A critical-speculative study of the true spirit in
Kantian philosophy(1)
1. In
the rising and ebbing flow of thought in Kantian philosophy we only
really encounter a single firm point which has remained standing intact
in the fluctuating stream of dialectic: a consciousness of man's
moral-spiritual activity and autonomy, a belief in a moral world order.
The immediate force of Kant's ethical sentiment was stronger than the
logical consistency of his scientific thought. His repudiation of all
knowledge of the super-sensible,
his attenuation of ideas to merely restrictive regulators of empirical
knowledge would have also made knowledge of ethical-spiritual activity
impossible, if one were strictly and logically consistent. At most one
could have said that we can know nothing definite about moral-spiritual
activity, about an ethical world order or about a moral law, but we are
nevertheless permitted to practically arrange our lives as if the
empirical motives of pleasure, usefulness, and the like, were not the only
ones which influence our will. It is obvious that a merely hypothetical
morality like this would paralyze all moral activity. For if even the
firmest conviction in a seemingly binding, categorically-definite moral
law, and even the clearest consciousness of one's moral-spiritual activity
and responsibility isn't always able to eliminate an immoral attitude
and way of behavior and help the opposing moral motives to victory,
then the reduction of spiritual activity and moral law to a mere regulative
idea, to a mere subjective maxim, to an albeit admissable but unnecessary
hypothesis, to an itself entirely unrecognizable problem, would have
killed all morality in the bud. A live moral feeling, a certain inborn
moral instinct, induced Kant to negate this skeptical volatilization
of the ideal — with a resulting sacrifice of scientific consistency
in the moral sphere — and made him try to reinstate ideas to their
proper place as practical constitutive motives and as necessary postulates
of a moral world order. It is not enough for Kant to have broken up
the unity of the scientific system, so that human reason is divided
in itself, and a gaping chasm is opened up between theory and practice,
knowledge and moral faith; but he tries to turn this same unscientific
character of his viewpoint to advantage in building up his moral world
conception. Countless times, and most extensively in Section IX of the
Critique of Practical Reason,
he expresses himself to the effect
that the theoretical unknowability of the supersensible is just one
more reason to place practical belief in the same — and moral action
in accordance with it — that much higher. One doesn't believe that
one is listening to the father of modern philosophy, but to some scholastic
theologian of the Middle Ages when we are assured that this impotence
of our cognitional faculty in supersensible affairs is necessary to
make possible a truly moral attitude directly consecrated to the law
of duty. So as commendable as it is that Kant stopped his speculative
skepticism short of the shrine of ethics, it is just as undeniable on
the other hand that Reason thus set back and deprived of its rights
revenged itself on its offender and provided a stunning example in his
ethics that one dare not sacrifice clear, scientific conviction to
any kind of faith, and that it is a contraGiction to deny knowledge
of the supersensible to reason, and yet want to attempt a scientific
establishment and presentation of the super-sensible in a definite form
(i.e., transcendental spiritual activity). Fichte already opined
accurately, that is, observed accurately, but philosophized badly about
this contradictory behavior (N.W. I, p. 454). The more energetic
the attempts originating from Kant's ethical individuality are to develop
the fundamental principles of moral action in the greatest possible
purity, the more glaringly at all corners and edges that speculative
impotence appears, through which (in incomprehensible illusion) he
wanted to provide a free space for his ethical ideal. Therefore a very
mixed feeling comes over the critic when he's supposed to show how the
deepest thoughts and most genial conceptions of ethical consciousness
shrivel under the icy breath of theoretical skepticism and are held
back at a certain stage of semi-maturity.
2. The
first question is: how do we arrive at the concept of spiritual activity,
the central point of all morality? Not by an empirical path, because
nature shows us only mechanical causality, in which every change is
determined by a previous condition, so that the series of. these never
ends. Spiritual activity, however, is an attribute of the spirit, and
is the capacity to begin a series of actions by itself by means of an
original action which is not empirically or phenomenally conditioned
(Critique of Pure Reason,
pp.166–169 in Hutchins' edition).
(2)
If there were nothing but causality in the world there could be no question
of spiritual activity and hence of morality. But actually, besides nature
there exists the region of moral spirit, besides the realm of necessity
there is the realm of moral ought, besides laws of mechanical connections
there are the pure imperatives of reason (Ibid. p.167). The ethical realm,
far from being capable of being constructed or deduced from
empirical-phenomenal components — ex pumice aquam!
(water from stone) — is a realm of its own, abiding by ideas
into which pure reason fits the empirical conditions (Ibid. p.168).
It is this very realm of ought, of the categorical
imperative, of moral law, which is the cognitional foundation for the
highest concept of morality: spiritual activity
(C. Pract. R.,
pp.291–304). Spiritual activity is the real foundation of moral law,
moral law is the cognitional foundation of spiritual activity. Of course
the critic immediately has to oppose this description with reasonable
doubts. Moral law as distinguished from the law of nature contains exactly
the same problem as the idea of spiritual activity, only it is the concept
of spiritual activity from the point of view that its content is not
arbitrary but is a system in accordance with ideas, reasons or moral
motives, just as nature is a system of mechanical-causal mediation.
In the same act one knows the content of moral law and the content of
moral-spiritual activity. What Kant really wants to say is this: That
our knowledge of spiritual-activity is not immediately knowledge of
the full, positive meaning of the word. By reflecting upon our actions
we gain the consciousness to begin with, that certain actions which
we call moral can not be exclusively derived from empirical motives, but
rather that we go considerably beyond the empirical motives of pleasure,
displeasure, usefulness and the like in every moral action. Therefore
Kant rightly observes that our concept of spiritual activity is at first
a negative or practical spiritual activity in so far as we encounter it
in operation in practical affairs
(Critique of Practical Reason, H.
