Thomas Aquinas and Augustine
Dornach, 22 May 1920
During these three days, I would like to
speak about a topic that one normally considers from a more
formal aspect, and whose contents one normally only considers
that the position of the philosophical worldview to
Christianity was fixed as it were by the underlying
philosophical movement of the Middle Ages. Because just this
aspect of the matter was recently refreshed because Pope Leo
XIII called on his clerics to do Thomism the official
philosophy of the Catholic Church, our present topic has a
certain significance from this side.
However, I would just like to look not only
from this formal aspect at the matter that is connected as
medieval philosophy with the central personalities of Albert
the Great (1193-1280) and Thomas Aquinas (~1225-1274), but in
the course of these days I would like to show the deeper
historical background from which this philosophical movement
arose which our time appreciates too little. One can say that
Thomas Aquinas tried to grasp the problem of knowledge, of the
complete worldview in a quite astute way in the thirteenth
century, in a way that is hard to comprehend with our thinking
today because conditions are part of reflection that the human
beings of the present hardly fulfil, even if they are
philosophers. It is necessary that you can completely project
your thoughts in the way of thinking of Thomas Aquinas, his
predecessors and successors that you know how you have to
understand the concepts which lived in the souls of these
medieval people about which, actually, the history of
philosophy reports quite externally.
If you look now at the centre of our
consideration, at Thomas Aquinas, he is a personality that
disappears, compared with the main current of Christian
philosophy in the Middle Ages, as a personality as it were who
is, actually, only the exponent of that which lives in a broad
worldview current and expresses a certain universality with
him. So that Thomism is something exceptionally impersonal,
something that only manifests by the personality of Thomas
Aquinas. Against it, you recognise immediately that you look at
a full, whole personality if you envisage Augustine (354-430)
who is the most important predecessor of Thomism. With
Augustine, we deal with a struggling person, with Thomas
Aquinas with the medieval church that determines its position
to heaven, earth, human beings, history et cetera. It expresses
itself — indeed, with certain restrictions — as church by the
philosophy of Thomas Aquinas.
A significant event takes place between
both men, and without looking at this event, it is not possible
to determine the position of both personalities to each other.
This event took place in 553 when Emperor Justinian I (527-565)
branded Origen (185-~254) as a heretic. The whole colouring of
Augustine's worldview becomes clear only if you consider the
historical background from which Augustine worked his way out.
However, this historical background changes because that
powerful influence on the West stops which had originated from
the Greek academies in Athens and somewhere else. This
influence lasted until the sixth century, and then it
decreased, so that something remained in the western current
that was quite different from that in which Augustine had still
lived.
I ask you to take into consideration that I
would like to give an introduction only today that I treat the
real being of Thomism tomorrow, and that the purpose of my
executions will completely appear, actually, only at the third
day. Since I am in a special situation, also with reference to
the Christian philosophy of the Middle Ages, in particular of
Thomism, — you forgive for this personal remark. I have emphasised
many a time what I experienced once when I reported that before
a proletarian audience what I have to regard as truth in the
course of western history. It caused that the students took
kindly to that, however, the leaders of the proletarian
movement believed that this was no real Marxism. Although I
appealed to freedom of teaching, one answered to me in the
decisive meeting that this party knows no freedom of teaching
but only reasonable compulsion! — Hence, I had to
finish my teaching, although I had many students of the
proletariat who supported me.
I experienced something similar another
time with that which I wanted to say about Thomism and the
medieval philosophy twenty years ago. At that time, the
materialist monism was on its climax. To the care of a free,
independent worldview, but only to the care of this materialist
monism, the Giordano Bruno
Association was founded in
Germany in those days. Because it was impossible for me to take
part in all empty gossip and phrases that appeared as monism in
the world, I held a talk on Thomism in the Berlin
Giordano Bruno
Association. I tried to prove in
this talk that Thomism is a spiritual monism, which manifests
by an astute thinking of which the modern philosophy
— influenced by Kant and Protestantism
— has no
idea or has no strength for it. Thus, I fell out also with
monism! Today it is exceptionally difficult to speak of the
things in such a way that the spoken arises from the real thing
and is not put into the service of any party. Hence, I would
like to speak about the phenomena, which I have indicated,
during these three days again.
