XI
Relationship of the Goethean Way of Thinking to Other Views
When one
speaks of the influence of earlier or contemporary thinkers upon the
development of Goethe's spirit, this cannot be done out of the
assumption that he formed his views on the basis of their teachings.
The way he had to think, the way he saw the world, were inherent in
the whole predisposition of his nature. And it lay in his being,
indeed, from his earliest youth. In this respect he then also
remained the same his whole life long. It is principally two
significant character traits that come into consideration here. The
first is his pressing urge to find the sources, the depths of all
existence. This is, ultimately, his belief in the idea. Goethe is
always filled with an intimation of something higher, better. One
would like to call this a deep religious impulse of his spirit. What
so many people need to do — to strip things of everything holy
and pull them down to their own level — is unknown to him. But
he does have the other need: to sense something higher and to work
his way up to it. He sought to gain from everything an aspect by
which it becomes holy to us. K. J. Schröer has shown this in the
most brilliant way with respect to Goethe's attitude toward love.
Goethe divests love of everything frivolous, careless, and it becomes
for him a devout state. This fundamental trait of his being is
expressed most beautifully in his words:
Within our bosom's pureness swells a striving,
To give oneself, in thankful, free devotion,
To something higher, purer, as yet unknown.
We call it: being devout!
This side
of his being, now, is inseparably connected with another one. He
never seeks to approach this higher something directly; he always
seeks to draw near to it through nature. “The true is like God;
it does not appear directly; we must guess it from its
manifestations”
(Aphorisms in Prose).
Besides his belief in the idea Goethe also has the other one: that we can
gain the idea by contemplating reality; it does not occur to him to seek
the divinity anywhere else than in the works of nature, but he seeks
everywhere to gain from them their divine aspect. When, in his youth,
he erects an altar to the great God who “stands in direct
connection with nature”
(Poetry and Truth),
this ritual definitely springs already out of a belief that we gain the
highest that we can attain by a faithful fostering of our
interrelationship with nature. Thus, that way of looking at things
which we have validated epistemologically is innate in Goethe. He
approaches reality with the conviction that everything is only a
manifestation of the idea, and that we can attain this idea only when
we raise sense experience into a spiritual beholding. This conviction
was inherent in him, and from his youth up, he looked at the world on
the basis of this presupposition. No philosopher could give him this
conviction. This is therefore not what Goethe sought from the
philosophers. It was something else. Even though his way of looking
at things lay deep in his nature, still he needed a language in which
to express it. His nature worked in a philosophical way, i.e., in
such a way that it can be expressed only in philosophical
formulations and can be validated only by philosophical
presuppositions. And he looked into the philosophers in order also to
bring clearly to consciousness for himself what he was, in
order also to know what lay in him as living activity.
He sought in them an explanation and validation of his own being.
That is his relationship to the philosophers. To this end, he studies
Spinoza in his youth and entered later into scientific discourse with
his philosophical contemporaries. In his early years, Spinoza and
Giordano Bruno seemed to the poet to best express his own nature. It
is remarkable that he first learned to know both thinkers from books
hostile to them, and, in spite of this fact, recognized how their
teachings relate to his nature. We see this substantiated especially
in his relationship to Giordano Bruno's teachings. He becomes
acquainted with him in Bayle's dictionary, where he is vehemently
attacked. And Goethe receives such a deep impression from him that,
in those parts of Faust which in their conception stem from
the period around 1770 when he was reading Bayle, the language echoes
sentences of Bruno. In his daily and yearly notebooks the poet
relates that he again occupied himself with Giordano Bruno in 1812.
