LECTURE XII Dornach, May 1, 1921
Yesterday I
tried to outline the various preparations of different
nations for the significant point in humanity's development
in the middle of the nineteenth century that then, in a
sense, flowed from that time on into our present age. All
this can be illustrated through descriptions of the
connections between external phenomena and the inner
spiritual course of development. Today, we shall bring
together several facts that can throw some light on the
actual underlying history of the nineteenth century. After
all, it is true that the middle of that century is the point
when intellectual activity completely turned into a function,
an occupation, of the human physical body. Whereas this
activity of the intellect was a manifestation of the etheric
body during the whole preceding age; from the eighth century
B.C.
until the fifteenth century
A.D.,
it has increasingly
become an activity of the physical body since that time. This
process reached a culmination in the middle of the nineteenth
century. Along with this, the human being has in fact become
more spiritual than was previously the case.
The insights
into the spiritual world that had come about earlier and had
diminished since the beginning of modern times were derived,
after all, from the more intensive union of the physical body
with the etheric body. Simply because they were now in a
position to carry out something completely nonphysical with
their physical body, namely, intellectual activity, human
beings thus became completely spiritual beings in regard to
their activity. But as I already pointed out yesterday, they
denied this spirituality. People related what they grasped
mentally only to the physical world. And as I attempted to
characterize it yesterday, the different nations were
prepared in different ways for this moment in the development
of modern civilization.
From this
earlier characterization, the fundamental difference between
the soul condition of the Roman-Latin segment of Europe's
population and that of the Anglo-Saxon part will have become
clear. A radical difference does indeed exist in regard to
the inner soul constitution. This radical difference can best
be characterized if certain spiritual streams that have run
their course in humanity's evolution since ancient times and
have been recognized long ago are juxtaposed to the contrast
between France, Spain, Italy, and the inhabitants of the
British Isles and their American descendants. This can be
characterized in the following way. Everything that was part
of the Ahura-Mazdao cult in the ancient Persian culture,
mankind's looking up to the light, encountered in a
diminished form in the Egypto-Chaldean civilizations and, even
more diminished, in Greek culture, finally became abstract in
the Roman culture. All this left residual traces in what has
been preserved throughout the Middle Ages and the modern era
in the Romance segment of the European population. The last
offshoot of the Ormuzd or Ahura-Mazdao culture has remained
behind, as it were, whereas, on the other hand, the stream
that was considered the ahrimanic one in the ancient Persian
world view emerges as modern culture. Indeed, like Ormuzd and
Ahriman, these two cultures confront each other in recent
times. We find poured into this Ormuzd stream everything that
comes from the Roman Church. The forms Christianity assumed
by enveloping itself with the Roman-juristic forms of
government, by turning into the papal church of Rome, are the
last offshoots. We have indicated much else from which these
forms originated, but together with all these things they are
the last offshoots of the Ormuzd cult. These last traces can
still be detected in the offering of the Mass and all that is
present in it. A proper understanding of what lies at the
basis of these traces will be attained only if less value is
placed on insignificant aspects as compared to the great
streams of humanity, only if in studying these matters the
true value is sought in the forms of thought and feeling that
hold sway.
In regard to
external civilization, modern impulses came to expression in
a tumultuous way in the French Revolution at the end of the
eighteenth century. As I indicated yesterday, there lived in
it though in abstractions, the appeal addressed to the
individual, the conscious human being. We might actually say,
like a counterblow against what continued to survive in
Romanism, these abstractions of freedom, equality, and
brotherhood came into being out of the world of ideas. We
must distinguish between what found its way into the Roman
forms of thought and feeling out of ancient spiritual
streams, and the element that originated from human nature.
After all, we must always distinguish the essence of a single
nationality from the ongoing stream of humanity in general.
We shall see how a light that clearly points to the
characteristic moment in humanity's evolution in that century
also takes shape precisely in the French civilization later
on in the nineteenth century. But the national element in the
French, Spanish, and Italian cultures contains in itself the
continuation of the Ormuzd element in those times in which
this element — naturally transformed through the
Catholicity of Christianity — appears as a shadow of an
ancient civilization. Therefore, we see that despite all
aspirations towards freedom Romanism became and has remained
the bearer of what the Roman Church in its world dominion
represents.