Augustine positions himself as a struggling
personality in the fourth and fifth centuries, as I have
already said. The way in which Augustine struggles makes a deep
impression if one is able to go into the special nature of this
struggle. Two questions rose in Augustine's soul of which one
has no idea today where the real cognitive and psychological
questions have faded, actually. The first question is that
which one can characterise possibly while one says, Augustine
struggles for the being of that which the human being can
acknowledge, actually, as truth fulfilling his soul. The second
question is, how can one explain the evil in a world that has,
nevertheless, sense only if at least the purpose of this world
deals with the good? How can one explain that never the voice
of the evil is silenced in the human nature also not if the
human being strives honestly and sincerely for the
good?
I do not believe that one approaches
Augustine really, if one interprets these two questions in such
a way, as the average human people of the present would like to
understand them. One has to look for the special colouring that
these questions had for this man of the fourth and fifth
centuries. Augustine experiences an internally moved, excessive
life at first. However, in this life both questions
appear repeatedly in him. He is in a conflict. The father is a
pagan; the mother is a devout Christ. The mother did her best
to win the son over to Christianity. At first, the son attains
a certain seriousness of life and turns to Manichaeism. We want
to look at this worldview later that Augustine got to know when
he changed from a dissolute life to a serious one. Then,
however, he felt more and more rejected — indeed, only
after years — by Manichaeism, and a certain scepticism
seized him from the whole trend of the philosophical life in
which at a certain time the Greek philosophy had ended, and
which survived then until the time of Augustine.
However, now scepticism withdraws more
and more. Scepticism
is only something to Augustine that brings
him together with Greek philosophy. This scepticism leads him to that
which exerted a deep influence certainly on his subjectivity on
his whole attitude for some time. Scepticism leads him to a
quite different direction, to Neoplatonism. Neoplatonism
influenced Augustine even more than one normally thinks. One
can understand his whole personality and his struggle only if
one recognises how much he is involved in the Neoplatonic
worldview. If one goes objectively into his development, one
hardly finds, actually, that the break, which in this
personality took place with the transition from Manichaeism to
Neoplatonism or Plotinism, recurred with the same strength,
when Augustine turned from Neoplatonism to Christianity. Since
one can say, actually, Augustine remained a Neoplatonist to a
certain degree. That is why his destiny induced him to get to
know Christianity. It is, actually, not at all a big leap, but
it is a natural development from Neoplatonism to Christianity.
One cannot judge the Christianity of Augustine if one does not
look at Manichaeism, a peculiar way to overcome the old pagan
worldview at the same time with the Old Testament, with
Judaism.
At that time, Manichaeism had expanded over
North Africa where Augustine grew up in which many people of
the West already lived. In the third century, Manichaeism came
into being by Mani, a Persian (216-277). History hands down
exceptionally little of it. If one wants to characterise
Manichaeism, one must say, it depends more on the attitude of
this worldview than on the literal contents.
It is typical for Manichaeism above all
that the separation of the human experience into spiritual and
material does not yet make sense. The words or ideas
“spirit” and “matter” have no sense for
Manichaeism. Manichaeism sees in that what appears material to
the senses something spiritual and does not tower above that
which presents itself to the senses if it speaks of the
spiritual. It applies to it much more than one normally thinks
that it assumes spiritual phenomena, spiritual facts, indeed,
in the stars and in their ways that it assumes that with the
sun mystery something spiritual takes place here on earth at
the same time. Something material manifests as something
spiritual at the same time and vice versa. Hence, it is a given
for Manichaeism that it speaks of astronomical phenomena, of
world phenomena in such a way as it also speaks of moral and of
events within the human evolution. Thus, the contrast of light
and darkness which Manichaeism teaches — copying the ancient
Persian worldview —
is something naturally spiritual at the
same time even more than one thinks. Manichaeism still speaks
of that what moves there apparently as sun at the firmament, of
something that is also concerned with the moral entities and
impulses within the human evolution. It speaks of the relations
of this moral-physical, which is there at the firmament, to the
signs of the zodiac like to twelve beings by whom the primal
being, the primal light being of the world, specifies its
activities.
