LECTURE XV Dornach, June 2, 1921
In the past
few weeks, I have repeatedly spoken of the great change that
took place in Western civilization during the fourth century
A.D.
When such a matter is discussed, one is obliged to point
out one thing again and again, that has already been the
subject of discussion here many times. Yet it is necessary to
focus on it time and again. I am referring to the
metamorphoses of human development, markedly differing from
each other on the soul level. When speaking of such a major
point in human evolution as the one in the fourth century,
one has to pay heed to the fact that the soul life of
humanity changed in a sense with one great leap.
This view is
not prevalent today. The prevailing opinion holds that the
human race has undergone a certain history. This history is
traced back to about the third or fourth millennium along the
lines of the most recent documented records. Then, going back
further, there is nothing for a long time; finally, one
arrives at animalistic-human conditions. But in regard to the
duration of the historical development, it is assumed that
human beings have in the main always thought and felt the way
they do today; at most, they formerly adhered to a somewhat
more childish stage of scientific pursuit. Finally, however,
human beings have struggled upward to the level of which we
say today that it is splendid how far we have come in the
comprehension of the world. To be sure, a reasonably unbiased
consideration of human life arrives at the opposite view. I
have had to indicate to you the presence of a mighty
transition in the fourth Christian century; I outlined the
other change in the whole human soul life at the beginning of
the fifteenth century. Finally, I described how a turning
point in human soul life occurred also during the nineteenth
century.
Today, we
shall consider one detail in this whole development. I would
like to place before you a personality who illustrates
particularly well that human beings in the relatively recent
past thought completely differently from the way we think
today. The personality, who has been mentioned also in
earlier lectures, is John Scotus Erigena,
[Note 1]
who lived in the ninth century
A.D.
at the court of Charles the Bald in France.
[Note 2]
Erigena, whose home was across the
Channel, who was born approximately in the year 815 and lived
well into the second half of the ninth century, is truly a
representative of the more intimate Christian mode of
thinking of the ninth century
A.D.
It is, however, a manner
of thinking that is still completely under the influence of
the first Christian centuries. John Scotus Erigena apparently
was intent on immersing himself in the prevalent scholarly
and theological culture of his time. In his age, scholarly
and theological knowledge were one and the same. And such
learning was most readily acquired across the British
Channel, particularly in the Irish institutions where
Christianity was cultivated in a certain esoteric manner. The
Franconian kings then had ways of attracting such
personalities to their courts. The Christian knowledge
permeating the Franconian kingdom, even spreading from there
further east into western Germany, was mainly influenced by
those who had been attracted from across the Channel by these
Franconian kings.
John Scotus
Erigena also immersed himself into the contents of the
writings by the Greek Church Fathers, studying also the texts
of a certain problematic nature within Western civilization,
namely, the texts by Dionysius the Areopagite.
[Note 3]
As you know, the latter is considered
by some to be a direct pupil of Paul. Yet, these texts only
surfaced in the sixth century, and many scholars therefore
refer to them as pseudo-Dionysian writings composed in the
sixth century by an unknown person, which were then
accredited to Paul's disciple.
People who
say that are ignorant of the way spiritual knowledge was
passed on in those early centuries. A school like the one in
which Paul himself taught in Athens possessed insights that
initially were taught only orally. Handed down from
generation to generation, they were finally written down
much, much later on. What was thus recorded at a later time,
was not necessarily anything less than genuine for that
reason; it could preserve to some extent the identity of
something that was centuries old. Furthermore, the great
value that we place on personality today was certainly not
attached to personality in those earlier ages. Perhaps we
will be able to touch upon a circumstance in this lecture
that must be discussed in connection with Erigena, namely,
why people did not place much value on personality in that
age.
There is no
doubt about one thing: The teachings recorded in the name of
Dionysius the Areopagite were considered especially worthy of
being written down in the sixth century. They were considered
the substance of what had been left from the early Christian
times, which were now in particular need of being recorded.
We should consider this fact as such to be significant. In
the times prior to the fourth century, people simply had more
confidence in memory working from generation to generation
than they had in later periods. In earlier ages, people were
not so eager to write everything down. They were aware,
however, that the time was approaching when it would become
increasingly necessary to write down things that earlier had
been passed on by word of mouth with great ease; for the
things that were then recorded in the writings of Dionysius
were of a subtle nature.