p.302). However, this dialectical means by which the concept of spiritual
activity is first given to us as a negative quantity (= insufficiency
of empirical motives in moral action) is only one side of its complete
concept, which immediately emerges upon sharper reflection. Namely,
if we observe that psychologically speaking the soul is never determined
negatively but always positively by some kind of a motive of a moral
or immoral kind, then from this viewpoint the concept of a negative
spiritual activity is meaningless; and those who understand spiritual
activity (freedom) only as a libertas a coactione (liberty
from necessity or compulsion) completely forget that with regard to
psychological determination it makes no difference whether I am determined
from without or within, and that true spiritual activity doesn't consist
of inner psychological necessitation at all, but rather that the worst
criminal as well as the conventionally most moral person find themselves
together in this realm of psychological determination. The concept of
ethical-spiritual activity is only then attained when one goes beyond
every necessitation by merely empirical motives; however this extension
and therefore this negative spiritual activity is itself only possible
by virtue of the capacity for positive spiritual activity. Purely negative
spiritual activity is contradictory from the standpoint of empiricism,
because the soul is always positively determined; it therefore also
cannot be the cause of phenomena, as Kant rightly observes
(Critique of Pure Reason,
p.169) it cannot become practical, and contradicts
its own concept. If on the other hand the concept of negative spiritual
activity cannot be abandoned because it is a necessary component of moral
consciousness, then what remains is to expand it to positive spiritual
activity and to elevate it into the region of true, transcendental,
ideal spiritual activity. If negative spiritual activity is one where
empirical causes do not completely determine us (Ibid., p.164), then
positive spiritual activity is a special way of drawing up the initiative
for one's actions out of the depths of ethical being or existence. It
therefore follows that negative spiritual activity is only possible
and comprehensible by means of positive spiritual activity, and those
who remain standing at negative spiritual activity in any form are like
the Hera of mythology who, laden with weights, was suspended between
heaven and earth. On one side the weight of empirical motivation presses
on them and prevents them from reaching the realm of spiritual activity,
on the other side they recognize morality to be a force which opposes
sensuousness and selfishness; out of the confused mixing — rather
than the dialectical connecting — of the two directions comes
negative spiritual activity — that one-sided abstraction of the
empirically given, which is incapable of lifting itself to the heights
of independent, positive thinking, and consequently eventually sinks
again into the depths of unethical behavior.
Thus,
if spiritual activity in its true essence has immediately proven itself
to be a positive force, and if we further recognize that moral law,
categorical imperative and the like only contain this essence in them
as if in paraphrase, then it's clear that we cannot get to know spiritual
activity through moral laws or the categorical imperative, or through
a feeling of ought or through any of its various moments at all, but
in the last instance we can only know it by means of an original and
direct self-reflection of the spirit on its own ethical nature — by
means of a practical a priori. It is still much less possible
therefore to establish the true concept of spiritual activity (freedom)
on a merely empirical path by comparison of various kinds of motivation,
or by abstraction from external compulsion, or the like. Even for the
simplest and plainest judgment of an action from moral points of view this
original practical a priori is necessary, and the only thing that
can be conceded to empiricism is that this a priori is developed
to ever greater clarity and purity through its exercise in our actions
in the empirical realm. But this also is not to be understood to mean
that the empirical exercise of morality as such could help us to greater
clarity about the nature and content of positive spiritual activity;
rather it is the practical consciousness of spiritual activity again
which in itself progresses to ever higher stages of power and purity
independently of all empiricism and only recognizes the limitations
in all empirical action above which it rises, the inadequate forms in
the battle with which the genius of spiritual activity unfolds its wings
ever more mightily and victoriously. Neither the Nemean lion not: the
twelve headed Hydra made Hercules, but the divine-like nature of our hero
became great in these partial trials by battling them, and this entire
empirical finiteness is only the battlefield for the ethical spirit on
which it, the spirit, is led on to ever more suitable forms of its being
and activity. What Kant therefore opposes to this view — namely as
if ethical cognition did not begin with spiritual activity — is
easy to refute and would, if it could prove anything, just as well
disprove the idea that moral law is the cognitional foundation for
spiritual activity. If namely to begin with it is said that the first
concept of spiritual activity is negative and that therefore knowledge of
the same cannot begin with it, then this objection is overcome by the
presentation of the practical a priori, which under all
circumstances, if ever so weakly and obscurely includes positive
knowledge. Positive spiritual activity is the first, original and
principal presupposition for the negative; we would never arrive
at a consciousness of what it means not to be necessitated
exclusively by natural or empirical motives if we didn't already
have some kind of knowledge of a system of higher motives which
practically and positively elevate us above that other series of
natural motives. A being that was completely and exclusively driven
by impulses which were foreign to the ethical realm in the strict
sense would on this account never even arrive at a negative spiritual
activity — and this simply for the reason that the so-called negative
spiritual activity in its true essence is really a positive instance
of it, and is only labelled as a merely negative faculty by reflection
which is not carried to completion.
The second
reason; that spiritual activity cannot be cognized from experience,
holds just as much for moral law; for what belongs to experience in
the latter (the expansion of the moral way of thinking into the system
of external actions) in its empirical existence cannot of course be
a source of knowledge for spiritual activity. If it is really true that
ought expresses a kind of necessity which otherwise doesn't occur in
all of nature
(Critique of Pure Reason,
p. 167), and if morality
essentially consists in being determined by the imperative ought, then
morality and with it the law and principle of morality cannot be cognized
by external, natural or even psychological means. But what belongs to
the inner ethical way of thinking in the realization of moral law is
precisely identical with the idea of positive spiritual activity, and
therefore knowledge of the ethical can begin just as well with spiritual
activity as with moral law. The only serious objection which Kant could
bring to bear against the cognition of spiritual activity by an original
act of practical self-consciousness, was his aversion for
“intellectual Anschauung” (‘intuition’ in
Hutchins) by means of which alone spiritual activity can be known as a
positive concept
(Critique of Practical Reason,
p.303). But after
all, one should no longer have to prove that the a priori synthetic
function, the transcendental self-consciousness, in the
Critique of Pure Reason
by its very nature and according to its tendency is or can
be anything else but exactly intellectual Anschauung, that is, a function
of reason in which the intellect as a thinking intellect recognizes itself
at the same time as the principle of and source of Anschauung's (that is,
perceptual) activity. Now just as in the theoretical realm transcendental
apperception is the highest principle of all intellectual activity, which
therefore cannot be understood by any subordinate, isolated fact of
experience, so in the practical realm an original, practical
self-consciousness is the source of consciousness of spiritual activity.
Both the theoretical and the practical a priori coincide in their
logical form: it is pure reason or intellectual Anschauung which is the
basis for both. As far as content goes, however, the practical a
priori is an extension of the theoretical one, and the idea of
spiritual activity is precisely the essence or the deepest form of
the a priori function, of transcendental self-consciousness, of
“intellectual Anschauung”.
If therefore in this realm of pure reason empiricism is inadequate to
establish a knowledge of the philosophical principle, if the latter
can only enter our consciousness by an original, synthetic action of
the spirit, then therefore eo ipso (by itself) it is also proven
that spiritual activity (pure reason in its highest and most perfect
form) can only begin with an original, transcendental, absolutely synthetic
act of our spirit, and only through such can it become an object of
knowledge. There can therefore no longer be any question about a derivation
of spiritual activity from moral law as a fact still different from
the former, and Kant would have done well to pursue more seriously his
conjecture expressed in the footnote for the beginning of §6, that
probably the only unconditioned law is the self-consciousness of pure,
practical reason, and that the latter is identical with the positive
concept of spiritual activity (Ibid., p.302). It remained for Fichte
to bring out the. principal significance of the idea of spiritual activity
for the theoretical as well as the practical realm; but also in Kant
everything which is advanced about spiritual activity depends upon that
original, practical self-consciousness of the spirit, and upon the unspoken
presupposition that spiritual activity can only be known by means of
a free, original, unconditioned act of the spirit.