This time also the impression is a powerful one, and in many of the
poems written after this year we can recognize echoes of the
philosopher of Nola. But all this should not be taken to mean that
Goethe borrowed or learned anything from Bruno; he only found in him
the formulations in which to express what had lain in his own nature
for a long time. He found that he could most clearly present his own
inner life if he did so in the words of that thinker. Bruno regarded
universal reason as the creator and director of the universe. He
calls it the inner artist that forms matter and shapes it from
within outward. It is the cause of everything that exists, and
there is no being in whose existence it does not take a loving
interest. “However small and trifling a thing may be, it still
has within it a portion of spiritual substance”, (Giordano Bruno,
About the Cause,
etc.). That was also Goethe's view, that we
first know how to judge a thing when we see how it has been set in
its place by universal reason, how it has come to be precisely that
which confronts us. Perceiving with the senses does not suffice, for
the senses do not tell us how a thing relates to the general world
idea, what it means for the great whole. There we must look in such a
way that our reason creates an ideal basis on which there can then
appear to us what the senses convey to us; we must, as Goethe
expresses it, look with the eyes of the spirit. Even for
expressing this conviction he found a formulation in Bruno: “For,
just as we do not recognize colours and sounds with one and the same
sense, so also we do not recognize the substratum of the arts and
that of nature with one and the same eye,” because we “see
the first with the physical eye and the second with the eye
of reason.” And with Spinoza it is no different. Spinoza's
teachings are indeed based on the fact that the divinity has merged
with the world. Human knowing can therefore aim only to penetrate
into the world in order to know God. Any other way of arriving at God
must seem impossible to anyone thinking consistently according to
Spinoza's way of thinking. For God has given up all existence of His
own; outside the world He exists nowhere. But we must seek Him where
He is. Any actual knowing must therefore be of such a kind that, in
every piece of world knowledge, it conveys to us a piece of divine
knowledge. Knowing, at its highest level, is therefore a
coming together with the divinity. There we call it knowing in
beholding (anschauliches Wissen). We know things “sub
specie æternitatis,” that is, as flowing from the
divinity. The laws that our spirit recognizes in nature are therefore
God in His very being; they are not only made by Him. What we
recognize as logical necessity is so because the being of the
divinity, i.e., the eternal lawfulness, dwells within it. That was a
view which is in accordance with the Goethean spirit. His own firm
belief that nature, in all its doings, reveals something divine to us
lay before him in Spinoza's writings in the clearest statements. “I
am holding firmly and ever more firmly to the atheist's (Spinoza) way
of revering God,” he writes to Jacobi when the latter wanted to
put the teachings of Spinoza in another light. Therein lies the
relatedness of Goethe to Spinoza. And it indicates a superficial
judgment of the matter when, with respect to this deep inner harmony
between Goethe's nature and Spinoza's teachings, one ever and again
emphasizes something purely external by saying that Goethe was drawn
to Spinoza because he, like Spinoza, would not tolerate a final cause
in explaining the world. The fact that Goethe, like Spinoza, rejected
final causes was only one result of their views. But let us
put the theory of final causes clearly before us. A thing is
explained, in its existence and nature, by the fact that one
demonstrates its necessity for something else. One shows that this
thing is of such and such a nature because that other thing is like
this or that. This presupposes that a world ground exists which
stands over and above both beings and arranges them in such a way
that they match each other. But if the world ground is inherent in
every single thing, then this kind of explanation makes no sense. For
then the nature of a thing must appear to us as the result of the
principle at work within it. We will seek, within the nature
of a thing, the reason why it is as it is and not different
than it is. If we hold the belief that something divine is inherent
in each thing, then it will not in fact occur to us to seek to
explain its lawfulness by any outer principle. The relationship of
Goethe to Spinoza should also not be grasped in any other way than
that he found in Spinoza the formulations, the scientific language,
for expressing the world lying within him.
When we now pass on to Goethe's connection to contemporary
philosophers, we must speak above all about Kant. Kant is generally
regarded as the founder of present-day philosophy. In his time he
called forth such a powerful movement that every educated person
needed to come to terms with it. It was also necessary for Goethe to
do so. But this did not prove to be a fruitful undertaking for him.