Now, what
John Scotus Erigena was able to study in these writings was
certainly apt to make an extraordinarily profound impression
on him. For the mode of thinking found in this Dionysius was
approximately as follows. With the concepts we from and the
perceptions we acquire, we human beings can comprehend the
physical sensory world. We can then draw our conclusions from
the facts and beings of this sensory world by means of
reasoning. We work our way upward, as it were, to a rational
content that is then no longer visually perceptible but is
experienced in ideas and concepts. Once we have developed our
concepts and thoughts from the sensory facts and beings, we
have the urge to move upward with them to the supersensory,
to the spiritual and divine.
Now,
Dionysius does not proceed by saying that we learn this or
that from the sensory things; he does not say that our
intellect acquires its concepts and then goes on to deduce a
deity, a spiritual world. No, Dionysius says, the concepts we
acquire from the things of the senses are all unsuitable to
express the deity. No matter how subtle the concepts we form
of sensory things, we simply cannot express what constitutes
divinity with the aid of these concepts. We must therefore
resort to negative concepts rather than positive ones. When
we encounter our fellowmen, for example, we speak of
personality. According to this Dionysian view, when we speak
of God, we should not speak of personality, for the concept
of personality is much too small and too lowly to designate
the deity. Rather we should speak of super-personality. When
referring to God, we should not even speak of being, of
existence. We say, a man is, an animal, a plant is.
We should not ascribe existence to God in the same sense as
we attribute existence to us, the animals, and the plants; to
Him, we ought to ascribe a super-existence. Thus, according
to Dionysius, we should try to rise from the sensory world to
certain concepts but then we should turn them upside down, as
it were, allowing them to pass over into the negative. We
should rise from the sense world to positive theology but
then turn upside down and establish negative theology. This
negative theology would actually be so sublime, so permeated
by God and divine thinking that it can only be expressed in
negative predicates, in negations of what human beings can
picture of the sensory world.
Dionysius the
Areopagite believed he could penetrate into the divine
spiritual world by leaving behind, so to speak, all that can
be encompassed by the intellect and thus finding the way into
a world transcending reason.
If we
consider Dionysius a disciple of Paul, then he lived from the
end of the first Christian century into the second one. This
means that he lived a few centuries prior to the decisive
fourth century
A.D.
He sensed what was approaching: The
culmination point of the development of human reason. With a
part of his being, Dionysius looked back into the days of
antiquity. As you know, prior to the eighth century
B.C.,
human beings did not speak of the intellect in the way they
did after the eighth century. Reason, or the rational soul
was not born until the eigth century
B.C.,
and from the birth
of the rational soul originated the Greek and Roman cultures.
These then reached their highest point of development in the
fourth century
A.D.
Prior to this eighth century
B.C.
people did not perceive the world through the intellect at all;
they perceived it directly, through contemplation. The early
Egyptian and Chaldean insights were attained through
contemplation; they were attained in the same manner in which
we acquire our external sensory insights, despite the fact
that these pre-Christian insights were spiritual insights.
The spirit was perceived just as we today perceive the
sensory world and as the Greeks already perceived the sensory
world. Therefore, in Dionysius the Areopagite, something like
a yearning held sway for a kind of perception lying beyond
human reason.
Now, in his
mind, Dionysius confronted the mighty Mystery of Golgotha. He
dwelled in the intellectual culture of his time. Anybody
studying the writings of Dionysius sees — regardless of
who Dionysius was — how immersed this man was in all
that the intellectual culture of his time had produced. He
was a well educated Greek but at the same time a man whose
whole personality was imbued with the magnitude of the
Mystery of Golgotha. He was a man who realized that
regardless of how much we strain our intellect, we cannot
comprehend the Mystery of Golgotha and what stands behind it.
We must transcend the intellect. We have to evolve from
positive theology to negative theology.
When John
Scotus Erigena read the writings of this Dionysius the
Areopagite, they made a profound impression on him even in
the ninth century. For what followed upon the fourth
Christian century had more of an Augustine character and
developed only slowly in the way I described in the earlier
lectures. The mind of such a person, particularly of one of
those who had trained themselves in the schools of wisdom
over in Ireland, still dwelled in the first Christian
centuries; he clung with all the fibers of his soul to what
is written in the texts of Dionysius the Areopagite. Yet, at
the same time, John Scotus Erigena also had the powerful urge
to establish by means of reason, by what the human being can
attain through his intellect, a kind of positive theology,
which, to him, was philosophy. He therefore diligently
studied the Greek Church Fathers in particular. We discover
in him a thorough knowledge, for example of Origen,
[Note 4]
who lived from the second to the third century
A.D.