You really do
not understand much of the course of European development, if
you do not clearly realize in what sense Roman
ecclesiasticism continues to live in Romanism to this day.
Indeed even the thought forms employed in the struggle
against the institutions of the Church are in turn themselves
derived from this Roman Catholic thinking. Thus, we have to
distinguish between the general stream of humanity's
evolution, which has assumed abstract character and flows
through the French Revolution, and the particular national,
the Roman-Latin stream, which is actually completely infected
with Roman Catholicity.
Out of this
stream of Roman Catholicity, a remarkable phenomenon arises
in the beginning of the nineteenth century. This phenomenon
and its significance for the development in Europe is given
far too little attention. Most people who spend their lives
being asleep to the phenomena of civilization know nothing of
what has been living in the depths of European culture since
the beginning of the nineteenth century and is still fully
grounded in Roman Catholicity. All this is concentrated, I
should say, in the first third of the nineteenth century in
the activities of a certain personality, namely, de Maistre.
[Note 1]
De Maistre is
actually the representative of the Catholicity borne by the
waves of Romanism, Catholicity that has the aspiration to
lead the whole of Europe back into its bosom. With de
Maistre, a personality of the greatest imaginable genius, of
compelling spirituality but Roman Catholic through and
through, appears on the scene.
Let us now
give some consideration to something that is completely
unfamiliar to those who think along Protestant lines, yet is
present in a relatively large number of people in Europe. It
is not commonly known that a spiritual stream does in fact
exist that is quite unknown to what has otherwise developed
since the beginning of the fifteenth century, but that is
itself well-acquainted with the effects of this new mentality
of the fifth post-Atlantean epoch.
Let us try to
characterize the world view in the minds of those for whom de
Maistre was a brilliant representative in the first third of
the nineteenth century. He himself has long since died, but
the spirit that inspired him lives on in a relatively large
number of people in Europe. Our present is the time in which
it is coming to life again, assuming new forms and seeking to
gain larger and larger dimensions. We shall characterize the
world view at its roots in a few sentences. This view holds
that since the beginning of the fifteenth century the course
of human life on earth is going downhill. Since that time,
only dissipation, godlessness, and vapidity have proliferated
in European civilization; the mere intellect focusing on
usefulness has gripped humanity. Truth, on the other hand,
which is identical with the spirituality of the world,
expresses something different since time immemorial. The
problem is that modern man has forgotten this ancient, sacred
truth. This primordial, sacred truth implies that man is a
fallen creature. The human being has cause to appeal to his
conscience and remorse in his soul so that he can lift
himself up, so that his soul will not fall prey to
materiality. But inasmuch as European humanity utilizes
materiality since the middle of the fifteenth century, the
European civilization is falling into ruin and with it the
whole of mankind.
That is the
world view whose main exponent is de Maistre. According to
this view all of humanity falls into two categories, one
representing the kingdom of God, the other representing the
kingdom of this world. The followers of this view look upon
the earth's population and distinguish those who they say
belong to the kingdom of God. They are the ones who still
believe in the ancient truths, who, in fact, have vanished in
their true form since the beginning of the fifteenth century.
Their noblest aftereffects can still be detected in the views
of Augustine,
[Note 2]
who also differentiates between human beings who are predestined
to salvation and those predestined to damnation. The adherents
of de Maistre claim that when one encounters a person in this
world, he either belongs to the kingdom of God, or to the
kingdom of this world. It only appears as though human beings
were all mixed together. In the eyes of the spiritual world
they are strictly separated from one another, and they can be
distinguished from one another. In antiquity, those who
belonged to the kingdom of the world, worshiped superstition,
that is, they fashioned for themselves false images of the
deity; since the beginning of the fifteenth century, they
cling to unbelief. That is what de Maistre and his followers
say. They know very well what the majority of the European
population has slept through, namely, the new age that has in
fact dawned since the beginning of the fifteenth century.
They indicate this point in time; they indicate it as that
moment in time when humanity forgot the source, the actual
source of divine truth. The put it like this: Through sole
use of the shadowy intellect, human beings found themselves
in a position where the connecting link between them and the
source of eternal truth was severed. Since that time,
Providence no longer extends mercy to mankind, only justice,
and this justice will hold sway on the day of Judgment.