For there is a deep antithesis between what the Kantian philosophy
teaches and what we have recognized as the Goethean way of thinking.
In fact, one can even say that all German thinking runs it course in
two parallel streams: one permeated by the Kantian way of thinking
and another that is close to Goethean thinking. But as philosophy
today draws ever closer to Kant, it is distancing itself from Goethe,
and through this the possibility for our age of grasping and
appreciating the Goethean world view is being lost more and more. Let
us set before us the main postulates of Kant's teachings insofar as
they are of interest with respect to Goethe's views. For Kant, the
starting point for human thinking is experience, i.e., the world
given to the senses (among which is included the inner sense that
conveys to us such facts as the psychic, historical, and the like).
This world is a manifoldness of things in space and of processes in
time. The fact that precisely this thing confronts me or that I
experience precisely that process is of no consequence; it could also
be different. I can think away the whole manifoldness of things and
processes altogether. What I cannot think away, however, are space
and time. For me, there can be nothing that is not spatial or
temporal. Even if there were some non-spatial or non-temporal thing,
I can know nothing about it, for I can picture nothing to myself
without space and time. I do not know whether the things themselves
partake of space and time; I only know that the things must appear
to me in these forms. Space and time are therefore the prerequisites
of my sense perception. I know nothing of any thing-in-itself;
I only know how it must appear to me if it is to be there for me.
With these postulates Kant introduces a new problem. He appears in
science with a new way of asking questions. Instead of asking, as
earlier philosophers did: What is the nature of things?, he asks: How
must things appear to us in such a way that they can become the
object of our knowing? For Kant, philosophy is the science of the
factors that determine the possibility of the world as a
manifestation for human beings. We know nothing about the
thing-in-itself. We have not yet fulfilled our task when we arrive at
a sense perception of a manifoldness in time and space. We strive to
draw this manifoldness together into a unity. This is a matter for
the intellect. The intellect is to be understood as a sum of
activities whose purpose is to draw the sense world together
according to certain forms already sketched out in the intellect. It
draws together two sense perceptions by, for example, designating one
as the cause and the other as the effect, or the one as substance and
the other as attribute, etc. Here also it is the task of the science
of philosophy to show under which conditions the intellect succeeds
in forming a system of the world. Thus the world, according to Kant,
is actually a subjective phenomenon arising in the forms of the sense
world and of the intellect. Only one thing is certain: that there is
a thing-in-itself; how it appears to us depends upon our
organization. It is also obvious now that it makes no sense to
ascribe to that world which the intellect has formed in association
with the senses any significance other than what it has for our
ability to know. This becomes clearest of all where Kant speaks of
the significance of the world of ideas. Ideas for him are nothing
other than the higher points of view of reason from which the lower
entities, which the intellect has created, are understood. The
intellect brings soul phenomena, for example, into a relationship;
reason, as the faculty for ideas, then grasps this relationship as
though everything went forth from one soul. But this has no
significance for the thing itself; it is only a means of orientation
for our cognitive faculty. This is the content of Kant's theoretical
philosophy insofar as it can be of interest to us here. One sees at
once that it is the polar opposite of the Goethean philosophy. Given
reality is determined, according to Kant, by us ourselves; it is as
it is because we picture it that way. Kant skips over the real
epistemological question. At the beginning of his
Critique of Reason
he takes two steps that he does not justify, and his whole
edifice of philosophical teachings suffers from this mistake. He
right away sets up a distinction between object and subject, without
asking at all what significance it has then for the intellect to
undertake the separation of two regions of reality (in this case the
knowing subject and the object to be known). Then he seeks to
establish conceptually the reciprocal relationship of these
two regions, again without asking what it means to establish
something like that. If his view of the main epistemological question
had not been all askew, he would have seen that the holding apart of
subject and object is only a transitional point in our knowing, that
a deeper unity, which reason can grasp, underlies them both, and that
what is attributed to a thing as a trait, when considered in
connection with a knowing subject, by no means has only subjective
validity. A thing is a unity for our reason and the separation into
“thing-in-itself” and “thing-for-us” is a
product of our intellect. It will not do, therefore, to say that what
is attributed to a thing in one connection can be denied it in other
connections. For, whether I look at the same thing one time from this
point of view and another time from that: it is after all still a
unified whole.