When we study
Origen, we actually discover a world view completely
different from the Christian view, that is from what appeared
later as the Christian view. Origen definitely still holds
the opinion that one has to penetrate theology with
philosophy. He believes that it is only possible to examine
the human being and his nature only if he is considered as an
emanation of the deity, as having had his origin in God.
Then, however, man lowered himself increasingly; yet through
the Mystery of Golgotha, he has gained the possibility of
ascending once again to the deity in order once more to unite
with God. From God into the world and back to God —
this is how one could describe the path that Origen perceived
as his own. Basically, something like this also underlies the
Dionysian writings, and then was passed on to such
personalities as John Scotus Erigena. But there were many
others like him.
One could say
that it is a sort of historical miracle that posterity came
to know the writings of John Scotus Erigena at all. In
contrast to other texts of a similar nature from the first
centuries that have been completely lost, Erigena's writings
were preserved until the eleventh, twelfth, a few even until
the thirteenth century. At that time, they were declared
heretical by the Pope; the order was given to find and burn all
copies. Only much later, manuscripts from the eleventh and
thirteenth century were rediscovered in some obscure
monastery. In the fourteenth, fifteenth, sixteenth, and
seventeenth centuries, people knew nothing of John Scotus
Erigena. His writings had been burned like so many other
manuscripts
[Note 5]
of a similar content from that period. From Rome's point of view
the search was more successful in the case of other manuscripts:
all copies were fed to the flames. Yet, of Erigena's works, a
few copies remained.
Now,
considering the ninth century and also taking into account
that in John Scotus Erigena we have an expert in the wisdom
and insights of the first Christian centuries, we must
conclude the following. He is a characteristic representative
of what extended form an earlier age, from the time preceding
the fourth century, into later periods. One could say that in
these later times, all knowledge had ossified in the dead
Latin language. All the wisdom of the spiritual world that
had been alive earlier became ossified, dogmatized, rigid,
and intellectualized. Yet, in people like Erigena lived
something of the ancient aliveness of direct spiritual
knowledge that had existed in the first Christian centuries
and was utilized by the most enlightened minds to comprehend
the Mystery of Golgotha.
For a time,
this wisdom had to die out in order for the intellect of man
to be cultivated from the first third of the fifteenth
century until our era. While the intellect as such is a
spiritual achievement of the human being, initially it turned
only to the material realm. The ancient wealth of wisdom had
to die so that the intellect in its shadowy nature could be
born. If, instead of immersing ourselves in a scholarly,
pedantic manner into his writings, we do so with our whole
being, we will notice that through Scotus Erigena something
had spoken out of soul depths other than those from which
people spoke later on. There, the human being had still
spoken out of mental depths that subsequently could no longer
be reached by human soul life. Everything was more spiritual,
and if human beings spoke intellectually at all, they spoke
of matters in the spiritual realm.
It is
extremely important for one to scrutinize carefully what the
structure of Erigena's knowledge was like. In his mighty work
on the divisions of nature that has come down to posterity in
the manner I described, he divided what he had to say
concerning the world in four chapters. In the first, he
initially speaks of the uncreated and the created world
(see outline below). In the way Erigena
believed himself able to do it, the first chapter describes
God and the way He was prior to His approaching something
like the creation of the world.
Ancient
Legacy
3. post-Atlantean Age:
|
I. Uncreated and created
world: Theology
|
2. post-Atlantean Age:
|
II. Created and creating
world: Ideal World
|
1. post-Atlantean Age:
|
III. Created and noncreating
world: Pneumatology
Cosmology, Anthropology
|
Living Striving:
|
IV. Uncreated and noncreating world:
Soteriology, Eschatology
Materialistic Natural Science
|
The Human Being
Existence: Father
Wisdom: Son
Life: Holy Spirit
|
1. is as a mineral being.
2. lives and thrives as plant.
3. feels as animal
4. judges and draws conclusions as human being.