If one
relates something like this, it is like telling people a
fairy tale; nevertheless, there are those in Europe who cling
to this view that since the beginning of the fifteenth
century divine world rule has assumed a quite different
position in regard to earth humanity. They cling to this
tenet just as modern scientists adhere to the law of gravity
or something like that. Despite the fact that the existence
of this view of life is of fundamental significance
particularly for the present, people today do not wish to pay
any heed to something like this. De Maistre sees the most
pronounced defection from ancient truth in the French
Revolution. He does not view it in the way we considered it,
namely, as the arising in abstract form of what is supposed
to direct human beings to the consciousness soul. Instead, he
views this Revolution as the fall into unbelief, the worst
thing that could have happened to modern humanity. The French
Revolution in particular signifies to him that the seal has
now been set on the fact that the divine world power no
longer has any obligation to extend mercy in any form on the
human being but merely justice, which will be sure to prevail
on the Day of Judgment. It is assumed in these circles that
those who will fall prey to the powers of doom are already
predestined, and also already preordained are those who are
the children of the Kingdom of God, who are destined to save
themselves because they still cling to ancient wisdom that
enjoyed its special bloom in the fourth century
A.D.
Such an
impulse pervades the text Observations About France de
Maistre wrote in 1796 when he still lived in Piermont.
Already then he reproached France, the France of the
Revolution, for its long list of sins. Already then, he
referred to the foundations of Romanism that still retain
what has come down from ancient times. This sentiment is
expressed even more strongly in de Maistre's later writings,
and the latter are connected with the whole mission in world
history de Maistre ascribed to himself.
[Note 3]
After all, he
chose Petersburg as the setting for his activity; his later
writings proceeded from there. De Maistre had the grandiose
idea to tie in with Russianism, particularly with the element
that had found its way since ancient times from Asia into the
Orthodox Catholic, Russian religion. From there, he wished to
create a connection to Romanism. He tried to bring about the
great fusion between the element living in the Oriental
manner of thinking in Russian culture, and the element coming
from Rome. The article he wrote in Petersburg in 1810,
”Essay Concerning the Creative Principle of Political
Constitutions,” is already imbued with this view. We
can discern from this text how de Maistre refers back to what
Christianity was in regard to its metaphysical view prior to
the scholastic age, what it was in the first centuries and
what was acceptable to Rome. De Maistre aimed for Roman, for
Catholic, Christianity as a real power, but in a certain
sense he even rejected what the Middle Ages had already
produced as an innovation on the basis of Aristotle's
philosophy. In a certain sense, de Maistre tried to exclude
Aristotle, for the latter was to him already the preparation
for what has appeared since the fifteenth century in the form
of the modern faculty of reason. Through human faculties
other than logic, de Maistre wanted to attain to a
relationship with spirituality.
The essay he
wrote in the second decade of the nineteenth century,
“Concerning the Pope,” moves particularly
strongly in the direction of this concept of life. We might
say that it is a text that exudes a classic spirit in its
composition, a spirit that belongs, in a manner of speaking,
to the finest times of French culture under Louis XIV. At the
same time, it had as penetrating an effect as any inspired
writing. The Pope is presented as the rightful ruler of
modern civilization, and it is significant that this is being
stated in Petersburg. The manner of presentation is such that
one is supposed to distinguish between the temporal, namely,
the corruption that has come into the world through a number
of Popes, the objectionable elements in regard to some of the
Popes, and the eternal principle of Roman Papacy. In a sense,
the Pope is represented as incarnation of the spirit of the
earth that is to rule over this earth. One is moved to say:
All the warmth that lives in this essay about the Pope is the
shining forth of Ormuzd's spirit that very nearly sees
Ahura-Mazdao himself incarnated in the Roman Pope and
therefore makes the demand that the Roman Catholic Church in
its fusion with all that found its way from the Orient into
Russia — for this is implied in the background —
will rule supreme, that it will sweep away all that the
intellectual culture has produced since the beginning of the
fifteenth century.
