the logic of
reality, the logic of things seen. Yet it is necessary
— necessary above all on account of the burning social
questions.
That is the one
example. For the other, we may take our start from some of
the things I told you yesterday. I said: It is characteristic
how men have observed, ever since Ricardo, Adam Smith and the
rest, that the economic order entails this consequence: That
in the social life of man together, human labor-power is used
like a commodity, brought on to the market like a commodity,
treated like a commodity after the laws of supply and demand.
As I explained yesterday, this is the very thing that excites
and acts as motive impulses in the proletarian
world-conception. Now one who merely thinks in the logic of
concepts, observing that this is so, will say to himself: we
must therefore find an economic science, a social science, a
conception of social life, which reckons with this fact. We
must find the best possible answer to the question:
“Seeing that labor power is a commodity, how can we
protect this commodity, labor power, from
exploitation?” But the question is wrongly put, wrongly
put not only out of theory, but out of life itself. The
putting of questions wrongly is having a destructive,
devastating effect in real life today. And it will continue
to do so if we do not find the way to reverse it. For here
once more the thing is standing on its head and must be set
upright again, we must not ask: How shall we make the social
structure so that man cannot be exploited, in spite of the
fact that his labor power is brought on to the market like
any other commodity, according to supply and demand.
For there is an
inner impulse in human evolution which works in the logic of
realities, although people may not express it in these words.
It corresponds to reality and we can state it thus: Even the
Grecian Age, the Grecian civilization which has come to mean
so much for us, is only thinkable through the fact that a
large proportion of the population of Greece were slaves.
Slavery, therefore, was the premise of that ancient
civilization which signifies so very much to us. So much that
the most excellent philosopher, Plato, considered slavery
altogether as a justified and necessary thing in human
civilization. But the evolution of mankind goes forward.
Slavery existed in antiquity and as you know, mankind began
to rebel against it, quite instinctively to rebel against men
being bought and sold. Today we may say it is an axiom: The
whole human being can no longer be bought and sold; and where
slavery still exists, we regard it as a relic of barbarism.
For Plato, it was not barbarism; it went without saying that
there were slaves, just as it did for every Greek who had the
Platonic mind, nay every Greek who thought in terms of the
state. The slave himself thought just the same, it went
without saying that men could be sold, could be put on the
market according to the laws of supply and demand, though of
course not like mere cattle. Then, in a masked and veiled
form, the thing passed over into the milder form of slavery
which we call serfdom. Serfdom lasted very long, but here
again mankind revolted.
And to our own
time this relic has remained. The whole human being can no
longer be sold, but only part of him, namely his labor-power.
And today man is revolting against this too. It is only a
continuation of the repudiation of slavery, if in our time it
is demanded that the buying and selling of labor-power be
repudiated. Hence it lies in the natural course of human
evolution for this opposition to arise against labor-power
being treated as a commodity, functioning as a commodity in
the social structure. The question, therefore, cannot be put
in this way: How shall man be protected from exploitation?
— assuming as an axiomatic premise that labor-power is
a commodity. This way of thinking has become habitual since
Ricardo, Adam Smith and others, and is in reality included in
Karl Marx and in the proletarian conception. Today it is
taken as an axiom that labor-power is a commodity. All they
want to do is, in spite of its being a commodity, to protect
it from exploitation, or rather to protect the worker from
the exploitation of his labor-power. Their whole thought
moves along these lines. More or less instinctively or
— as in Marx himself— not instinctively, they
take it as an axiom. Notably the ordinary run of Political
Economists who occupy the professional chairs assume it is an
axiom from the very outset, that labor-power is to be
treated, economically speaking, on the same basis as a
commodity.
In these
matters countless prejudices are dominating our life today:
and prejudices are disastrous above all in this sphere of
life. I am well aware how many there may be, even among you,
who will regard it as a strange expectation, that you should
spend your time in going into all these things. But we cannot
possibly study the fullness of life if we are unable to think
about these things. For if we cannot do so, we become the
victims of all manner of absurd suggestions. How many an
illustration the last four years have provided; what have
they not brought forth? One could witness the most
extraordinary things: I will only give you one example.
Returning again and again to Germany — and in other
places it was no different — every time, one found
there was some new watchword, some new piece of instruction
for the true patriot. Thus, the last time we went back to
Germany, once more there was a new patriotic slogan: Do not
pay in cash! Deal in checks as much as possible! i.e., do not
let money circulate, but use checks. People were told that
this was especially patriotic, for, as they thought, this was
necessary in order to help win the war. No one saw through
this most obvious piece of nonsense. But it was not merely
said, it was propagated with a vengeance, and the most
unbelievable people acted up to it — people of whom you
might have supposed that they would understand the rudiments
of economics — directors of factories and industrial
undertakings. They too declared: pay in check and not in
ready money, that is patriotic!