5. perceives as angel
6. intuits as archangel
|
John Scotus
Erigena clearly describes this in the way he learned through
the writings of Dionysius. He describes by means of
developing the most refined intellectual concepts. At the
same time, he is aware that with them he only reaches up to a
certain limit beyond which lies negative theology. He
therefore merely approaches the actual true being of the
spirit, of the divine. Among other topics, we find in this
chapter the beautiful discourse about the Trinity,
instructive even for our age. He states that when we view the
things around us, we initially discover existence as an
overall spiritual quality (see above).
Existence embraces everything. Now, we should not attribute
existence as possessed by things to God. Yet, looking upward
to existence transcending existence, we cannot but speak
summarily of the deity's existence.
Likewise, we
find that things in the world are illuminated and permeated
by wisdom. To God, we should not merely ascribe wisdom but
wisdom beyond wisdom. But when we proceed from things, we
arrive at the limit of wisdom-filled things. Now, there is
not only wisdom in all things. They live; there is life in
all things. Therefore, when Erigena calls to mind the world,
he says: I see existence, wisdom, life in the world. The
world appears to me in these aspects as an existing,
wisdom-filled, living world. To him, these are three veils,
so to speak, that the intellect fashions when it surveys all
things. One would have to see through these veils, then, to
see into the divine-spiritual realm. To begin with, Erigena
describes these veils: When I look upon existence, this
represents the Father to me; when I look upon wisdom, it
represents the Son to me; when I look upon life, it
represents the Holy Spirit in the universe.
As you can
see, John Scotus Erigena certainly proceeds from
philosophical concepts and then makes his way up to the
Christian Trinity. Inwardly, proceeding from the
comprehensible, he still experiences the path from there to
the so-called incomprehensible. Indeed, of this he is
convinced. Yet, from the way he speaks and presents his
insights we can see that he has learned from Dionysius.
Precisely when he arrives at existence, wisdom, and life,
which to him represent the Father, the Son, and the Holy
Spirit, he would really like to have these concepts dissolve
in a general spiritual element into which the human being
would then have to rise by transcending concepts. However, he
does not credit the human being with the faculty of arriving
at a state of mind that goes beyond the conceptual.
In this, John
Scotus Erigena was a product of the age that developed the
intellect. Indeed, if this age had understood itself
correctly, it would have had to admit that it could not enter
into the realm transcending the conceptual level.
The second
chapter then describes something like a second sphere of
world existence, the created and the creating world
(see above).
It is the world of the spiritual
beings where we find the angels, the archangels, the Archai,
and so on. This world of spiritual beings, mentioned already
in the writings of Dionysius the Areopagite. is creative
everywhere in the world. Yet this hierarchical world is
itself created; it is begun, hence created, by the highest
being and in turn is active creatively in all details of
existence surrounding us.
In the third
chapter, Erigena then describes as a third world the created
world that is noncreating. This is the world we perceive
around us with our senses. It is the world of animals,
plants, and minerals, the stars, and so on. In this chapter,
Erigena deals with almost everything we would designate as
cosmology, anthropology, and so forth, all that we would call
the realm of science.
In the fourth
chapter, Erigena deals with the world that has not been
created and does not create. This is again the deity, but the
way it will be when all creatures, particularly all human
beings, will have returned to it. It is the Godhead when it
will no longer be creating, when, in blissful tranquility
— this is how John Scotus Erigena imagines it — it
will have reabsorbed all the beings that have emerged from
it.
Now, in
surveying these four chapters, we find contained in them
something like a compendium of all traditional knowledge of
the schools of wisdom from which Scotus Erigena had come.
When we consider what he describes in the first chapter, we
deal with something that can be called theology in his sense,
the actual doctrine of the divine.
Considering
the second chapter, we find in it what he calls in terms of
our present-day language the ideal world. The ideal is
pictured, however, as existing. For he does not describe
abstract ideas but angels, archangels, and so forth. He
pictures the whole intelligible world, as it was called. Yet
it was unlike our modern intelligible world; instead it was a
world filled with living beings, with living, intelligible
entities.
As I said, in
the third chapter Erigena describes what we would term
science today, but he does so in a different way. Since the
days of Galileo and Copernicus, who, after all, lived later,
we no longer possess what was called cosmology or
anthropology in Scotus Erigena's age. Cosmology was still
described from the spiritual standpoint. It depicted how
spiritual beings direct and also inhabit the stars, how the
elements, fire, water, air, and earth are permeated by
spiritual beings. What was described as cosmology, was indeed
something different. The materialistic way of viewing things
that has arisen since the middle of the fifteenth century did
not yet exist in Erigena's time, and his form of anthropology
also differed completely from what we call anthropology in
our materialistic age.