De Maistre
was really brilliantly effective in this direction. In 1816,
his translation of Plutarch was published.
[Note 4]
In it he tried to demonstrate the
sort of power that Christianity possessed; a power, so he
thought, that had insinuated itself as thought form into
Plutarch's dissertations although the latter was still a
pagan. Finally, the last work from de Maistre's pen, again
proceeding from Petersburg,
Twilight Hours in St. Petersburg,
was published in two volumes.
[Note 5]
First of all, everything I have
already characterized appears in them in an especially
pronounced form; in particular he depicts the radical
struggle of Roman Catholicism against what appears on the
British Isles as its counterpart.
If, on the
one hand, we see how Roman Catholicism crystallizes in all
this in a certain direction, if we note what is connected in
the form of Roman Catholicism with personalities like
Ignatius of Loyola,
[Note 6]
Alfonso di Liguori,
[Note 7]
Francis Xaverius,
[Note 8]
and others and
relate this to the brilliant figure of de Maistre; if we
observe everything that is present here, then, in a manner of
speaking, we see the obsolete, archaic light of Ormuzd. On
the other hand, we note what de Maistre sees arising on the
British Isles and what he then assails cuttingly with the
pungent acid of his penetrating mind. This struggle by de
Maistre against the true essence of the Anglo-Saxon spirit is
one of the most grandiose spiritual battles that has ever
taken place. In particular, he aims at the personality of the
philosopher Locke
[Note 9]
and sees in him the very incarnation of the spirit that leads
mankind into decline. He opposes Locke's philosophy brilliantly
to excess.
We need only
recall the significance of this philosophy. In the
background, on the one hand, we must note the Roman
principles of initiation that express themselves like a
continuing Ormuzd worship. We must be aware of everything
that flowed into this from somebody like Ignatius of Loyola,
Bossuet,
[Note 10]
and in such grand
manner from de Maistre himself. On the other hand, in
contrast to everything that has its center in Roman
Catholicism in Rome itself, yet is based on initiation and, I
might say, is certainly the newest phase of the Ormuzd
initiation, we have to observe all the secret societies that
spread from Scotland down through England and of which
English philosophy and politics are an expression. From a
certain, different viewpoint, I have described that on
another occasion. De Maistre is just as well informed about
what makes itself felt out of an ahrimanic initiation
principle as he is knowledgeable about what he is trying to
bring to bear as the Ormuzd initiation in the new form for
European civilization. De Maistre knows how to evaluate all
these things; he is intelligent enough to recognize them
esoterically, inasmuch as he attacks the philosopher Locke
who in a sense is an offspring, an outward, exoteric
offspring, of this other, ahrimanic initiation. He is
attacking an important personality, the one who made his
appearance with the epochal book
Concerning Human Reason,
which then greatly influenced French thinking.
Subsequently, Locke was indeed revered by Voltaire.
[Note 11]
His influence was such that Madam de Sevigne
[Note 12]
remarked concerning an Italian writer who made Locke palatable
in a literary sense for Italy, that the latter would have liked
to consume Locke's rhetorical embellishments in every bowl of
boullion.
Now de
Maistre took a close look at Locke and said: It is impossible
that Voltaire, for example, and other Frenchmen could have
even read this Locke! In his book
Twilight Hours in St. Petersburg
de Maistre discusses in detail how writers
actually gain world fame. He demonstrates that it is quite
possible that Voltaire had never read Locke; he really could
not have read him, otherwise he would have been smart enough
not to defend Locke as he did.
Even though
de Maistre sees a veritable devil in Voltaire, he still does
him justice by saying this of him. And in order to
substantiate this, he offers long essays on how individuals
like Locke are written and spoken about in the world,
individuals who are viewed as great men. This is
notwithstanding the fact that in reality people are not
concerned with gaining firsthand knowledge about them, but
instead familiarize themselves with such individuals by means
of secondary sources. It is as if humanity were imprisoned in
error — this is how Locke affects these people. The
whole modern way of thinking that, according to de Maistre's
view, then led to the catastrophe of the French Revolution
actually proceeds from Locke; in other words Locke is the
exponent, the symptom, the historical symptom for this. From
the point from which Locke proceeded, this way of thinking
dominates the world. De Maistre scrutinizes Locke, and he
says that there were few writers who had such an absolute
lack of a sense of style as did Locke, and he demonstrates
this in detail. He tries to prove in every instance that
Locke's statements are so trivial, so matter of fact, that
one need not reckon with them at all, that it is quite
unnecessary to trouble one's thoughts with them. He states
that Voltaire said Locke always clearly defined everything,
but, asks de Maistre, what are these definitions by Locke?