3. Kant
gave his whole investigation of moral law and of the nature of spiritual
activity a wrong turn from the start in that he considered moral law
to be a mere legislative form, and everything material in morality,
all content-containing motives of the will to be simply a contamination
of the ethical realm. According to this then, spiritual activity is
also defined generally as total independence from the laws of nature
and as determination purely by the law-giving form (Ibid., § 5
and 6, p.301). Now to be sure, it is quite correct that the principle
of morality cannot coincide with any of its manifold manifestations
in moral life, because each of these can only appear and gain validity
under the presupposition of an all-comprehensive ethical context; but
this doesn't begin to prove that the moral principle must disregard
all content, all particular character and peculiar nature of the phenomenal
will, and that it has to make laws as a purely abstract, general form.
Rather it is obvious that an empty form loses all definiteness and all
relation to the situations given empirically and also that the expansion
of a moment — simply separated from this phenomenal world —
into the latter becomes impossible (and so does the entire system of
objective morality), if the ethical principle is supposed to be only the
empty form, while the phenomenal world is supposed to be the mere content
in contrast to the ethic-producing form. Aside from it being inconceivable
how an empty form would ever be able to produce the fulness of a most
manifold concrete content out of itself: spiritual activity in its truly
positive character is endangered and volatilized to a merely negative
independence from the empirically given. For this reason Kant never
quite succeeded in giving the idea of spiritual activity in a really
positive, clearly defined content; nevertheless we encounter definitions
in his work which do more justice to the ideas than anything else that
dogmatic philosophy before him has attained.
4. Already
in the so-called antithetic of pure reason
(Critique of Pure Reason,
p.141), Kant defined spiritual activity as the capacity to initiate
a condition, and therefore also a series of effects of it, so that nothing
precedes it whereby an action in progress is determined by existing
laws. This seems to sound very positive, but as it stands here it is
a completely negative and empty phrase which is incapable of being carried
out dialectically even in Kantian terms. A pure and simple beginning can
first of all mean two different things: it can mean an existence, a being,
an action or a thought which for us is a pure and simple presupposition
beyond which we can in no way go. An action would therefore begin purely
and simply if it were only defined and determined by this last, absolute
presupposition. In any case a condition would be established which
temporally speaking precedes our action and which causally speaking
conditions it according to an existing law. Such a beginning is apparently
not what Kant had in mind. Spiritual action should absolutely not
presuppose anything; it should begin a state and therewith a series of
states without precondition, it should be equipped with creative power in
the most daring sense in that it places a something in the empty place of
nothing (for “nothing” is presupposed). To be sure Kant also
expresses himself occasionally to the effect that spiritual activity is
the capacity of the subject to begin an action simply out of himself. But
this version runs into the same dilemma. Either the subject latches onto
a presupposed condition, existence or change in himself, or he creates
something similar out of nothing, whereby one should note that the
expression “out of himself” becomes invalid, since nothing
precedes the original action of the subject, and therefore also not on
an anyway already present, definite and responsible subject or ego, so
that the subject is necessitated in Munchhausenic fashion as causa
sui (cause of himself) to yank himself out of the swamp of
non-existence into the region of existence. In other words, a pure and
simple beginning in the Kantian sense involves the contradiction that
something existing (ego, subject) is treated as something non-existent
(which has to posit its state and therewith itself for the first time).
This is definitely not to say that transcendental spiritual activity
couldn't also acquire an admissable meaning, the discussion of which
however we'll have to reserve for another occasion.
5. A
more positive result appears to be provided by the definition in which
spiritual activity is formulated as the ability to be determined by
the mere form of a moral law.
(Critique of Practical Reason
§ 2, 3, 5, 6, besides notes; then the fundamental law § 7).
However, the wealth which seems to lie in this all-comprehensive moral
principle is only the outline of a general concept which is entirely
devoid of content and which depends on an abstract formulation of the
concept “law”. But what constitutes the content of a law is
the mode of action of components of existence itself, and it therefore
is something real, actual, concrete, and not a form merely floating
over things which one assumes will later compel the latter to obedience.
So moral law then also does not manifest itself in the human spirit
as a formula confronting man externally, before which he has to bow
down in bIfid obedience, he knows not why or wherefore. Where moral
law in this form is felt to be like a categorical imperative, or only
a command of a foreign power, there true morality, true spiritual activity
and autonomy are not present at all. Instead, no discrepancy should
exist anymore between the form of moral law and the content of my moral
action, between the law and the deepest essence of my ethical nature,
between the godhead on the world throne and the will which is destined
to take the former into itself, between the heteronomous command which
comes to me as the emanation of a higher or foreign power, and my spiritual
activity which is certain in its attitude and in its ethical action
of being connected with and one with that higher power in the deepest
ground of its being. In short, the form of moral law is either empty
talk, a concept which says nothing or it is the deepest substance of the
ethical-personal spirit itself, in other words, it is not just the most
universal or general moment of moral life but it is also at the same time
the most special or concrete one in every single ethical individuality.
Kant and all those after him who only talk about a general human nature
to which the single person feels obligated in his moral action has only
asserted the general nature of moral law and has therefore not advanced
at all to the concept of true spiritual activity as a moment of really
individualistic life. The consciousness of my moral duty is never an
abstract, but a concrete universal one, i.e., it must meet not merely
the generally valid requirements of moral life but also the special
and particular requirements and relations of the individual position,
setting, environment and the most complicated detail of the private
circumstances. Therefore, anyone moral action in concreto cannot
be produced by laborious reflection about what might possibly be applied
as a general rule by every person in a particular case or what might
agree with the general nature and dignity of the human spirit. Nor can
an unethical motive be overcome and silenced by general discussion.
Rather what is required at every moment is a directly active impulse
of the moral. principle (of direct ethical tact) which doesn't merely
accompany me in easily surveyable situations, but which — like that
Socratic daimon — stands at my side advising me or warning me even in
the most concrete and individual branches of practical life. Higher
than the categorical imperative — whose content I after all can only
gain by reflection about the multiplicity of human actions — is the
Fichtean teaching of conscience, which tells me in every single situation
of my existence what I'm supposed to do or avoid in this situation,
which accompanies me in all the events of my life and never fails to
advise me when I have to act, and which immediately convinces me and
irresistibly wins my approval
(The Vocation of Man,
Book 3: Faith I).