However, something else is still
distinctive of Manichaeism. It considers the human being by no
means as that which the human being is to us today. The human
being appears to us as a kind of crown of the earth creation.
Manichaeism does not concede this. It considers the human
being, actually, only as a scanty rest of that which should
have become a human being on earth by the divine light being.
Something else should have become a human being than that which
now walks around as a human being on earth. That which now
walks around as a human being on earth originated because the
original human being whom the light being had created for
supporting him in his fight against the demons of darkness lost
this fight against these demons and was moved by the good
powers into the sun. However, the demons still managed
it to snatch a part of this original human being as it were
from the real human being escaping to the sun and to form the
earthly human race from it, which walks about on earth like a
worse issue of that what could not live on the earth here
because it had to be carried away into the sun during the big
spiritual fight. The Christ Being appeared to lead the human
being who was like a worse edition of his original destiny on
earth, and Its activity shall erase the effect of the demons
from the earth.
I know very well that not everything that
one can still put into words of this worldview by our word
usage, actually, is sufficient; since all that just arises from
the depths of the soul life that are substantially different
from the present ones. However, the essentials are that what I
have already emphasised. Since as fantastic it may appear what
I tell you about the progress of the earth in the sense of
Manichaeism, it did not imagine that as something that one can
only behold spiritually, but that a sense-perceptible
phenomenon happens at the same time as something
spiritual.
That was the first to work powerfully on
Augustine. We understand the problems that are connected with
the personality of Augustine, actually, even by the fact that
one envisages this mighty effect of Manichaeism, of its
spiritual-material principle. One must ask himself, why did
Augustine become dissatisfied with Manichaeism? Not, actually,
because of its mystic contents but because of the whole
attitude of Manichaeism.
First,
Augustine was taken in by the sensory
descriptiveness, the vividness of this view, in a way. Then, however,
something stirred in him that could not be content just with
the vividness with which one considered the material as
spiritual and the spiritual as material. One really does not
manage it differently, as if one goes over from
that which one has often only as a formal consideration to
reality if one looks at the fact that Augustine was just a
person who resembled very much the people of the Middle Ages
and maybe even modern people
than those people who were the natural
bearers of Manichaeism. Augustine already has something of a
renewal of mental life.
In our intellectual time that is prone to
the abstract, one considers that which goes forward
historically in any century as result of the preceding century
and so on. It is pure nonsense if one states that that which
happens, for example, in the eighteenth year of a human being
is a mere effect of that which has happened in the thirteenth,
fourteenth years. Since in between something takes place which
works its way up from the depths of human nature which is not a
mere effect of the preceding in the sense as one speaks of
effect and cause justifiably, but which is the sexual maturity
which just emerges from the nature of humanity. One has to
acknowledge such leaps also at other times of the individual
human development, where something works up its way from depths
to the surface; so that one cannot say, what happens is only
the immediately straight effect of that which has
preceded.
Such leaps also take place in the evolution
of humanity, and you have to suppose that the spiritual
condition of Manichaeism was before such leap and Augustine
lived after the leap. He could not help ascending from that
which a Manichaean considered as material-spiritual to the
purely spiritual. Hence, he had to turn away from the vivid
worldview of Manichaeism. That was the first to experience in
his soul intensely, and we read his words: “the fact that
I had to imagine bodily masses if I wanted to meditate on God
and believed that nothing could exist but of that kind
— this was
the most substantial and almost the only reason of error which
I could not avoid.”
Thus, he points back to that time in which
Manichaeism lived in his soul; and thus he characterises this
lifetime as an error. He wanted something at which he could
look up as to something that forms the basis of the human
being. He needed something that one cannot see as something
material-spiritual immediately in the sensory universe, as the
principles of Manichaeism did. As everything struggles
intensely seriously and strongly to the surface of his soul,
also this: “I asked the earth, and it spoke, I am not
that. And what is on it, confessed the same.”