Nothing but truisms, “nonsensical tautologies,”
to use a modern term, and ridiculous. According to him, all
of Locke's pen pushing is supposedly a joke without style,
without brilliance, full of tautologies and platitudes.
This is how
de Maistre characterized something that became most valuable
for modern mankind, namely, that people today see greatness
in platitude, in popular style, in the lack of genius and
style, in what can be found in the streets but passes itself
off as philosophy.
Yet, de
Maistre is actually a person who in all instances pays
attention to the deeper spiritual principles, to the
spiritually essential. It is most difficult for matters such
as these encountered here to be made comprehensible to a
person today. For the way a personality like de Maistre
thinks is really quite foreign to present day human beings
who are accustomed to the shadowy intellect. De Maistre not
only observes the individual person; he sees the spiritual
element working through that individual. What Locke wrote
must be characterized in de Maistre's sense in the way I have
just described it. However, de Maistre expresses this with
extraordinary brilliance and geniality. At the same time, he
says: If, in turn, I consider Locke as a person he was indeed
a quite decent fellow; one can have nothing against him as a
person. He is the corrupter of Western European humanity, but
he is a decent person. If he would be born again today and
would have to watch how human beings make use of this
triviality that he himself recognized as such after death, he
would cry bitter tears over the fact that people have fallen
for his platitudes in this manner.
All this is
expressed by de Maistre with tremendous forced and plausible
emphasis. He is imbued with the impulse thus to annihilate
what appears to him as the actual adversary of Roman
Catholicism and what, according to his view, thrives
especially on the other side of the Channel. I would like to
read to you one passage verbatim from the
“Petersburg Twilight Conversations,”
where he speaks of the —
to his view wretched — effect of Locke on politics:
“These dreadful seeds” — so he says —
“perhaps would not have come to fruition under the ice
of his style; animated in the hot mud of Paris, they have
produced the monster of the Revolution that has engulfed
Europe.”
After having
uttered such words against the spirit working through Locke,
he again turns to Locke as a person. This is something that
is so difficult to impress on people of our age who
constantly confuse the external personality with the
spiritual principle that expresses itself through that human
being and see it as a unit. De Maistre always distinguishes
what reveals itself as actual spirituality from the external
human being. Now he turns again to the outward personality
and says: He is actually a man who had any number of virtues,
but he was gifted with them about as well as was that master
of dance who, according to Swift,
[Note 13]
was so accomplished in all the
skills of dance and had only one fault — he limped.
Thus, says de Maistre, Locke was gifted with all virtues.
Yet, de Maistre truly sees him as an incarnation of the evil
principle — this is not my figure of speech, de Maistre
himself uses this expression — that speaks through
Locke and holds sway supersensibly since the beginning of the
fifteenth century. One really gains some respect for the
penetrating spirituality that imbued de Maistre. One must
also be aware, however, that there really exist people who
are gaining influence today and are on the verge now of
winning back their influence over European civilization, who
are definitely inspired by that spirituality that de Maistre
represented on the highest level.
De Maistre
still retained something of the more ancient, instinctive
insights into the relationship between world and man. This is
particularly evident from his discourse about the Sacrifice
Offering and the ritual of the Sacrifice. He had somewhat of
an awareness of the fact that what is linked to the physical
body in regard to the consciousness soul must make itself
felt independently in the human being and that it is embodied
in the blood. Basically, it was de Maistre's view that the
divine element had only been present in human evolution up to
the fourth Christian century. He did not wish to acknowledge
the Christ Who works on continuously. Above all, he tried to
extinguish everything existing since the fifteenth century.