Also, he who only finds the moral rule to be applied in a given
case after laborious reflection and casuistic cleverness is lower in our
moral esteem, because in someone like this we miss the live moral
conviction and the undoubting certainty with which the ethical impulse
should grasp and shape the individuality of the particular case. Far
higher in our esteem for this reason is the open-minded moral
consciousness, the decisive firmness of the pure soul, the heroic
greatness of the moral genius who unites vivid warmth of feeling with the
clarity of his conviction. If spiritual activity is to become my spiritual
activity, a moral action my action, if the good and the right are to be
realized by me, by the action of this particular individual personality,
then I cannot possibly be satisfied with a general law which ignores all
the individuality and specialness of the factors competing with each
other in an action and which commands me to examine before every action
whether the motive underlying it agrees with the abstract norm of universal
human nature or whether the way in which it lives and works in me could
become a universally valid maxim: Aside from the fact that such an
examination could lead to no result, since I often hardly know what is
appropriate for me and my circumstances, seldom what is good for others
and never what is right for all, so I can never assure myself of the
universal validity of my maxim on the path of general reflection and
logical subsumption of the single case under the general categorical
imperative or under the idea of a universal human nature: aside from this,
such a leveling of my moral action to the general pattern, such an
adaptation to the generally customary and acceptable would make every
individual spiritual activity, every progress beyond the ordinary and
domestic, every significant, outstanding and trail-blazing ethical
achievement impossible. The majority of the proponents of the universal
human nature of the categorical imperative are known to be little suited
to serve as models of moral behavior, and whoever strives to guide himself
in his practical self-consciousness by the common sense of ordinary moral
practice will in any case never astonish the world with an outstanding
achievement, he will never belong to those who as ethically normative
people “pre-construct” spiritual activity for their fellow
man with a concrete example — not with a general concept. Precisely
the highest achievements of heroic
morality, e.g., the sacrifice of one's life in the service of the truth
and the just can never be deduced from general human nature and therefore
can also never become the content of general moral regulation, not because
such a deed would not be a moral achievement, but on the contrary, because
it is such an intense but individual achievement of the moral spirit
that an obligation for it cannot be expected generally, cannot be expressed
from the common sense of practical life, but can only be hoped for as
the emanation of an exceptionally highly intense, morally ingenious
individuality. Kant and all those after him who plague themselves with
their obligation to a general human nature, which from their point of view
can after all only be viewed nominalistically as a collective concept of
the. prevailing moral consciousness and not as a power which transcends the
manifesting particularity and concretion, all of these have not penetrated
to the deepest core of moral life. “In Kant especially there's
still quite a bit of that antiquated rationalism of the Enlightenment
period which doesn't respect anything which can't be fitted completely
into an exact logical formula. This explains his veneration for general
abstract formulae, the constrainedness and rigidity of his deductions
and divisions, the careful erasing of all personal advancement, which
he abhors as idolization, and the pedantical rigor which commands all
comfortable interests to sacrifice themselves to the cold paragraphs
of the law of duty. This also explains his subjugation of spiritual
activity (this most individual ethical principle in the human spirit,
from which everything springs which leads humanity beyond itself, the
highest and the deepest to which only a small number of the elect ever
advance) by the emptiest and most abstract principle of formal law
imaginable, which at most represents the average degree of practical
common sense attained at anyone moment, but never represents the creative
spiritual activity which carries the law of its moral action in itself.
6. We
meet a kind of equalization between the concrete idea of a personal
spiritual activity and the abstract form of moral law in Kant's concept
of autonomy. Namely, insofar as man can disregard sensual motives and
determine himself purely by a consciousness of moral law, he is
autonomous; the opposite of this — the determination
by sensual impulses, by any matter, or by an object of any kind
— heteronomy.
(Critique of Practical Reason,
8, Proposition IV, p.304). Now if we once and for all disregard
the erroneous opposition of the material and formal principles of
practical action it becomes easier for us to do justice to the deep
truth that Kant expressed with his autonomous moral principle. For
if it previously remained unclear what it meant that man has the
capacity to determine himself independently of the compulsion of sense
impulses”
(Critique of Pure Reason, p.164)
or “to
begin a series of actions by itself” and if it seemed downright
incomprehensible how in pure and simple un preconditioned action one
could call a deed into existence out of non-existence, then thanks now
to the idea of autonomy this causeless spiritual activity has become
thinkable. Namely, spiritual activity now means the direct determination
of the will by the condition of a generally binding moral law
(C. Prac. R., p.310, 321 ff.);
to begin an action
by itself doesn't mean to shoot it out of a pistol without any
mediation, but it means to be driven to an action by the content
of moral law alone; autonomy is not mere whim anymore or mere
negative spiritual activity, or mere indifferent liberty, but
it is a positive expression of the will on the strength of a
moral motive which doesn't lie outside the will as a sensory impulse,
but which constitutes the true essence of the human spirit and the
substance of the will itself. In short, autonomy signifies a fact of
greatest importance: that the content of the moral does not confront the
will as an external, foreign, merely abstract (general) law, but it is the
true substance and real essence of the human spirit itself. Hence spiritual
activity if understood truly and positively is also not different from
the content of moral law, but it is the capacity to be active as an
autonomous will, a true spirit and an ethical personality. By means
of autonomy, or ethical-spiritual activity, the human personality acquires
a new dignity and significance which could never accrue to it on an
empirical path. What is truly essential in the determination of the
human personality is not the ability to be determined by empirical motives,
is not the existence of and the activity in the terrestrial phenomenon
as such, is not the subjugation of the spirit to a foreign albeit moral
law and is not the authoritative guardianship of a will standing over
me, — but what's truly essential in the determination of the human
personality is spiritual activity firstly as negative independence from
the mechanism of the whole of nature, or from the whole sum of all
sense-dependent conditions (to which it should be added that the spirit
only matures under the authoritative discipline of a spirit confronting
it) and then secondly and most importantly, it is the ability to follow
specific, practical rules given in and by the reason. According to this,
man actually belongs to two worlds: the world of sense phenomena and the
world of ethical-spiritual activity. As a phenomenal personality however
and as a part of phenomenal existence he is subjected to the intelligible
personality, to the personality as ethical spirit. In the ethical spirit
therefore lies the content, substance and the true nature of man; in
ethical-spiritual activity resides his second and highest determination or
vocation; in autonomous self-determination lies the persistent stipulation
of that value which man can only give himself; from this point of view
every man can and must view himself with nothing but reverence and the
highest respect
(Critique of Practical Reason,
p.325 ff.).