It is an error, running through Kant's entire edifice of teachings,
for him to regard the sense-perceptible manifoldness as something
fixed, and for him to believe that science consists in bringing this
manifoldness into a system. He has no inkling at all that the
manifoldness is not something ultimate, that one must overcome
it if one wants to comprehend it; and therefore all theory becomes
for him merely a supplement that the intellect and reason add onto
experience. For him, the idea is not what appears to reason as the
deeper ground of the given world when reason has overcome the
manifoldness lying on the surface, but rather the idea is only a
methodological principle by which reason orders the phenomena in
order to have a better overview of them. According to the Kantian
view, we would be going totally amiss if we were to regard things as
traceable back to the idea; in his opinion, we can only order our
experiences as though they stemmed from a unity. According to
Kant, we have no inkling of the ground of things, of the “in-itself.”
Our knowing of things is only there in connection with us; it is
valid only for our individuality. Goethe could not gain much from
this view of the world. The contemplation of things in their
connection to us always remained for him a quite subordinate one,
having to do with the effect of objects upon our feelings of pleasure
and pain; he demands more of science than a mere statement as to how
things are in their connection to us. In the essay
The Experiment as Mediator between Subject and Object,
he determines what the
task of the researcher is: He should take his yardstick for
knowledge, the data for his judgment, not from himself, but rather
from the sphere of the things he observes. This one statement
characterizes the deep antithesis between the Kantian and the
Goethean way of thinking. Whereas with Kant, all judgments about
things are only a product of subject and object, and only
provide a knowing about how the subject beholds the object, with
Goethe, the subject merges selflessly into the object and draws the
data for his judgment from the sphere of the things. Goethe himself
says therefore of Kant's adherents: “They certainly heard me
but had no answer for me nor could be in any way helpful.”
The poet believed that he gained more from Kant's critique of the
power of judgment.
Philosophically, Goethe benefited far more from Schiller than from
Kant. Through him, namely, Goethe was really brought one stage
further in the recognition of his own way of viewing things. Up to
the time of that first famous conversation with Schiller, Goethe had
practiced a certain way of viewing the world. He had observed plants,
found that an archetypal plant underlies them, and derived the
individual forms from it. This archetypal plant (and also a
corresponding archetypal animal) had taken shape in his spirit, was
useful to him in explaining the relevant phenomena. But he had never
reflected upon what this archetypal plant was in its essential
nature. Schiller opened his eyes by saying to him: It is an idea.
Only from then on is Goethe aware of his idealism. Up until that
conversation, he calls the archetypal plant an experience for he
believed he saw it with his eyes. But in the introduction that he
later added to his essay on the metamorphosis of the plants he says:
“So from now on, I undertook to find the archetypal animal,
which means, ultimately, the concept, the idea of the animal.”
But we must bear in mind here that Schiller did not provide Goethe
with something foreign to him, but rather Schiller, by observing the
Goethean spirit, struggled through for the first time to a knowledge
of objective idealism. He only found the right term for the
way of viewing things that he recognized and marveled at in Goethe.