He longed to return to ancient times. Thus, he acquired his
particular view of the Christ, a view that possessed
something of the ancient Yahweh, indeed of the old pagan
gods, for he really went back to the cult of Ormuzd. And he
gathered from this viewpoint that the divine element can only
be sought far beyond the human consciousness soul, hence,
beyond the blood. Based on such profound depths of his world
view de Maistre expressed the thought that the gods —
namely the gods of whom he spoke — have a certain
distaste for the blood, and in the first place have to be
appeased by the blood sacrifice. The blood has to offer
itself up in sacrifice.
[Note 14]
It goes
without saying that this is something the supremely
enlightened modern human being laughs at. Yet it is something
that has passed on from de Maistre to those who are his
followers and who represent a segment of humanity that must
be taken seriously, but who are also intimately connected
with everything proceeding today from Roman ecclesiasticism.
We must not forget that in de Maistre we confront the finest
and most brilliant representative of what infused France from
Romanism and what indeed has come to expression in French
culture, I would say, in an ingenious but folk-oriented form.
It is this that lives in French culture and has constantly
brought it about that clericalism played a significant role
in everything motivating French politics throughout the whole
nineteenth century.
In France,
the abstract impulses of freedom, equality, and brotherhood
clashed with what existed there as Roman Catholicism. Actually,
we must vividly feel what imbued a person such as Gambetta
[Note 15]
when, at a decisive
moment, the deep sigh escaped from him:
“Le clericalisme, voila l'ennemi!”
(“Clericalism, that is the enemy!”).
He sensed this clericalism that pulsed up from everything in
the art of social experimentation during the first half of
the nineteenth century. It lived in Napoleon III; it was
something even the Commune
[Note 16]
had to struggle against. It was an element that survived into
later times, permeating the Boulangism
[Note 17]
of the 1880's and the conflicts
around the personality of Dreyfus;
[Note 18]
it is something that is alive even
today.
An element is
present in France that stands in an inner, spiritual, and
absolutely radical difference to all that exists on the other
side of the Channel in Great Britain and is basically
embodied in the elements that remained behind from something
else, from the various Masonic orders and lodges. Whereas, on
the one hand, we are dealing with initiated Roman
Catholicism, on the other hand we encounter the movements of
secret societies, which I have already characterized here
from another viewpoint and which represent the ahrimanic
stream. There is a tremendous difference in the way the
modern question of one person's individual status is
expressed, say, in the elections to Parliament in France, or
over in Great Britain. In France, everything proceeds from a
certain theory, from certain ideologies. In England,
everything emerges directly from the practical relationships
of commercial and industrial life and collides, as I pointed
out yesterday, with the ancient patriarchal conditions that
prevailed particularly in the landowners' lifestyle. Just
look at the way things take place in France. You find
everywhere what you might call spiritual battles. There are
struggles for freedom, for equality and brotherhood; people
fight for the separation of school and church. People
struggle to push the church back. But it is not possible to
do so, for the church dwells in the depths of the soul's
existence. Everything runs its course, in a manner of
speaking, in the domain of certain dialectics, of certain
arguments.
Over in
England, these matters run their course as questions of
power. There, we find a certain spiritual movement that is
typical of the Anglo-Saxon people. I have often pointed out
that as the middle of the nineteenth century approached,
certain people came to the conclusion that things could not
be allowed to go on in the same way any longer; human beings
had to be made aware of the fact that a spiritual world does
exist. The merely shadowlike intellect did not suffice. Yet
people could not make up their minds to bring this
inclination towards the spirit to the attention of the world
in a manner other than through something that is
“super-materialistic,” namely, through spiritism.
This spiritism, which in turn has a greater impact than one
would think, has its origins there. Spiritism, out to grasp
the spirit externally, so to speak, just as one grasps
matter, is therefore super-materialistic, is more
materialistic than materialism itself. Locke lives on, so to
say, in this super-materialism. And this element that in a
sense, dwells in the inner sphere of the modern cultural
development, expresses itself outwardly. It is certainly
again and again the same phenomenon.
We encounter
a tendency toward that spiritual stream de Maistre opposes so
radically in the 1840's across the Channel: The tendency to
comprehend everything by means of material entities. Locke
basically referred to the intellect in such a manner that he
deprived the intellect of its spiritual nature. He made use
of the most spiritual element in the human being in order to
deny the spirituality in the human being, indeed, in order to
direct human beings only to matter. Similarly people in the
nineteenth century referred to the spirit and tried to
demonstrate it through all sorts of material manifestations.