What does Augustine look for? He looks for
the actual divine. —
Manichaeism would have answered to him: I
am that as earth, as far as the divine expresses itself by the
earthly work. —
Augustine continues: “I asked the sea
and the abysses and what they entail as living: we are not your
God, search Him above us. — I asked the blowing
winds and the whole atmosphere with all its inhabitants: the
philosophers who looked the being of the things in us were
mistaken, we are not God.” Neither the sea, nor the
atmosphere, nor everything that you can perceive with the
senses. “I asked the sun, the moon, and the stars. They
said: we are not God whom you search.”
Thus, he got free of Manichaeism, just of
the element of Manichaeism that one has to characterise,
actually, as the most significant. Augustine looks for a
spiritual that is free of anything sense-perceptible. He
lives just in that epoch of soul
development when the soul had to break away from mere
considering the sense-perceptible as something spiritual, the
spiritual as something sense-perceptible; since one also
misjudges the Greek philosophy in this respect absolutely.
Hence, people have difficulties to understand the beginning of
my Riddles of
Philosophy because I tried to
characterise it in such a way as it was.
If the Greek speaks of ideas, of concepts,
the today's human beings believe that he means that with his
ideas that we call thoughts or ideas today. This is not the
case, but the Greek spoke of ideas as of something that he
perceives in the outside world like colours and
tones.
What appeared in Manichaeism with an
oriental nuance exists in the entire Greek worldview. The Greek
sees his idea as he sees a colour. He still has the
sensory-spiritual, spiritual-sensory, that soul experience
which does not at all ascend to that which we know as something
spiritual that is free of anything sense-perceptible as we
understand it now —
whether as a mere abstraction or as real
contents of our soul, this we do not yet want to decide at this
moment. The soul experience that is free of anything
sense-perceptible is not yet anything that the Greek envisages.
He does not differentiate between thinking and sense
perception.
One would have to correct the whole
conception of the Platonic philosophy, actually, from this
viewpoint, because only then it appears in the right light. So
that one may say, Manichaeism is only a post-Christian
elaboration of that what was in Hellenism. One also does not
understand the great philosopher Aristotle who concludes the
Greek philosophy if one does not know that — if he still speaks
of concepts —
he already stands, indeed, hard at the
border of abstract understanding that he speaks, however, still
in the sense of tradition seeing the concepts close to
sense-perception.
Augustine was simply forced by the
viewpoint, which people of his epoch had attained by real
processes that took place in them among whom Augustine was an
outstanding personality, no longer to experience in the soul as
a Greek had experienced. He was forced to a thinking that still
keeps its contents if it cannot talk of earth, air, sea, stars,
sun and moon that does not have vivid contents. He has to push
his way to a divine that should have such abstract contents.
Only such worldviews spoke to him, actually, which had
originated from another viewpoint that I have just
characterised as that of the sensory-extrasensory. No wonder
that these souls came to scepticism because they
strove in uncertain way for something that was not yet there
and because they could only find that which they could not take
up.
However, on the other side the feeling to
stand on a firm ground of truth and to get explanation about
the question of the origin of the evil was so strong in
Augustine that, nevertheless, Neo-Platonism influenced him
equally considerably. Neo-Platonism or Plotinism in particular
concludes Greek philosophy. Plotinus (~204-270) shows
— what
strictly speaking Plato's dialogues and in the least the
Aristotelian philosophy cannot show — how the whole soul
life proceeds if it searches a certain internalisation.
Plotinus is the last latecomer of a kind of people who took
quite different ways to knowledge than that which one later
understood generally about which one developed an idea later.
Plotinus appears to the modern human being, actually, as a
daydreamer.
Plotinus appears just to those who have
taken up more or less of the medieval scholasticism as an awful
romanticist, even as a dangerous romanticist. I experienced
that repeatedly. My old friend
Vincenz Knauer (1828-1894), a
Benedictine monk who wrote a history of philosophy and a book
about the main problems of philosophy from Thales to Hamerling
was the personified gentleness. This man scolded as never
before if one discussed the philosophy of Neo-Platonism, in
particular that of Plotinus. There he got very angry with
Plotinus as with a dangerous romanticist. Franz Brentano
(1838-1917), the brilliant Aristotelian, empiricist, and
representative of the medieval philosophy wrote a
booklet What a Philosopher Is
Epoch-making Sometimes (1876).