Here, I can
point out something extraordinarily characteristic for what
anthropology is to John Scotus Erigena. He looks at the human
being and says: First, man bears existence within himself.
Hence, he is a mineral being, for he contains within himself
a mineral nature
(see outline above).
Secondly, man lives and thrives like a plant. Third, man
feels as does the animal. Fourth, man judges and draws
conclusions as man. Fifth, man perceives as an angel.
It goes
without saying that in our age this would be an unheard-of
statement! When John Scotus Erigena speaks of judgment and
conclusions, something that is done, for instance, in a legal
court where one pronounces judgment over somebody —
then, so he says, human beings do this as human beings. But
when they perceive, when they penetrate the world in
perception then human beings do not behave as human beings
but as angels! The reason for pointing this out is that I am
trying to show you that for that period anthropology was
something different from what it is for our present age. For
it is true that you could hardly hear anywhere, not even in a
theological seminar, that human beings perceive as angels.
Therefore, one is forced to conclude that our science no
longer resembles what Erigena describes in the third chapter.
It has turned into something different. If we wanted to call
Erigena's science by a word that is no longer applicable to
anything existing today, we would have to say that it was a
spiritual doctrine of the universe and man, pneumatology.
Now to the
fourth chapter: This contains, first of all, Erigena's
teaching of the Mystery of Golgotha and the doctrine
concerning what the human being has to expect in the future,
namely, entrance into the divine-spiritual world, hence, what
in modern usage would be called soteriology.
“Soter,” after all, means savior; the teaching of
the future is eschatology. We find that Erigena here deals
with the concepts of the Crucifixion and Resurrection, the
emanation of Divine Grace, man's path into the
divine-spiritual, world, and so on.
There is one
thing that truly holds our attention, if we study attentively
a work such as the De divisione naturae by John Scotus
Erigena about the divisions of nature. The world is
definitely discussed as something that is perceived in
spiritual qualities. He speaks of something spiritual as he
observes the world. But what is not contained in this work?
We have to pay attention, after all, to what is not included
in a universal science such as Erigena is trying to establish
there.
In John
Scotus Erigena's work, you discover as good as nothing of
what we call sociology today, social science, and things of
that kind. One is almost inclined to say it appears from the
way Erigena pictures human beings that he did not wish to
give mankind social sciences, no more so than any animal
species, say the lion, the tiger, or any bird species, would
come out with a sociology if it produced some sort of
science. For a lion would not talk about the way it ought to
live together with the other lions or how it ought to acquire
its food and so on; this is something that comes
instinctively. Just as little could we imagine a sociology of
sparrows. Surely sparrows could reveal any number of the most
interesting cosmic secrets from their viewpoint, but they
would never produce any teaching about economics, for
sparrows would consider this a subject that goes without
saying, something they do because their instinct tells them
to do it.
This is what
is remarkable: Because we discover as yet nothing like this
in Erigena's writings, we realize that he still viewed human
society as if it produced the social elements out of its
instincts. With his special kind of insight, he points to
what still lived in the human being in the form of instincts
and drives, namely, the impulses of social living. What he
describes transcends this social aspect. He describes how the
human being had emerged from the divine, and what sort of
beings exist beyond the sense world. Then, in a form of
pneumatology, he shows how the spirit pervades the sensory
world, and he presents the spiritual element that penetrated
into the world of the senses in his fourth chapter on
soteriology and eschatology. Nowhere is there a description,
however, of how human beings ought to live together. I should
say, everything is elevated above the sensory world. It was
generally a characteristic of this ancient science that
everything was elevated beyond the sense world.
Now, if we
contemplate writings such as John Scotus Erigena's teaching
in a spiritual scientific sense, we discover that he did not
think at all with the same organs humanity thinks with today.
We simply do not understand him if we try to understand him
with the thinking employed by mankind today. We understand
him only when, through spiritual science, we have acquired an
idea of how to think with the etheric body, the body that, as
a more refined body, underlies the coarse sensory
corporeality.