However,
running along side these in every respect excellent and incontestable
definitions are others from which one can conclude that the conciliation
of moral-spiritual activity as a personal act of the ego, and the content
of an over-powerful, generally valid, moral law, was not entirely
successful. We see this especially from the way that Kant described the
relation of the feeling of respect to moral law. True autonomy and
therefore true morality is namely, as noted above, only present where the
content of moral law in no way confronts the will, either as empirical
rule or as a dictate of another person, or as an abstract general formula,
but where will and law, phenomenal individual and ethical spirit,
autos and nomos, limited self and unlimited content of
morality have become so completely united, that, as Hegel so excellently
puts it, the spirit's true consciousness of itself coincides with the
consciousness of its ethical-spiritual activity (W. W. XI, p. 62),
and that the phenomenal world — this whole natural existence —
is only felt as the medium in which and through which the ethical,
self-assured and mighty spirit reveals itself. This ethical-spiritual
activity as true self-consciousness of the spirit now reflects itself
immediately in our feeling life as the feeling of self-respect, as the
elevating consciousness of our moral dignity, and as a justified moral
pride which is inseparable from the ethical individuality. This feeling of
respect, however, is not essentially different from ethical-spiritual
activity, but is only the legitimate reflection of the same; it is also
— as Kant (loc. cit, p.323) rightly notes — not the primary
motive of morality, but morality itself, considered subjectively as a
motive. First, moral law objectively
and directly determines the will, and only then does the effect of this
determination on the feeling follow, on the one hand as displeasure
insofar as the sensual and selfish individual is suppressed, on the
other hand, as pleasure insofar as the individual obedient to the law
of duty becomes aware of his worth, his nobility, and his irrestible
power. Once this reflection in the feeling is present, it again can
act as a powerful ethical motive insofar as this highest enjoyment of
personal life induces man to provide and retain the same for himself,
and it is a foolish doctrinaire exaggeration of modern pessimism to
regard this striving for ethical eudaimonia (which is very essentially
connected with moral activity and is always conditioned by the same)
as a corruption of morals. With the same injustice Kant denied every
characteristic of pleasure or displeasure to the feeling of respect,
after he himself after all, described the depressing effect that sensuality
and selfishness — and the elevating effect that ethical behavior
— have on moral feeling, in a way which cannot be understood without
the inclusion of emotional moments (Ibid,. p.324); and in contradiction to
the positive nature of moral-spiritual activity and moral pride he only
ascribes a negative value to moral feeling (Ibid, p.326). Such
contradictions come about through Kant's wrong conception of pleasure as
a mere sensual affection; whereas pleasure itself in man — insofar
as he has begun to raise himself above the basest sensuality and animality
— has an essential spiritual and ethical significance; as all who
occupy themselves with the higher interests of spiritual existence
themselves experience
(Goethe: The song which pours from the throat is a reward which
rewards generously).
However,
respect for moral law as heteronomous morality understands it is quite
different. Here the content of moral law confronts the human will and
therefore can only be felt by the latter as an incommensurable,
overpowering quantity which suppresses and humiliates it. This discrepancy
between moral content and human will underlies all heteronomy, and is
everywhere equally false, no matter how the content of moral law is
conceived. In principle it makes no difference whether a moral law
confronts me in the guise of a human or a divine authority, and if in
affairs of moral life I'm conscious of perceiving anything else but the
voice of my own practical reason, then true morality is not attained at
all. Quite a bit of this heteronomy, or the moral respect (in the
heteronomous sense) connected with it, is even still clinging to Kantian
ethics. The reason for this is that Kant wasn't able to bring moral law
into a concrete form in which it appears as the innermost being of the
spirit itself. As a general law it always remains an abstract formula, and
one can't see how the spirit is supposed to find the highest expression
of its concrete individuality in it again. As an individual manifesting
outwardly I don't know how I arrive at this generally valid law; since
the connecting threads between the absolute ethical will and my individual
will are missing I don't know why this law should be binding for me,
and since it is purely and simply an abstract formula which says everything
and nothing I don't know how to apply it in a particular case. Lastly,
since this moral law demands of me a pure and simple renunciation of
all pleasure, of all individual well being, of all likes, and even of
all pleasure from the good, I can only see an oppressing, inhuman measure
in it, and the highest condition of all morality — consciousness of
the intimate connection of one's being with the ultimate ground of ethical
life — can never be fulfilled. The greatest respect for the solemn
majesty of this law, combined with a consciousness of his utter inability
to ever do justice to its dictates is the only feeling which man can ever
have for the categorical imperative. This duality however is an attribute
of heteronomous morality, and only in contradiction with this does Kant
allow our soul to rejoice at the magnificence of this law and to elevate
itself above itself to the extent that it sees the sacred law sovereign
above itself and its perishable nature (Ibid, p.324). Yet how can and
should a moral law — which in its terrible majesty and truly draconic
strictness goes far beyond human standards and which “cannot be
degraded to any intimate inclination” (Ibid, p.324), simultaneously
crush me and elevate me, let me feel my moral powerlessness and
simultaneously my moral greatness, fill me with heteronomous respect
for a transcendental command, and with autonomous respect for my own
moral dignity and sublimity? Because of his abstract-formal conception
of ethics, Kant is not in a position to bridge the gap between
heteronomous and autonomous morality, and yet his whole heart is
on the side of the spiritually active personality,
of which his poetic student said that it has taken the godhead into
its will and has filled the gap which separates the heteronomous and
therefore guilt-conscious conscience from the moral realm. A criticism
cannot help point out this vacillation between heteronomy and autonomy
in Kant, and yet it is only objective and just if it acknowledges that, in
spite of everything, the center of gravity in Kantian morality definitely
lies on the side of autonomous spiritual activity.