Goethe experienced but little benefit from Fichte. Fichte moved in a
sphere that was much too foreign to Goethean thinking to be of much
possible benefit. Fichte founded the science of consciousness in the
most brilliant way. In a unique and exemplary way, he traced the
activity by which the “I” transforms the world that is
given, into a world that is thought. But in doing so, he made the
mistake of not merely regarding this activity of the “I”
as one that brings the given content into a satisfactory form, that
brings the unrelated given into the appropriate relationships; he saw
this activity as a creating of everything which takes place within
the “I.” Therefore his teachings appear as a one-sided
idealism that takes its whole content from consciousness. Goethe, who
always devoted himself wholly to what is objective, could find very
little to attract him in Fichte's philosophy of consciousness. Goethe
lacked understanding for the region where that philosophy is valid;
but the lengths to which Fichte carried it (he saw it as the
universal science) could only appear to the poet as an error.
Goethe had many more points of contact with the young Schelling.
Schelling was a student of Fichte. He did not only carry further the
analysis of the activity of the “I,” however, but also
investigated this activity within the consciousness by which nature
is grasped. What takes place in the “I” when it is
knowing nature seemed to Schelling to be at the same time that which
is objective about nature, the actual principle within it. External
nature was for him only a form of our nature concepts that has become
fixed. What lives in us as a view of nature appears to us again
outside, only spread out, spatial-temporally. What confronts us from
outside as nature is a finished product, is only something already
determined, the form of a living principle that has become rigid. We
cannot gain this principle through experience from outside. We must
first create it within our inner being. “To philosophize about
nature means to create nature,” our philosopher says
therefore. “We call nature, as a mere product (natura
naturata), ‘nature as object’ (all empiricism devotes
itself to this alone). We call nature, as productivity (natura
naturans), ‘nature as subject’ (all theory devotes
itself to this alone).” (Introduction to Schelling's
First Sketch of a System of Natural Philosophy)
[ 63 ]
“The contrast between empiricism and science rests, indeed, on the
fact that empiricism studies its object in existence as something finished
and already brought about, whereas science, on the other hand,
studies the object in its becoming and as something still to be
brought about.” (Ibid.) Through these teachings, with
which Goethe became acquainted partly from Schelling's writings and
partly from personal encounters with the philosopher, the poet was
again brought a stage higher. He now developed the view that his
tendency was to proceed from what is finished, the product, to what
is becoming, the productive. And, with a definite echo of Schelling,
he writes in his essay
The Power to Judge in Beholding
that his striving was to make himself “worthy, through beholding an
ever-creating nature, of participating spiritually in its
productions.”
And through Hegel, finally, Goethe received his last help from the
side of philosophy. Through him he gained clarity, namely, as to how
what he called the archetypal phenomenon fitted into
philosophy. Hegel understood the significance of the archetypal
phenomenon more deeply than anyone else and characterized it aptly in
a letter to Goethe on February 20, 1821 with the words: “The
simple and abstract, what you quite aptly call the archetypal
phenomenon, this you put first, and then show the concrete phenomena
as arising through the participation of yet other influences and
circumstances; and you direct the whole process in such a way that
the sequence proceeds from the simple, determining factors to the
composite ones, and, thus arranged, something complex appears in all
its clarity through this decomposition. To seek out the archetypal
phenomenon, to free it from other extraneous chance surroundings —
to grasp it abstractly, as we call it — this I consider to be
the task for a great spiritual sense for nature, just as I consider
that procedure altogether to be what is truly scientific in gaining
knowledge in this field.” ... “But may I now also speak
to you about the particular interest which the archetypal phenomenon,
lifted out in this way, has for us philosophers; namely, that we can
put something prepared in this way precisely to philosophical use!
If, in spite of everything, we have finally led our initially
oysterlike, grey, or completely black absolute out toward the air and
light, so that it desires them, then we need windows in order to lead
it out fully into the light of day; our schemata would disperse into
mist if we were to transfer them directly into the colourful,
confused society of a resistant world. Here is where your archetypal
phenomena now stand us in excellent stead; in this twilight —
spiritual and comprehensible through its simplicity, visible or
graspable through its sense-perceptibility — the two worlds
greet each other: our abstruse existence and the manifest one.”