Thus Erigena
did not think with the brain but with the etheric body. In
him, we simply have a mind which did not yet think with the
brain. Everything he wrote down came into being as a result
of thinking with the etheric body. Fundamentally speaking, it
was only subsequent to his age that human beings began to
think with the physical body, and only since the beginning of
the fifteenth century did people think totally with the
physical body. It is normally not recognized that during this
period the human soul life has truly changed, and that if we
go back into the thirteenth, twelfth, and eleventh centuries,
we encounter a form of thinking that was not yet carried out
with the physical but with the etheric body. This thinking
with the etheric body was not supposed to extend into later
ages when, dialectically and scholastically, people discussed
rigid concepts. This former thinking with the etheric body,
which certainly was the form of thinking employed during the
first Christian centuries, was declared to be heretical. This
was the reason for burning Erigena's writings. Now, the
actual soul condition of a thinker in that age becomes
comprehensible.
Going back to
earlier times, we find a certain form of clairvoyance in all
people. Human beings did not think at all with their physical
body. In past ages, they thought with their etheric body and
carried on their soul life even with the astral body. There,
we should not speak of thinking at all, since the intellect
only originated in the eighth century
B.C.,
as I have pointed
out. However, certain remnants of this ancient clairvoyance
were retained, and it is particularly true of the most
outstanding minds that with the intellect, which had already
come into being, they tried to penetrate into the knowledge
that had been handed down through tradition from former ages.
People tried to comprehend what had been viewed in a
completely different manner in past times. They tried to
understand, but now had to have the support of abstract
concepts such as existence, wisdom, life. I would say that
these individuals still knew something of an earlier
spirit-permeated insight and at the same time felt quite at
home within the purely intellectual perception.
Later on,
when the intellectual perception had turned into a shadow,
this was not felt anymore. Earlier, however, people felt that
in past ages insights had existed that permeated human beings
in a living way out of spiritual worlds, it was not something
merely thought up. Erigena lived in such a divided state. He
was only capable of thinking, but when this thinking arrived
at perception, he sensed that there was something of the
ancient powers that had permeated the human being in the
ancient manner of perception. Erigena felt the angel, the
angelos, within himself. This is why he said that human
beings perceive as angels. It was a legacy from ancient
times, extending into his age of intellectual knowledge, that
made it possible for a mind like Scotus Erigena's to say that
man perceives like an angel. In the days of the Egyptian,
Chaldean, and the early ages of the Hebrew civilization,
nobody would have said anything else but: The angel perceives
within me; as a human being, I share in the knowledge of the
angel. The angel dwells within me, he cognizes, and I take
part in what he perceives.
This was true
of the era when reason did not yet exist. When the intellect
had appeared, it became necessary to penetrate this older
knowledge with reason. In Scotus Erigena, however, there
still existed an awareness of this state of permeation with
the angel nature.
Now, it is a
strange experience to become involved in this work of
Erigena's and to try and understand it completely. You
finally arrive at a feeling of having read something most
significant, something that still dwells very much in
spiritual regions and speaks of the world as something
spiritual. But then, in turn, the feeling arises that
everything is basically mixed up. You realize that with this
text you find yourself in the ninth century when the
intellect had already brought much confusion. And this is
truly the case. For if you read the first chapter, you are
dealing with theology. But it is a theology that is certainly
secondary even for John Scotus Erigena, a theology which
evidently points back to something greater and more direct. I
shall now speak as if all these matters were hypotheses, but
what I now develop as a hypothesis can be established by
spiritual science as a fact. A condition must once have
existed, and we look back on it, when as yet theology was not
addressed in such an intellectual manner but was considered
to be something one delved into in a living way. Without
doubt, it was that kind of theology the Egyptians spoke of,
those Egyptians of whom the Greeks — I mentioned it
above — report that Egyptian sages told them: You
Greeks are like children;
[Note 6]
you have no knowledge of the world's origin, we do possess this
sacred knowledge of the world's beginnings.
Obviously,
the Greeks were being referred to an ancient, living
theology. Thus, we have to say: During the time of the third
post-Atlantean period, which begins in the fourth millennium
and ends in the first millennium
B.C.
in the eighth pre-Christian century, approximately in the year
747 B.C.,
there existed a living theology. It now needed to be
penetrated by Erigena's intellect. It was obviously present
in a much more vital form to the personality who must be
recognized as Dionysius the Areopagite. Dionysius had a much
more intense feeling for this ancient theology. He felt that
it was something that existed but could no longer be
approached, that becomes negative as one tries to approach
it. Based on the intellect, so he thought, one can only
arrive at positive theology. Yet, with the term, negative
theology, he was really referring to an ancient theology that
had disappeared.