There, he got just angry with Plotinus, because Plotinus is the
philosopher who was epoch-making as a dangerous romanticist at
the end of the ancient Greek era. It is very difficult for the
modern philosopher to understand Plotinus.
About this philosopher of the third
century, we may say at first, that what we experience as our
mind contents, as the sum of concepts that we form about the
world is to him not at all, what it is to us. I would like to
say if I may express myself figuratively (Steiner draws): We
understand the world with sense perception, then we abstract
concepts from the sense perception and end up in the concepts.
We have the concepts as an inner soul experience and we are
aware more or less that we have abstractions. The essentials
are that we end up there; we turn our attention to the sensory
experience and end up where we form the sum of our concepts,
our ideas.
That was not the way for Plotinus. To
Plotinus this whole world of sense perception hardly existed at
first. However, that which was something for him about which he
spoke as we speak about plants, minerals, animals and physical
human beings, that was something that he saw now above the
concepts, this was a spiritual world, and this spiritual world
had a lower border for him. This lower border was the concepts.
We get the concepts by turning to the sensory things,
abstracting and forming the concepts and say, the concepts are
the summaries, the essences of ideal nature from sense
perception. Plotinus said who cared little about sense
perception at first, we as human beings live in a spiritual
world, and that which this spiritual world reveals as a last to
us that we see as its lower border this are the
concepts.
For us the sensory world is beneath the
concepts; for Plotinus a spiritual world, the real intellectual
world, is above the concepts. I could also use the following
image: we imagine once, we would be immersed in the sea, and we
looked up to the sea surface, the sea surface would be the
upper border. We lived in the sea, and we would just have the
feeling: this border surrounds the element in which we
live.
For Plotinus this was different. He did not
care about this sea around himself. However, for him
this border which he saw there was the border of the world of
concepts in which his soul lived, the lower border of that what
was above it; so as if we interpreted the sea border as the
border with the atmosphere. For Plotinus who was of the opinion
that he continued the true view of Plato is that what is above
the concepts at the same time that which Plato calls the world
of ideas. This world of ideas is definitely something about
which one speaks as a world in the sense of Plotinism.
It does not come into your mind, even if
you are followers of modern subjective philosophy,
if you look out at a meadow to
say: I have my
meadow, you have your meadow, the third one has his meadow,
even if you are persuaded by
the fact that you all have the mental
picture of the meadow only, isn't that so? You talk about one
meadow that is outdoors; in the same way, Plotinus speaks about
one world of ideas, not of the world of ideas in the first
head, or in the second head, or in the third head. The soul
takes part in this world of ideas. So that we may say, the
soul, the psyche, develops as it were from the world of ideas,
experiencing this world of ideas. Just as the world of ideas
creates the psyche, the soul, the soul for its part creates the
matter in which it is embodied. Hence, that from which the
psyche takes its body is a creation of this psyche.
There, however, is only the origin of
individuation, there only the psyche divides, which, otherwise,
participates in the uniform world of ideas, into the body A,
into the body B and so on, and thereby the single souls
originate only. The single souls originate from the fact that
as it were the psyche is integrated into the single material
bodies. Therefore, in the sense of Plotinism the human being
can consider himself as a vessel at first. However, this is
only that by which the soul manifests and is individualised.
Then the human being has to experience his soul that rises to
the world of ideas. Then there is a higher kind of experience.
Talking about abstract concepts did not make sense to a
Plotinist; since a Plotinist would have said, what should
abstractions be? Concepts cannot be abstract, cannot be
in limbo, they must be the concrete manifestations of the
spiritual. One is wrong if one interprets in such a way that
ideas are abstractions. This is the expression of an
intellectual world, a world of spirituality. That also existed
in the usual experience with those people out of whom Plotinus
and his followers grew up. For them such talking about concepts
generally did not make sense, because for them the spiritual
world projected into their souls. At the border of this
projection, this world of concepts originated. However, only if
one became engrossed, if one developed the soul further, that
resulted which now the usual human being could not know which
just someone experienced who soared a higher experience. Then
he experienced that which was still above the world of ideas
which was the One if you want to call it this way, so he
experiences the One what was for Plotinus that which no concept
reaches if one could delve into it without concepts in the
inside, and which one calls Imagination
spiritual-scientifically. You can read up that in my book
How Does One Attain Knowledge of Higher Worlds?