In this way, through Hegel, the thought becomes clear to Goethe that
the empirical researcher has to go as far as the archetypal phenomena
and that the paths of the philosopher lead on from there. But from
this it is also clear that the basic thought of Hegelian philosophy
follows from the Goethean way of thinking. The overcoming of human
nature, the entering deeply into it in order to ascend from the
created to the creating, from the determined to the determining, is
fundamental to Goethe, but also to Hegel. Hegel, indeed, wants to
present nothing other in philosophy than the eternal process from
which everything finite emerges. He wants to know the given as a
result of that to which he can grant validity as something
undetermined.
Thus for Goethe, acquainting himself with philosophers and with
directions in philosophy means an ongoing clarification of what
already lay in him. He gained nothing new for his views; he was only
given the means of speaking about what he did, about what was going
on in his soul.
Thus the Goethean world view offers many points of reference for
philosophical elaboration. But these were initially taken up only by
the pupils of Hegel. The rest of philosophy took a stand of dignified
rejection toward the Goethean view. Only Schopenhauer bases himself
in many respects upon the poet, whom he values highly. We will speak
in a later chapter about his apologetic of the colour theory. Here it
is a matter of describing the general relationship of Schopenhauer's
teachings to Goethe.
[ 64 ]
In one point the Frankfurt
philosopher comes close to Goethe. Schopenhauer rejects, namely, any
deriving from outer causes of the phenomena given us and admits the
validity only of an inner lawfulness, of a deriving of one phenomenon
from another. This seems to be the same as the Goethean principle of
taking the data for an explanation from the things themselves; but
only seemingly. Schopenhauer wants to remain in the realm of
phenomena because he believes we cannot attain in knowledge the
“in-itself” lying outside this realm, since all the
phenomena given us are only mental pictures
[ 65 ]
and our ability to make mental pictures never takes us outside our
consciousness; Goethe, on the other hand, wants to remain within the
phenomena, because he in fact seeks within the phenomena themselves
the data needed for their explanation.
In conclusion, let us still compare the Goethean world view with the
most significant scientific phenomenon of our time, with the views of
Eduard von Hartmann. This thinker's
Philosophy of the Unconscious
[ 66 ]
is a work of the greatest historical significance.
Taken together with the other writings of Hartmann (which elaborate
in all directions what he there sketched out and in fact bring new
points of view to that main work in many respects), this book mirrors
the entire spiritual content of our age. Hartmann demonstrates a
remarkable profundity and an amazing mastery of the material of the
individual sciences. He stands today in the vanguard of culture. One
does not need to be an adherent of his to have to acknowledge this
unreservedly.
His view is not so far from Goethe's as one might believe at first
glance. Someone who has access only to the
Philosophy of the Unconscious
will not, to be sure, be able to see this. For, one
sees the definite points of contact between these two thinkers only
when one goes into the consequences that Hartmann drew from
his principles and which he set down in his later writings.
Hartmann's philosophy is idealism. He does not want to be a mere
idealist, it is true. But where, for the purpose of explaining the
world, he needs something positive, he does after all seek help from
ideas. And the most important thing is that he thinks of the idea as
the underlying principle everywhere. His assumption of an unconscious
means nothing other, in fact, than that what is present in our
consciousness as idea is not necessarily bound to this form of
manifestation within our consciousness. The idea is not only present
(active), where it becomes conscious, but also in another
form. The idea is more than a merely subjective phenomenon; it has a
significance founded within itself. It is not merely present within
the subject; it is the objective world principle. Even though
Hartmann includes will, in addition to the idea, among the
principles constituting the world, it is nevertheless
incomprehensible that there are still philosophers who regard him as
an adherent of Schopenhauer. Schopenhauer carried to extremes the
view that all conceptual content is only subjective, is only a
phenomenon of consciousness. With him, it is absolutely out of the
question for the idea to have participated as a real principle in the
constitution of the world. For him, will is the exclusive
world ground. Therefore Schopenhauer could never find a way, with any
content, of handling the specialized branches of philosophy, whereas
Hartmann followed up his principles into all the particular sciences.