Again, when
we consider what appears in the second chapter as the ideal
world, we could believe that it is something modern. That,
however, is not the case, That ideal world actually is
identical with a true idea of what appears in the ancient
Persian epoch, just as I described it in my
Occult Science,
hence in the second post-Atlantean period.
Among Plato and the Platonists, this ancient Persian living
world of angels, the world of the Amshaspands, and so on, had
already paled into the world of ideals and ideas due to a
later development. Yet, what is actually contained in this
ideal world and is clearly discernible in Scotus Erigena goes
back to this second ancient Persian age.
What appears
in Erigena's book as pneumatology, as a kind of pantheism is
not vague and nebulous such as is frequently the case today,
but a pantheism that is alive and spiritual, though dimmed in
Erigena's writing. This pneumatology is the last remnant, the
very last vestige filtered out of the first post-Atlantean,
ancient Indian period.
And what
about the fourth chapter? Well, it contains Erigena's living
perception of the Mystery of Golgotha and the future of
humanity. We hardly speak of this anymore today. As an
ancient tradition, it is still mentioned by theologians, but
they know of it only in rigidified dogmas. They even deny
that man could attain such insight through living knowledge.
But it did originate from what was thus cultivated as
soteriology and eschatology. You see, the theology of former
times was handed over, as it were, to the councils; there, it
was frozen into dogmas and incorporated into Christology. It
was not to be touched anymore. It was viewed as impenetrable
to perception. It was removed, so to speak, from what was
carried out in schools by means of knowledge. As it was,
exoteric matters were already being preserved like nebulous
formations from ancient times. But at least the activities in
schools were to be linked with thoughts that emerged in the
age of thinking. They were to be connected, after all, with
the Mystery of Golgotha and the future of mankind. There, one
spoke of the Christ being's rule among human beings; one
spoke of a future day of judgment. The concepts that people
could come up with were used for that.
Thus, we see
that Scotus Erigena actually records the first three chapters
as though they had been handed down to him. Finally, he
applies his own intellect to the fourth chapter but in such a
manner that he speaks of things that far surpass the
physical, sensory world, yet have something to do with this
world. We realize that he took pains to apply the intellect
to eschatology and soteriology. After all, we know the kind
of scholarly disputes and discussions Scotus Erigena was
involved in. For example, he was involved in discussions of
the question whether in Communion, that is, in something that
was related to the Mystery of Golgotha, human beings confront
the actual blood and the actual body of Christ. He took part
in all the discussions of human will, its freedom and lack of
freedom in connection with divine grace. Hence, he honed and
schooled his intellect in regard to everything that was the
subject of his fourth chapter. This is what people discussed
then.
We could say
that the content of the first three chapters was an ancient
tradition. One did not change it much but simply communicated
it. The fourth chapter, on the other hand, was a living
striving; there, the intellect was applied and schooled.
What became
of this intellect that was schooled there? What happened to
the concepts of soteriology and eschatology arrived at by
people like Scotus Erigena in the ninth century? You see, my
dear friends, since the middle of the fifteenth century this
has become our science, the basis of the perception of
nature. Once, people employed the intellect in order to
consider whether bread and wine in the Sacrament are
transformed into the body and blood of Christ. They pondered
whether grace is bestowed on man in one way or another. This
same intellect was later used to consider whether the
molecule consists of atoms and whether the sun's body
consists of one form of substance or another, and so on. It
is the continuation of the theological intellect that
inhabits natural science today. Precisely the same intellect
that stimulated Scotus and the others who were involved with
him in the dispute over Communion — and the discussions
were indeed very lively in those days — survived in the
teachings of Galileo and Copernicus. It survived in
Darwinism, even, say, in Strauss's materialism. It has lived
on in a straight line. You know that the old is always
preserved alongside the new. Therefore, the same intellect
that in David Friedrich Strauss hatched the book The Old and
the New Faith, which preaches total atheism, occupied itself
in those days, with soteriology and eschatology; it continues
in a straight line.
We could
therefore say that if this book had to be written today based
as much on modern conditions as Scotus Erigena based what he
wrote on the conditions of his age, then, here
(referring to outline above),
total atheism
would not appear, but rather our natural science. For,
naturally, complete atheism would contradict the first
chapter. In the ninth century soteriology and eschatology
still appeared there, for then the intellect was applied to
other things. But here, (see p. 281), materialistic science
would emerge today. History reveals to us nothing else but
this. Now, we can perhaps see what becomes evident from the
whole conception of this work.