7. The
essential moment which underlies the entire preceding description of
spiritual activity — expressly pointed out by Kant, but neither
further secured against all objections of empiricism, nor investigated to
its full depth — is the thought that morality is capable of
influencing the human will directly
(Critique of Practical Reason,
p.310, 321); that therefore ethical-spiritual activity is completely
independent of all sensual motives and signifies a truly autonomous,
morally productive activity. Spiritual activity is — to use Kant's
own words — causa noumenon (thinkable but not
sense-perceptible cause): with complete
spontaneity it makes its own system of ideas into which it fits the
empirical conditions, and in accordance with which it declares actions
to be necessary which perhaps have never occurred yet, nor will ever
occur, but it equally presupposes for all actions that reason has causality
with respect to them, for without this it couldn't expect practical
results from its ideas
(Critique of Pure Reason, p.168;
Critique of Practical Reason,
p.318, 311 ff.). In my opinion Kant reached
the high point of his speculations in his idea of ethical-spiritual
activity as a transcendental causality (directly determined by the content
and ultimate ground of morality) which regulates the phenomenal world
by its own laws; with this he more or less made good the errors he incurred
in the founding of his principle of knowledge, in his treatment of the
absolutely synthetic a priori function, in his limitation of all
knowledge to experience of the phenomenal world, and in his overthrow of
all metaphysics. We don't want to hold ourselves up by describing how this
transcendental ethical causality in all points runs directly counter
to the end result of the
Critique of Pure Reason:
here transcendental apperception which has to be given the substance
and content of its activity from intellectual perception, there
transcendental ethical-spiritual activity which brings forth morality
(which as regards content and form is independent
of all empirical material) out of its own perfect power, and subjects
the phenomenon to this new system of ideas: here theoretical knowledge
which only is in a position to read phenomena as experience, there a
practical ability to order and shape phenomena in accordance with
supersensible motives: here the direct rejection of “intellectual
perception” of the intellect as a principle not merely for
conceptual thinking but
also for sense-bound thinking; there the just as direct admission that
positive spiritual activity can only be recognized by “intellectual
perception” and therefore the reality of the former guarantees
the truth of the latter: here the volatilization of all ideas to mere
things in themselves, mere negative limiting concepts, mere regulative
units of experiential thinking, there the consolidation of the reason-idea
to a positive magnitude, and the expansion of the empirical by the
transcendental realm of ethical-spiritual activity, or by the constitutive
force of moral activity: here the negation of all metaphysics, the
repudiation of all knowledge of the supersensible, there the restoration
of both as a science of pure, autonomous, practical reason. Kant never
became aware of the contradictions in which he entangled himself by tying
his teaching of transcendental spiritual activity to the final result of
his reason-critique. With complete certainty he once and for all convinced
himself of the sophism that reason is a supersensible capacity only
from a practical point of view, but that from a theoretical point of
view it is quite incapable of establishing anything about metaphysical
things. The less he was able to raise his ethical principle to the level
of a firmly established, scientific proposition, the more inwardly he
clung to the ethical fact itself, because he saw that the value of
our actions, the dignity of our personality, the significance of all
phenomenal existence depends on ethical-spiritual activity, on the
possibility of directly influencing the human will with moral law. Very
unlike certain modern proponents of philOsophical thinking and of so-called
higher education who — from the skeptical hollowness and the asthenia
of their speculative thinking ability — immediately derive the right
to throw the whole content of an ethical world conception overboard,
Kant held fast to ethical-spiritual activity as a last anchor-chain
which we dare not let go, even if a theoretical insight into its nature
and into the connection of jts members with each other and with the
rest of the positions of our existence is denied us. With the certainty
of unreflective instinct Kant felt that we here stand at the point where
the existence or non-existence of the world, in the highest sense, is
decided. That is, if the content of moral law is such that man can never
become consCious of it in its purity and its full power, then all
scientific endeavors to gain a conclusive principle of ethics are futile.
If the ethical principle does not possess the power to work regulatively
into the human will without any mediation, without any empirical admixture,
without depending on any impulse of pleasure or displeasure or usefulness
in the bad egotistical sense: then pure, unclouded morality remains
an ever unattainable ideal for man. If in the human personality — and
that means in everyone without exception — there isn't some point in
which — speaking in principle and ignoring empirical complications
— the power of sensual and selfish motives, the striving of bad
egoity, the domination of opposing evil is absolutely conquered, eliminated
and erased, then this selfishness, this bad egoity and this evil will
be regarded as irredeemable substance of the spirit, and therefore the
real possibility of an ethical world evolution in general, and ethical
progress in particular will be abandoned. So infinitely much depends
upon our grasping the pure and simple independence of the moral principle
— the absolute, transcendental causality in affairs of moral action
— with complete clarity and sharpness, and all the misery in all
areas of human life — in science, art and practical life — has
its origin in the skeptical dissolution of this fundamental norm in our
spiritual organization, the organization of our mental capacity. However,
if we look around for the reasons with which Kant supported the
transcendental causality of ethical-spiritual activity
(Critique of Practical Reason, II:
About the Right of Pure Reason etc., p.311 ff.)
then it is admittedly not difficult to prove that none of these completely
serve the purpose. In support of the concept of a causa noumenon
he has:
a. That
the concept of a cause springs entirely from pure reason. Not only did
Kant fail to prove this statement anywhere but he also directly upset
it again in that he limited the application of all categories to objects
of sense perception and rejected as inadmissable a so-called transcendental
use of the same above and beyond experience. But this is just the most
important thing about the causa noumenon. If the category of
causality refers exclusively to the phenomenal realm, then the idea
of a noumenal causality automatically falls.
b. The
causality concept's objective reality is ensured by deduction through
looking at the objects, i.e., it has factual validity. — Of course,
the validity of pure intellectual concepts is proven insofar as they
incorporate the condition that they have all possible experience in
them, but this proof is no help in establishing spiritual activity as
a causa noumenon. Throughout Kant empiricism is ruled by laws
of mechanical causality; spiritual activity however establishes a system
of ideas, a realm of ought, independent of the mechanism of nature.
Experience cannot be regarded as a valid witness to the factuality of
ethical-spiritual activity; rather, the fact and the content of the latter
— as well as the real possibility of its appearance in this world of
phenomena — must be established independently before it can be
determined whether any phenomenon, fact or action is an emanation of and
an objective description of ethical-spiritual activity. The
“empirical character” of transcendental
ethical-spiritual activity, i.e., a psychological-motivation
in accordance with definite rules, can only then be regarded as a type
or pattern of the “intelligible character” of the same if
we presuppose the idea of the latter and also presuppose the possibility
that reason has real causality with regard to phenomena
(Critique of Pure Reason,
p. 168); whereas it is quite impossible to establish
the reality of ethical-spiritual activity by beginning with its empirical
character. All conditions of nature, all mechanical connections have
no bearing on the determination of free will (spiritual activity) itself,
but only on the effect and the consequences of the same in the phenomenon
(Ibid, H. p. 168).
c. The
concept of causality as regards its origin is independent of all sensual
conditions. Very good, except that when expressed this precisely the
concept of causality is equivalent to the idea of transcendental-spiritual
activity and therefore cannot first be drawn in as proof of the latter's
truth. Rather the order of thoughts is the reverse: if the
Critique of Practical Reason
is incapable of independently developing the
idea of autonomous ethical-spiritual actIvity from observation of ethical
life and from the critical elaboration of the phenomena of the same, then
an a priori causality remains a logical abstraction without support
or content. This is exactly why in the
Critique of Pure Reason
Kant fell down again from the heights of a priori speculation into
the “bathos of experience”, because he was incapable of
connecting the idea of spiritual activity with the principle of knowledge
or of presenting the former as the truth and perfection of all speculation.
Since that time, one-sided logicism — which believes it can gain the
true philosophical principle from mere elements of intellectual knowledge
and that it can ignore real, objective ethical and metaphysical facts,
— has remained the hitherto unrecognized root evil of all
philosophical speculation.
d. As
a concept of non-sensible origin, causality cannot be limited to phenomena
but must also be applied to things with a purely intellectual nature.