Whereas Schopenhauer can say nothing more about the extremely rich
content of history than that it is a manifestation of will, Eduard
von Hartmann knows how to find the ideal core of every single
historical phenomenon, and how to incorporate each phenomenon into
the total historical development of mankind. The individual entity,
the individual phenomenon, cannot be of interest to Schopenhauer, for
he knows only one essential thing to say about it: that it is a
manifestation of the will. Hartmann takes up each particular entity
and shows how the idea is everywhere perceptible. The basic character
of Schopenhauer's world view is uniformity; that of von Hartmann is
unity. Schopenhauer bases the world upon an empty uniform urge;
Hartmann bases it upon the rich content of the idea. Schopenhauer
sets an abstract unity as a basis; with Hartmann, we find the
concrete idea as principle, whose unity — or rather unifiedness
— is only one characteristic of the idea. Schopenhauer would
never have been able, as Hartmann was, to create a philosophy of
history or a science of religion. When Hartmann says that “reason
is the logical form principle of the idea — of the idea that is
inseparably united with the will — and as such altogether
governs and determines the content of the world process”
(Philosophical Questions of the Present Day
[ 67 ]),
then this presupposition makes it possible for him, in every
phenomenon that confronts us in nature and in history, to seek out
its logical core, which, although not graspable by the senses, is
quite graspable by thinking, and in this way to explain the
phenomenon. Whoever does not make this presupposition will never be
able to justify his wanting to determine anything at all about the
world by reflection in the medium of ideas.
In his objective idealism Eduard von Hartmann stands entirely upon
the ground of the Goethean world view. When Goethe says that
“everything of which we become aware and about which we are
able to speak is only a manifestation of the idea”
(Aphorisms in Prose),
and when he states that the human being must develop
within himself a capacity for knowledge of such a kind that the idea
becomes just as observable to him as an outer perception is to his
senses, then he stands upon that ground where the idea is not merely
a phenomenon of consciousness but is an objective world principle;
thinking is the flashing up in consciousness of that which
objectively constitutes the world. The essential thing about the
idea, therefore, is not what it is for us, for our consciousness, but
rather what it is in itself. For, through its own particular being it
underlies the world as principle. Therefore thinking is a becoming
aware of what exists in and of itself. Therefore, although the idea
would not come to manifestation at all if there were no
consciousness, still the idea must be grasped in such a way that its
characteristic feature consists not of its being conscious but rather
of what it is in itself, of what lies within the idea itself; and
this is not affected by its becoming conscious. Therefore, according
to Eduard von Hartmann, we must base the world upon the idea —
without regard to its becoming conscious — as something working
and unconscious. That is what is essential for Hartmann: that we must
seek the idea in everything unconscious.
But not much is accomplished by this distinguishing between what is
conscious and what is unconscious. For that is, after all, only a
distinction for my consciousness. But one must grapple with
the idea in all its objectivity, in all its fullness of content; one
must consider not only that the idea is at work unconsciously,
but also what this working element is. If Hartmann had stopped
at the fact that the idea is unconscious and if he had explained the
world out of this unconscious element — that is, out of a
one-sided characteristic of the idea — then he would have added
a new uniform system to the many systems that derive the world from
some abstract formal principle or other. And one cannot declare his
first main work to be entirely free of this uniformity. But Eduard
von Hartmann's spirit works too intensively, too comprehensively and
penetratingly, for him not to have recognized that the idea cannot be
grasped merely as something unconscious; rather, one must in fact go
deeply into what one has to address as unconscious, must go beyond
this characteristic to its concrete content and derive from it the
world of individual phenomena. In this way, Hartmann transformed
himself from the abstract monist, which he still is in his
Philosophy of the Unconscious,
into a concrete monist. And it is the
concrete idea that Goethe addresses in the three forms: archetypal
phenomenon, typus, and “idea in the narrower sense.”