The intention was to make the spirit comprehensible to human
beings through materialism. The element, however, that imbued
the initiates of the various fraternities then passed over
into the external social and political conditions.
One is
inclined to say: By fighting for the abolition of the grain
tariff in 1846 and succeeding in that endeavor, the cotton
merchant Cobden and the Quaker Bright
[Note 19]
were the outward agents of the inner
spiritual stream in the political life in the same way as the
two most inept individuals who ever existed in politics,
Asquith and Grey in the year 1914.
[Note 20]
Certainly, Cobden and Bright were
not as blind as Asquith and Grey, but basically it is the
same symptom, presented to the world in outward phenomena
such as the abolition of the grain tariff in 1846 when
industry was victorious over the ancient patriarchal system,
only on a new stage. Yesterday, I listed the other stages
preceding this one. Then we can observe, so to speak, stage
following upon stage. We see the workers organizing
themselves. We note that the Whigs increasingly become the
party concerned with industry, that the Tories turn into the
party of the landowners, of the old patriarchal system. But
we also see that this ancient patriarchal element could no
longer resist the abrupt clash with modern technology —
I characterized the manner of that yesterday — and
that, all at once, modern industrialism pushed its way in.
Thus, centuries, indeed millennia, were skipped, and
England's mental condition that dated back to pre-Christian
eras and existed well into the nineteenth century simply
merged with what has developed in recent times.
Then we see
the right to vote increasingly extended, the Tories calling
for the support of a man, who only a short while ago
certainly would not have been counted among them, Disraeli,
Lord Beaconsfield, who was of Jewish extraction, an
“outsider.”
[Note 21]
We watch the Upper House finally becoming a shadow and the year
1914 approaching in which a quite new England emerges. Only
future historiography will be able to evaluate this emergence
of the new England correctly.
You see, this
is the course of the major events in the development of the
nineteenth century. We see the various moments flashing up,
indicating how significant a point in humanity's evolution
has actually appeared. Only the most enlightened minds,
however, can discern the light flashes that are the most
important. I have frequently called attention to a phenomenon
that is highly significant for the comprehension of the
development in the nineteenth century. I have called
attention to the moment in Goethe's house in Weimar when,
having heard of the July revolution in France, Eckermann
appeared before Goethe and Goethe said to him: “In
Paris, unheard-of things have occurred, everything is in
flames!” Naturally, Eckermann believed that Goethe was
referring to the July revolution. That was of no interest at
all to Goethe; instead, he said: “I don't mean that;
that is not what interests me. Rather, in the academy in
Paris, great controversy between Cuvier and Geoffroy de
Saint-Hilaire has broken out concerning whether the
individual types of animals are independent or whether the
one type passes over into the next.” Cuvier claimed the
first, namely, that one is dealing with firm, rigid types
that cannot evolve into other types. Geoffroy held that one
has to view a type as being changeable, that one type passes
over into the next.
[Note 22]
For Goethe, this was the major world event of modern times!
In fact, this
was true. Goethe, therefore, had a profound, tremendously
alive sensitivity. For what did Geoffroy de Saint-Hilaire
argue against Cuvier? The former sensed that when human
beings look into their inner being, they can animate this
shadowy intellect, that it is not merely logic, which is
passively concerned with the external world, but that this
logic can discover something like living truth about the
things in this world within itself. In what imbued Geoffroy
de Saint-Hilaire, Goethe sensed the assertion of the living
intellect, something that arose, I might say, in the occult
development of modern humanity and reached its culmination in
the middle of the nineteenth century. Goethe really sensed
something of great significance.
Cuvier, the
great scholarly scientist, claimed that one had to be able to
differentiate between the individual species and had to place
them side by side. He stated that it was impossible to
transform one type into the next, least of all, for example,
the bird species into that of the mammals, and so on.
Geoffroy de Saint-Hilaire, on the other hand, claimed that it
was possible to do so.