What I called Imagination there delves into that which is above
the world of ideas according to Plotinus.
Any cognition about the human soul also
arose for Plotinus from this worldview. It is already contained
in it. One can be an individualist only in the sense of
Plotinus, while one is at the same time a human being who
recognises that the human being rises to something that is
above any individuality that he rises to something spiritual in
which he rises upwards as it were, while we are more used today
to submerging in the sensory. However, everything that is the
expression of something that a right scholastic considers as a
rave is nothing fictional for Plotinus, is not hypothetical.
For Plotinus this was sure perception up to the One that could
be experienced only in special cases, as for us minerals,
plants, animals are percepts. He spoke only in the sense of
something that the soul experiences immediately if he spoke
about the soul, the Logos that participates in the Nous, in the
world of ideas and in the One.
For Plotinus the whole world was a
spiritual being as it were; again it has a nuance of worldview
different from that of Manichaeism and that of Augustine.
Manichaeism recognises a sensory-extrasensory; for it, the
words and concepts “matter” and
“spirit” do not yet make sense. From his sensory
view, Augustine strives for attaining a spiritual experience
that is free of the sense-perceptible. For Plotinus the whole
world is spirit, for him sensory things do not exist. Since
that which seems material is only the lowest manifestation of
the spirit. Everything is spirit, and if we penetrate deeply
enough into the things, everything manifests as
spirit.
This is something with which Augustine
could not completely go along. Why? Because he did not have the
view. Because Augustine just lived already as a forerunner in
his epoch —
as I would like to call Plotinus a
latecomer, Augustine was just a forerunner of those human
beings who do no longer feel that in the world of ideas a
spiritual world manifests. He did not behold this world. He
could learn it only from others. He could only find out it that
one said this, and he could still develop a feeling of the fact
that something of a human way to truth is contained in it. This
was the conflict, in which Augustine faced Plotinism. However,
actually, he was never completely hostile to an inner
understanding of Plotinism, even if he could not behold. He
only suspected that in this world something must be which he
could not reach.
In this mood, Augustine withdrew into
loneliness in which he got to know the Bible and Christianity,
and later the sermons of Aurelius Ambrosius (St. Ambrose,
~340-397, Bishop of Milan) and the Epistles of Paul. This mood
persuaded him finally to say, what Plotinus sought as the being
of the world in the being of the world of ideas, of the Nous,
or in the One that one reaches only in special preferential
soul states this appeared on earth in the person of Christ
Jesus. — This arose to him as a conviction from the Bible: you
do not need to soar the One; you need only to look at the
historical tradition of Christ Jesus. There the One descended
and became a human being.
Augustine swaps the philosophy of Plotinus
for the church. He pronounces it clearly when he says:
“Who could be so blinded to say that the church of the
apostles deserves no faith which is so loyal and is supported
by the accordance of so many brothers that it handed its
scriptures conscientiously down to the descendants that it also
maintained their chairs up to the present bishops with
apostolic succession.” Augustine now places much value on
the fact that one can prove, in the end, — if one only goes
back through the centuries — that there
lived human
beings who still knew the disciples of the Lord, and an ongoing
tradition of plausible kind exists that on earth that appeared
which Plotinus tried to gain in the mentioned way.
Augustine was now eager to use Plotinism,
as far as he could penetrate into it to the understanding of
that which had become accessible to his feeling by
Christianity. He really applied that which he had received from
Plotinism to understand Christianity and its contents. Thus, he
transformed, for example, the concept of the One. For Plotinus
this One was an experience; for Augustine who could not
penetrate to this experience the One became something that he
called with the abstract term “being,” the world of
ideas was something that he called with the abstraction of
“essence,” psyche something that he named with the
abstraction “life” or also with the concept
“love.” The fact that Augustine proceeded in such a
way characterises best of all that he tried to grasp the
spiritual world from which Christ Jesus had come with
Neoplatonic, with Plotinist, he thought that there is a
spiritual world above the human beings from which Christ comes.