Only, the non-sensible origin of a category merely indicates the negative
fact that the realm of sense experience does not constitute the only
content of our knowledge. But then how can spiritual activity be thought
as a positive concept by means of a merely possible, thinkable, but
empty concept?
e. However,
the extension of the causality concept above and beyond the phenomena
holds only for its practical use; in this extension, it theoretically
remains a merely possible and thinkable, but empty, concept. — It is
true that with the causality-concept (insofar as it is spread out over
the phenomenal world) we go over into the realm of transcendental spiritual
activity. But whoever maintains that for speculation this idea is a
merely possible and empty concept fails to recognize the unity of reason
(which comes to its sharpest expression precisely in this idea) and
makes it. into an irrational quantity and an object of an unscientific
faith. We are greatly indebted to Fichte for having raised the concept
of spiritual activity to the substance of all reason and to the central
point of every scientific world conception, and therewith for having
paved the way for the first time for the final reconciliation of all
dualistic ways of thinking. But more recent philosophers believe they're
doing something significant when in renewing the ethical-practical realm,
the realm of spiritual activity, and. religious faith they present Kantian
dualism as a noli me tangere, which philosophical speculation
has to keep away from its body as much as possible, that is, which it has
to consider and treat solely as an illusion of uncultured and uneducated
minds. Kant expelled the ethical-practical region from speculation and
banished it into the realm of faith; the later Kantians, who possess
the capacity of a unified world conception to a far lesser degree than
Kant, banish the content of faith into the realm of illusion. However,
modern positivism has drawn the final conclusion about this conception
in that it has reduced ideals in general and therewith philosophical
speculation itself to dreams of poetical phantasy. Therewith the series
of corrupted products stemming from Kantian dualism is closed, for now.
8. Now
although the reasoning by which spiritual activity was to be established
as a causa noumenon is invalid, the matter itself is by no means
settled hereby. Only, the path by which we arrive at the consciousness
of a direct determination of our will by the content of moral law is a
different one than Kant chose. If we are to arrive at a scientifically
valid concept of ethical-spiritual activity, then this cannot occur on the
basis of a “transcendental logic” (or, as one says now, theory
of knowledge) which negates the idea of spiritual activity by giving it
the form of a source of knowledge which is a priori, absolutely
synthetic and rational and independent of all empirical and perceptual
material. In logic it was wasted effort to only want to hold on to the
rational principle in anyone of its manifold forms of manifestation,
as percept, mental image, concept, judgment and the like and in ethics
it is lost labor to want to look for a capacity which first makes possible
an ethical action that is independent of all empirical motives and that
transcends all manifestations of moral consciousness. Furthermore, an
error which is connected with the one just mentioned is that one can put
things like the principle of speculation, a unified world conception, what
philosophy should be or wants to do — into a purely logical form,
such as: the three so-called laws of thinking, or a transcendental
apperception, or an absolute ego, or an absolute subject-object, or an
absolute knowledge. All these forms of the philosophical principle are
of a purely logical nature; they contain neither the principle of natural
existence nor the basis of ethical existence, and it is therefore
impossible to go
over to natural and ethical existence by dialectically irreproachable
means. The fundamental defect of all previous philosophizing, including
classical German idealism from Kant to Hegel lies in this one-sided
logicism, which builds up its world conception on the most abstract,
emptiest, and therefore least sound and promising foundations, and which
doesn't allow the further evolution of the system to follow from this
one-sided principle, but only places the single evolutionary phases
of the same side by side, or at most reconciles them with each other
by an abstract, vague expression such as “otherness”,
“return into itself,” etc. However, consistent thinking
would require that the
form in which the philosophical principle emerged at the end of the
dialectical course of evolution should also have been placed at the
foundation of the philosophical system as its true beginning. If instead
of a single empirical fact or the totality of the same (nature), or a
single logical law or the abstract expression of the same (the pure ego
or pure knowledge), and if instead of a finite form of the ethical spirit,
or the totality of its manifestations (the nature-free or world-free
abstract spirit) we place the absolute ethical spirit (as the principle
of the total natural and spiritual existence) at the foundation of the
philosophical system — only then can a unified world conception be
created in which its single members are not rhapsodically roused or placed
together externally in only a quite. abstract form, but are conceived to
be the inner essential expression of — and the continuously evolving
members. of — the absolute ethical spirit itself. In Kant the lack
of a unified world conception — and his one-sided logicism —
makes itself felt in that he failed in all of his attempts to establish
the concept of spiritual activity scientifically and also to reconcile
spiritual activity and nature — that sharpest expression of the
contrast between empiricism and rationalism, real and ideal, a posteriori
and a priori, observation and thinking.
9. The
first way that Kant believed he could unite spiritual activity and the
necessity of nature is by differentiating between the world as phenomenon
and the world as thing in itself. Insofar as things are phenomenon they
are subject to the laws of mechanical causality; insofar as they are
things in themselves, transcendental spiritual activity rules.
(C.Pu.R.,
p. 165ff.;
C.Pr.R.,
p. 328ff.). Every thing or
every human action can and must be considered from this double point of
view. Every action as a temporal phenomenon is conditioned by other
actions, i.e.,
by the sum and product of impulses working on the human soul. But every
action as an activity of a thing in itself, or as a noumenon,
or an intelligible character, has its seat in the spiritually active
self-determination of the subject and must therefore be ascribed to the
latter for good or bad, must be charged to it or given to its credit. This
mode of uniting nature and spiritual activity is already untenable for the
reason that the instance to which Kant refers — the distinction of
thing in itself and phenomenon — contains exactly the same problem as
the relation of spiritual activity and nature. For spiritual activity and
nature constitute precisely the greatest, sharpest, and most significant
contrast, which is only reflected in a diluted abstract-logical form
in the contrast of thing and phenomenon. As long as this universal,
ethical contrast of spiritual activity and nature (the absolute ethical
spirit and its manifestation in the manifoldness of sense phenomena)
is not settled by an independent path of metaphysical speculation, so
long the contrast of thing in itself and phenomenon will also haunt
“transcendental logic” and cognitional or scientific theory.
Only an unparalleled naivety would want to refer to that contrast as
a final solution of the world riddle, and the suspicious haste with
which the neo-Kantians of all confessions allow all problems which they're
unable to solve (Ideas, the supersensible, spiritual activity, religion,
the concept of God) to flee into the asylum ignorantiae of
the unknowable thing in itself, shows quite clearly that criticism has
only fluffed up a pillow for them so that their lazy thinking can take
a dogmatic siesta.