What sort of
confrontation was that? Ordinary truth and sublime error? Oh
no, that is not the case. With ordinary, abstract logic, with
the shadow-intellect, one can just as easily prove the
correctness of what Cuvier claims as of what Geoffroy de
Saint-Hilaire has stated. On the basis of ordinary reason,
which still prevails in our science today, this question
cannot be resolved. This is why it has come up again and
again; this is why we see Geoffroy de Saint-Hilaire confront
Cuvier in Paris in 1830 and in a different manner
Weissmann
[Note 23]
and others confront Haeckel.
[Note 24]
These questions cannot be determined by way of this external
science. For here, the element that has turned into the
shadowlike intellect since the beginning of the fifteenth
century, something that de Maistre detests so much, is really
aiming at abolishing spirituality itself.
De Maistre
pointed to Rome, even to the fact that the Pope —
except for the temporal, passing papal personalities —
sits in Rome as the incarnation of what is destined to rule
over modern civilization. The culmination point of these
discourses by de Maistre was reached in the year 1870, when
the dogma of the Pope's infallibility was proclaimed. By way
of the outmoded Ormuzd worship, the element that should be
sought in spiritual heights was brought down into the person
of the Roman Pope. What ought to be viewed as spirituality
became temporalized matter; the church was turned into the
secular state. This was subsequent to the fact that the
church had already for a long time been successful in fitting
the secular states into the form it had assumed itself when
it had turned into the state religion under Constantine.
Therefore, in
Romanism, we have on the one hand something that turns into
the modern state inasmuch as the legal principle itself
rebels and brings about its own polarity, so to speak, in the
French Revolution; on the other hand, we have the outdated
Ormuzd worship. Then we confront the element arising from the
economic sphere, for all the measures that are taken on the
other side of the English Channel originate from that sphere.
In de Maistre we encounter the last great personality who
tries to imprint spirituality into the judicial form of the
state, who tries to carry the spirit into earthly
materiality. This is what anthroposophically oriented
spiritual science has to oppose. It wishes to establish
super-sensible spirituality. It tries to add to the prolonged
Ormuzd worship, to the ahrimanic worship, something that will
bring about a balance, it wishes to make the spirit itself
the ruler of the earth.
This cannot
be accomplished other than in the following manner. If, on
the one hand, the earthly element is imprinted into the
structure of political laws and, on the other hand, into the
economic form, this spiritual life, in turn, is established
in such a way that it does not institute the belief in a god
who has become secular but rather inaugurates the reign of
the spirit itself that flows in with each new human being
incarnating on earth. This is the free spiritual life that
wishes to take hold of the spirit that stands above all that
is earthly. Once again, the intention is t bring to bear what
one might call the effusion of the Spirit.
In
A.D. 869,
during the general ecumenical council, the view of the spirit
was toned down in order to prevent human beings from arriving
at the acknowledgment of the spirit that rules the earth from
heaven, at the beginning of the fifteenth century, in order
to make possible the appearance of a man such as de Maistre
as late as the nineteenth century.
This is what
is important: Rather than appealing to the spirit believed to
be incarnated in an earthly sense, a Christ-being believed to
be living on in an earthly church, we must appeal to the
spiritual entity that is indeed connected with the earth, yet
must be recognized and viewed in the spirit. But since
everything human beings must attain in the earthly domain has
to be acquired within the social order, this cannot come
about in any other way but by acknowledging the free right of
the spirit descending with each new human life in order to
acquire the physical body, the spirit that can never become
sovereign in an earthly personality and dwells in a
super-sensible being.
The
establishment of the dogma of infallibility is a defection
from spirituality; the last point of what had been intended
with that council of 869 had been reached. We must return to
the acknowledgment, belief in, and recognition of the spirit.
This, however, can only come about if our social order is
permeated with the structure that makes possible the free
spiritual life alongside other things — the earth-bound
political and economic life.
This is how
the insight human beings must acquire today places itself
into the course of civilization. This is how it has to be
experienced within the latter. If we fail to do that, we
cannot arrive at the essence of what is actually trying to
come to expression in the
“Threefold Social Organism,”
of what tries to work for the salvation of a
civilization that otherwise must fall victim to decline in
the manner described by Spengler.
|