The tripartition was something that had become clear to
Augustine from Plotinism. The three personalities of
trinity — Father, Son, and Spirit — became clear to
Augustine from Plotinism.
If one asks, what filled the soul of
Augustine if he spoke of the three persons? One has to answer,
that filled him, which he had learnt from Plotinus. He also
brought that which he had learnt from Plotinus into his Bible
understanding. One realises how this works on, because this
trinity comes alive again, for example, with Scotus Eriugena
(John Scotus Eriugena, ~815- ~877, Irish theologian,
philosopher) who lived at the court of Charles the Bald in the
ninth century. He wrote a book about the division of nature
(De divisione
naturae, original title:
Periphyseon) in which we still find a similar trinity.
Christianity interprets its contents with the help of
Plotinism.
Augustine kept some basic essentials of
Plotinism. Imagine that, actually, the human being is an
earthly individual only, because the psyche projects down to
the material like into a vessel. If we ascend a little bit to
the higher essential, we ascend from the human to the divine or
spiritual where the trinity is rooted, then we do no longer
deal with the single human beings but with the species, with
humanity.
We do no longer direct our ideas so
strongly to the whole humanity from our concepts as Augustine
did this from Plotinism. I would like to say, seen from below
the human beings appear as individuals; seen from above
— if one
may say it hypothetically — the whole humanity
appears as a unity. For Plotinus now from this viewpoint the
whole humanity grew together, seen from the front, in Adam.
Adam was the whole humanity. While Adam originated from the
spiritual world, he was a being, connected with the earth, that
had free will, and that was unable to sin because in it that
lived which was still up there — not that which
originates from the aberration of the matter. The human being
who was Adam at first could not sin, he could not be unfree,
and with it, he could not die. There the effect of that came
which Augustine felt as the counter-spirit, as Satan. He
seduced the human being who became material and with it the
whole humanity.
You realise that in this respect Augustine
lives with his knowledge completely in Plotinism. The whole
humanity is one to him. The single human being does not sin,
with Adam the whole humanity sins. If one dwells on that which
often lives between the lines in particular of the last
writings of Augustine, one realises how exceptionally difficult
it was for Augustine to consider the whole humanity as sinful.
In him, the individual human being lived who had a sensation of
the fact that the single human being becomes responsible more
and more for that which he does and learns. It appeared almost
as something impossible to Augustine at certain moments to feel
that the single human being is only a member of the whole
humanity. However, Neo-Platonism, Plotinism was so firm in him
that he was able to look at the whole humanity only. Thus, this
state of all human beings — the state of sin and
death — transitioned into the state of the inability to be free
and immortal.
The whole humanity had fallen with it, had
turned away from its origin. Now God would simply have rejected
humanity if he were only fair. However, He is not only fair; He
is also merciful. Augustine felt this way. Hence, God decided
to save a part of humanity — please note: to save
a part of humanity —
God decided that a part of humanity
receives His grace by which this part of humanity is led back
to the state of freedom and immortality which can be realised,
however, completely only after death. The other part of
humanity — they are the not selected — remains in the state
of sin. Hence, humanity disintegrates into two parts: in those
who are selected, and in those who are rejected. If one looks
in the sense of Augustine at humanity, it simply disintegrates
into these two parts, into those who are without merit destined
to bliss only because the divine plan has wisely arranged it
this way, and in those who cannot get the divine grace whatever
they do, they are doomed. This view, which one also calls the
doctrine of predestination, arose for Augustine from his view
of the whole humanity. If the whole humanity sinned, the whole
humanity would deserve to be condemned.
Which dreadful spiritual fights did arise
from this doctrine of predestination? Tomorrow I would like to
speak how Pelagianism, Semipelagianism grew out of it. However,
today I would still like to add something in the end: we
realise now how Augustine as a vividly struggling personality
stands between that view which goes up to the spiritual and for
which humanity becomes one. He interprets this to himself in
the sense of the doctrine of predestination. However, he
felt compelled to ascend from the human individuality to
something spiritual that is free of any sense-perceptible and
can arise again only from the individuality. The characteristic
feature of the age whose forerunner Augustine was is that this
age became aware of that of which in antiquity the human being
did not became aware: the individual experience.