Basically,
what is listed here
(outline above)
would have to appear in a different sequence. The third
chapter would have to read: world view of the first
post-Atlantean age. The second chapter, would have to read:
world view of the second post-Atlantean age, and the first
chapter: world view of the third post-Atlantean age. In the
sense of Scotus Erigena — who lived in the fourth
post-Atlantean age that only came to an end in the fifteenth
century — the last chapter applies to the fourth
post-Atlantean epoch. The sequence (in the outline) would
therefore have to be: III, II, I, IV. This is what I meant
when I said earlier that one receives the impression that
things are actually mixed up. Scotus Erigena simply possessed
bits of the ancient legacy but he did not list them in
accordance with their sequence in time. They were part of the
knowledge of his age, and he mentioned them in the order in
which they were most familiar to him. He listed the nearest
at hand as the highest; the others appeared so nebulous to
him that he considered them to be inferior.
Yet, the
fourth chapter is nevertheless most remarkable. Let us try to
understand from a certain viewpoint what it should actually
be. Let us go back into pre-Christian times. If we were to
seek among the Egyptians a representative mind such as Scotus
Erigena was for the ninth century, such a person would still
have known something concerning theology in a most lively
way. He would have had even more alive concepts of the ideal
or angelic world, of the sphere that illuminates and
permeates the whole world with spirit. He would still have
known all that and would have said: In the very first age,
there once existed a human world view that beheld the spirit
in all things. But then, the spirit was abstractly lifted up
into the heights. It became the ideal world, finally the
divine world. Then, the fourth epoch arrived. It was supposed
to be even more spiritualized than the theological epoch.
This Greco-Latin period was really supposed to be more
spiritualized than the third epoch. And above all, the fifth
which then followed, namely our time, would have to be an
even more spiritualized era, for with materialistic science
in place of soteriology or eschatology it would have to be
listed in fourth place, or we would have to add a fifth
listing with our natural science, and the latter would have
to be the most spiritual view.
Yet, in fact,
my dear friends, matters are buried. We hear Scotus Erigena
saying that man exists as a mineral being, lives and thrives
as a plant, feels as an animal, judges and draws conclusions
as a human being, perceives as an angel — something
Erigena still knew from ancient traditions. Now, we who
aspire to spirit knowledge would have to go even further. We
would have to say: Right, human beings exist as mineral
beings, live and thrive as plants, feel as animals, judge and
draw conclusions as human beings, perceive as angels and,
sixth, human beings behold — namely, imaginatively, the
spiritual world — as archangels. When we speak of the
human being since the first third of the fifteenth century,
we would have to ascribe to ourselves the following. We
perceive as angels and develop the consciousness soul by
means of soul faculties of vision — to begin with,
unconsciously, but yet as consciousness soul — as
archangels.
Thus, we face
the paradox that in the materialistic age human beings
actually live in the spiritual world, dwelling on a higher
spiritual level than they did in earlier times. We can
actually say: Yes, Scotus Erigena is right, the angel
experience is awakening in man, but the archangel experience
is also awakening since the first third of the fifteenth
century. We should rightfully be in a spiritual world.
In realizing
this, we could really look back also to a passage in the
Gospels that is always interpreted in a most trivial way,
namely, the one saying: The end of the world is near and the
kingdoms of heaven are at hand. Yes, my dear friends, when we
have to say of ourselves that in us the archangel is
developing vision so that we can receive the consciousness
soul, then there results a strange view of this approach of
the heavens. It appears that it is necessary to revise such
conceptions of the New Testament once more from the
standpoint of spiritual science. These views are very much in
need of revision, and we really have two tasks: First, to
understand whether our age is not actually meant to to be
different than the age when Christ walked on earth and
whether the end of the world of which Christ spoke might not
be something we have behind us already? This is the one task
we confront. And if it is true that we have the so-called
end of the world behind us and we therefore already face the
spiritual world, then we would have to explain why it has
such an unspiritual appearance, why it has become so
material, arriving finally at that terrible, astounding life
that characterizes the first third of the twentieth century?
Two mighty and overwhelming questions place themselves before
our soul. We shall continue speaking about that tomorrow.
|