That fact is,
it would be patriotic, but only under one
assumption, namely this: you would have to calculate on each
occasion how much time you saved in dealing in checks instead
of ready money. True, most people cannot perform such a
reckoning, but there are those who can. Then you would have
to add up all the time that was saved, and come up and say: I
have been paying my accounts in checks and have saved so much
time, I want to spend it usefully; please give me a job! Only
if you did so would it be a real saving. But of course they
did not do so, nor did it ever occur to them that the thing
would only have a patriotic importance on economic grounds on
this assumption. Such nonsense was talked during the last
four and a half years to an appalling extent. The most
unbelievably dilettante propositions were realized.
Impossibilities became realities, because of the utter
ignorance of people — even of those who gave out such
instructions — as to the real connections in this
domain of life.
Now with
respect to the questions I have just raised, the point is
this: It must be the very aim of our investigations to find
out — How shall we shape the social structure, the
social life of man together, so as to loosen and free the
objective commodity, the goods, the product, from the
labor-power? This must be the point, my dear friends, in all
our economic endeavors. The product should be brought onto
the market and circulated in such a way that the labor-power
is loosed and freed from it. This is the problem in economics
that we must solve. If we start with the axiom that the
labor-power is crystallized into the commodity and
inseparable from it, we begin by eclipsing the essential
problem and then we put things upside-down. We fail to notice
the most important question — the question on which, in
the realm of political economy, the fortunes and misfortunes
of the civilized world will depend. How shall the objective
commodity, the goods, the product, be loosed and severed from
the labor-power, so that the latter may no longer be a
commodity? For this can be done if we believe in that
three-folding of the social order which I have explained to
you, if we make our institutions accordingly. This is the way
to separate from the labor-power of man the objective
commodities, the goods, which are, after all, loosed and
separated from the human being.
It must be
admitted, my dear friends, that we find little understanding
as yet for these things, derived as they are from the
realities. In 1905 I published my essay on “Theosophy
and the Social Question,” in the periodical
Lucifer-Gnosis. I then drew attention to the first
and foremost principle which must be maintained in order to
sever the product from the labor. Here alone, I said, could
we find salvation in the social question, and I emphasized
that this question depends on our thinking rightly about
production and consumption. Today men are thinking altogether
on the lines of Production. We must change the direction of
our thought. The whole question must be diverted from
Production to Consumption. In detail, one had occasion to
give many a piece of advice: but through the inadequate
conditions and other insufficiencies, such advice could not
really take effect, as one experienced — unhappily
— in many cases. And it is so indeed; the men of today,
through their faith in certain logical conclusions, which
they mistake for real conclusions, have no sense for the need
of looking at the Realities. But in the social domain above
all it is only the Reality which can teach us the right way
to put our questions. Of course people will say to you: Do
you not see that it is necessary for labor to be done if
commodities are to be produced? That is so indeed. Logically,
commodities are the result of labor. But Reality is a very
different thing from Logic.
I have
explained this to our friends again and again from another
aspect. Look at the thought of the Darwinian Materialists. I
remember vividly the first occasion — it was in the
Munich group — when I tried to make this clear to our
friends. Imagine a real, thorough-going follower of Haeckel.
He thinks that man has arisen from an apelike beast. Well,
let him as a scientist form the concept of an ape-like animal
and then let him form the concept of Man. If as yet no man
existed and he only had the concept of the ape-like animal,
he would certainly never be able to “catch,” out
of this concept of the animal, the concept Man. He only
believes what [in?] the ape-like creature, because the one
proceeded out of the other in reality. Thus in real life men
do after all distinguish between the logic of pure concepts
and ideas and the logic of things seen. But this distinction
must be applied through and through; otherwise we shall never
gain an answer to the social and political questions, such as
is necessary for the present and the immediate future. If we
will not turn to that realistic thinking which I have
explained to you once more today, we shall never come to the
Goetheanic principle in public life. And that the Goetheanic
principle shall enter into the world, this we desired to
signalize by erecting, upon this hill, a
“Goetheanum.”
In humorous
vein, I would advise you to read the huge advertisement that
appeared on the last page of today
Basler Nachrichten,
calling on everyone to do all in his power
for the greatest day in world-history which is now about to
dawn, by founding a “Wilsoneanum.” True, as yet,
it is only an advertisement, and I only mention it in a
jocular spirit. Nevertheless, in the souls of men, to say the
least of it, the “Wilsoneanum” is being founded
pretty intensely at the present moment.
As I said a
short while ago, it has indeed a certain meaning that there
is now a Goetheanum standing here. I called it a piece of
“negative cowardice.” The opposite of cowardice
was to come to expression in this action. And it is indeed
the case, my dear friends, events are coming in the future
— though this advertisement is only an amusing prelude
— events are coming which will seem to justify this
prophetic action which is being made out of the spirit of a
certain world-conception. Though we need not take the
half-page advertisement for a “Wilsoneanum”
seriously, it is well for us to know that Wilsoniana will
indeed be founded. Therefore a Goetheanum was to stand here
as a kind of protest in advance.
|