Today one takes many things as phrases.
Klopstock (1724-1803, German poet) was still serious, he did
not use commonplace phrases when he began his
Messiah with the words: “Sing, immortal soul, on the
sinful men's redemption.” — Homer began honestly
and sincerely: “Sing, o goddess, to me about the rage
...” or: “Sing, o muse, to me of the man, the
widely wandered Odysseus.” — These men did not
speak of that which lived in the individuality; they spoke of
that which speaks as a general humanity, as a type soul, as a
psyche through them. This is no commonplace phrase if Homer
lets the muse sing instead of himself. The fact that one can
regard himself as an individuality arises only gradually.
Augustine is one of the first to feel the individual existence
of the human being with individual responsibility. Hence, he
lived in this conflict. However, there just originated in his
experience the individual pursuit for the non-sensory
spiritual. In him was a personal, subjective
struggle.
In the subsequent time, that understanding
was also buried which Augustine could still have for Plotinism.
After the Greek philosophers, the latecomers of Plato and
Plotinus, had to emigrate to Persia, after these last
philosophers had found their successors in the Academy of
Gondishapur, in the West this view to the spiritual
disappeared, and only that remained which the philistine
Aristotle delivered as filtered Greek philosophy to future
generations, but also only in single fragments. This propagated
and came via the Arabs to Europe. This was that which had no
consciousness of the real world of ideas. Thus, the big
question was left; the human being has to create the spiritual
from himself. He must bear the spiritual as an abstraction. If
he sees lions, he thinks the concept
of the “lion” if he sees wolves, he thinks the
concept “wolf” if he sees the human being, he
thinks the concept of the human being, these concepts live only
in him, they emerge from the individuality.
The whole question would not yet have had
any sense for Plotinus; now this question still gets a deep
different sense. Augustine could still grasp the mystery of
Christ Jesus with that which shone from Plotinism in his soul.
Plotinism was buried; with the closing of the Neoplatonic
Academy in Athens by Emperor Justinian in 529, the living
coherence with such views ended. Different people felt deeply,
what it means: the scriptures and tradition give us account of
a spiritual world, we experience supersensible concepts from
our individuality, concepts which are abstracted from the
sensory. How do we relate to existence with these concepts? How
do we relate to the being of the world with these concepts? Do
our concepts live only as something arbitrary in us, or does it
have anything to do with the outer world?
In this form, the questions appeared in
extreme abstraction, but in an abstraction that were very
serious human and medieval-ecclesiastical problems. In this
abstraction, in this intimacy the questions emerged in Albert
the Great and Thomas Aquinas. Then the quarrel between realists
and nominalists took place. How does one relate to a world
about which those concepts give account that can be born only
in ourselves by our individuality? The medieval scholastics
presented this big question to themselves. If you think which
form Plotinism accepted in the doctrine of predestination, then
you can feel the whole depth of this scholastic question: only
a part of humanity could be blessed with the divine grace, can
attain salvation; the other part was destined to the
everlasting damnation from the start whatever it does. However,
that which the human being could gain as knowledge to himself
did just not arise from that into which Augustine could not yet
transform his dreadful concept of predestination; this arose
from the human individuality. For Augustine humanity was a
whole, for Thomas every single human being was an
individuality.
How is this big world process of
predestination associated with that which the single human
being experiences? How is that associated which Augustine had
completely neglected, actually, with that which the single
human being can gain to himself? Imagine that Augustine took
the doctrine of predestination because he did not want to
assert but to extinguish the human individuality for the sake
of humanity; Thomas Aquinas only faced the single human being
with his quest for knowledge. In that which Augustine excluded
from his consideration of humanity, Thomas had to look for the
human knowledge and its relation to the world.
It is not enough that one puts such a
question in the abstract, intellectually and rationalistically.
It is necessary that you grasp such a question with your whole
heart, with your whole personality. Then you can estimate how
this question weighed heavily on those persons who were its
bearers in the thirteenth century.
|