10. The
same problem returns in a different form in the
Critique of Judgment
insofar as here the contrast of the mechanical and the teleological world
conceptions is to be balanced. The progress which Kant made in this book
is as follows. In both the preceding critiques nature appears purely and
simply as the realm of mechanical causality and sense phenomenon. Every
phenomenon is conditioned by another one and the chain of conditions must
not anywhere be broken or torn off. Yet with the eoncept of a natural law
or an order of nature we already stand on ground which has a close
relationship to the content of the sensible. Kant expresses this
relationship of natural law to moral law in the sentence: By the form of
lawfulness in general, sense-world nature is to be regarded as the type
(Typus)
for intelligible Nature (for moral-spiritual activity). Every moral
action, insofar as it becomes manifest, must therefore correspond to
this type; it must carry the general form of lawful order in itself,
since it would otherwise conceal the order and connection of things.
If the maxim for an action is so constituted that it doesn't meet the
standard of the form of a natural law at all, then it is also morally
objectionable. By this rule, for example, all evil, selfish actions
are therefore already inadmissable because they would cancel natural
and social life if everyone consistently did them
(C. Pra R.,
p. 317ff.), Herewith Kant broke through the rigid dualism between nature
and moral law, and in the general lawfulness of the former he recognized
the connecting link (scheme, type, or sign) which leads nature over
to where it can be considered from ethical points of view. However as
nature is thus brought closer to the ethical realm, the latter takes
on a more universal form. If nature in the form of lawful connections
shows traces of a moral order, if morality in its external appearance
as practical spiritual activity (the sign and type of the transcendental
spiritual activity:
C. Pu. R., p. 235)
can only appear in the
form of a causal connection, then the conclusion lies extraordinarily
near that nature and spiritual activity no longer confront each other
as rigid quantities, that they also don't just stand next to each other
indifferently and unconnectedly like thing in itself and phenomenon, but
that a point can and must be found in which both diverging lines meet.
The Critique of Judgment
drew this conclusion and showed that
point in the teleological world view. In this last critique it is also
repeatedly and rightly impressed on us that the explanation of Nature by
mechanical causes in its proper place is a justified and necessary side
of the knowledge of Nature, but the final, comprehensive and in. the last
instance only satisfying view of Nature depends exclusively upon the
application of the teleological view. This teleological viewpoint however
consists in our advancing beyond the mechanical-causal connection of
things to the supersensible, which lies beyond every possible empirical
mental image of Nature
(C.J.,
p. 558). In consequence of the
application of this highest idea to the whole of existence, the latter
must be viewed as a teleological system which is directed towards a final
purpose. The content of this ultimate purpose, however, is man as subject
of morality and as a spiritually active moral being (Ibid, p. 587).
Therefore spiritual activity — which in the earlier critiques
confronted nature as the thing in itself — here becomes the substance
and ultimate purpose of all natural evolution. Nature (the entire
phenomenal world) is a system of last causes which in the last instance
are all aimed at the creation of man as an ethically spiritually-active
being. This system of last causes however — with ethical-spiritual
activity
as the substance and ultimate purpose of evolution in Nature — is the
keystone of the entire critical structure, also from a speculative point
of view; insofar as thereby all other ideas of God and immortality (which
as mere regulative ideas in the
Critique of Reason
were without ground and support) obtain objective reality through
spiritual activity and the ethical ultimate purpose
(C.Pr.R.,
Preface; C.I. p. 607).
Thus the last word Kant spoke as a critical philosopher would run as
follows: in God (the super-sensible substratum of Nature) we have the
binding together of the mechanical and teleological world views, and the
unifying point of nature and spiritual activity, and the principle of a
conclusive ethical world conception. Ethico-theology is the reasonable
conclusion of the whole critical undertaking
(C.I.,
p. 591–593). One would deceive oneself however if one believed that
Kant was capable of giving these sentences a strictly scientific and
uniformly executed foundation. What we mentioned in general at the
beginning of this examination
of the ethical investigation of our philosopher applies to an even greater
extent to the conclusion of it in the teleological and ethico-theological
consecration of existence. Kant not only was unable to free himself
from his old superstition that we bring general concepts into the world
of sense perception (and accordingly he also pronounced the teleological
principle to be a merely subjective, regulative and heuristic axiom
of which one can't see how the phenomena are then supposed. to correspond
to it), he also retained the incompatible ideas that we can't say anything
about the supersensible substratum of Nature, except that it's the being
in itself, of which we know only the outer appearance
(C.I.,
p. 581), whereas elsewhere he thinks it very important that the idea
of spiritual activity makes the objective reality of God possible and
expands our reason beyond those limits within which every (theoretical)
concept of Nature would have to remain hopelessly imprisoned
(C.Pr.R.,
p. 291;
C.I.,
p. 607). Finally — instead
of (as a philosopher) extending the rights of reason to all things
(without exception) which might be given in any way, be it as a component
of our ethical-practical world conception, be it finally as the very
principle of our knowledge — he took his last refuge in faith,
which — without insight into the dialectical mediation between
nature and spiritual activity, thing and phenomenon — resolves
(and makes into a permanent fundamental principle)
to accept as true the conditions of the highest ultimate moral purpose
(C.I.,
p. 607). We get what for philosophy and criticism is
a strange spectacle: reason gives itself up, diminishes its rights, and
cancels knowledge — to make room for faith
(Preface to 2nd edition of
C.Pu.R.,
p. 10), and therewith threatens to shake the whole
scientific work to its foundations — especially the critical
establishment of the concept of spiritual activity and of an ethical
world conception.
In spite
of all this — as long as human reason exists it will remain to Kant's
undying and imperishable credit that as a critical philosopher he exposed
the one-sidedness of the philosophical standpoint which arose before
him in the area of pure and practical reason and that he clearly and
unequivocally and for the first time set philosophy its true task: to
make a conclusive world conception from the point of view of an ethical
teleology. Kant's philosophy didn't enter the world as subjectivism,
empiricism, scepticism, illusionism, positivism, or pessimism, but as
ethicism, and his just for this reason truly critical and truly speculative
followers took it up into their philosophical thinking and developed
it further. Only when modern thinking has returned from all these false
side cruises (which all sail under the proud flag of criticism) to Kant,
the father of an absolute, ethical world view — and neither ignores,
ridicules or bemoans the development of this ethical world view in Fichte,
Schelling and Hegel, but understands it and takes it up into its inner
being and life — only then will a new epoch begin for philosophy, and
the content and task of this new epoch will be the old problem: to gather
together the rays scattered by the proponents of our classical German
ethical idealism and to unite them with a newly creative impulse into
a more unified and more satisfying world picture.
* * * * *
Notes:
1. Philosophische Monatshefte, Vol. 18
(G. Weiss), 1882
2. Great Books of the Western World, Kant,
(R.M. Hutchins, 1952)
|