What we find of Goethe's world view in Eduard von Hartmann's
philosophy is the becoming aware of something objective within our
world of ideas, and the devotion, arising from this becoming aware,
to this objective element. Hartmann was led by his philosophy of the
unconscious to this merging with the objective idea. Since he
recognized that the being of the idea does not lie in its being
conscious, he had to recognize the idea also as something existing in
and of itself, as something objective. The fact that he also includes
the will among the principles constituting the world does make him
differ again from Goethe, to be sure. Nevertheless, where Hartmann is
really fruitful, the will motif does not come into consideration at
all. That he assumes this motif at all comes from the fact that he
regards the ideas as something static which, in order to begin
working, needs the impetus of will. According to Hartmann, the will
alone can never achieve the creation of the world, for it is the
empty, blind urge for existence. If the will is to bring forth
something, then the idea must enter in, because only the idea
gives the will a content for its working. But what are we to
make of this will? It slips away from us when we want to grasp it;
for we cannot after all grasp an empty urging that has no content.
And so it turns out after all that everything which we actually grasp
of the world principle is idea, because what is graspable must in
fact have content. We can only grasp what is full of content, not
what is empty of content. If therefore we are to grasp the concept
will, it must after all arise in the content of the idea; it
can appear only in and along with the idea, as the form in which it
arises, never independently. What exists must have content;
there can only be existence which is full; there cannot be an empty
one. Therefore, Goethe pictures the idea as active, as
something working, which needs no further impetus. For, something
full of content may not and cannot first receive from something empty
of content, the impetus to come into existence. The idea therefore,
according to Goethe, is to be grasped as entelechy, i.e., as
an already active existence; and one must first draw an abstraction
from its form as an active existence if one then wants to bring it
back again under the name will. The will motif also has no
value at all for positive science. Hartmann also does not need it
when he confronts the concrete phenomenon.
If we have recognized in Hartmann's view of nature an echo of
Goethe's world view, we find an even more significant one in that
philosopher's ethics. Eduard von Hartmann finds that all striving for
happiness, all pursuing of egoism, is ethically worthless, because we
can, after all, never achieve contentment on this path. Hartmann
considers acting out of egoism, and trying to satisfy it, to be
illusory. We should grasp the task we are set in the world, and act
purely for the sake of this task itself, with
self-renunciation. We should find our goal in our devotion to the
object, without demanding that our subject profit from it in some
way. But this forms the basic impulse of Goethe's ethics. Hartmann
should not have suppressed the word that expresses the character of
his teachings on morality: love.
[ 68 ]
Where we claim nothing personally, where we act only because something
objective moves us, where we find in the act itself the motive for our
action, there we are acting morally. But there we are acting out of
love. All self-will, everything personal, must disappear there. It
is characteristic of the way Hartmann's powerful and healthy spirit
works, that in spite of the fact that he first grasped the idea
one-sidedly as unconscious, he still pressed forward to concrete
idealism; and that in spite of the fact that he took his start in
ethics from pessimism, he was still led by this mistaken standpoint
to the ethical teaching of love. Hartmann's pessimism, in
fact, does not mean what those people interpret it to mean who like
to lament about the fruitlessness of our activity because they hope
to find themselves justified by this in folding their hands in their
laps and accomplishing nothing. Hartmann does not stop at such
lamenting; he raises himself above any such impulse to a pure ethics.
He shows the worthlessness of the pursuit of happiness by revealing
its fruitlessness. He directs us thereby to our own activity. That he
is a pessimist at all is his error. That is perhaps still a remnant
from earlier stages of his thinking. From where he stands now, he
would have to realize that the empirical demonstration that in the
world of reality what is unsatisfying outweighs what is satisfying
cannot establish pessimism. For the higher human being cannot wish
for anything else at all than that he must achieve his happiness for
himself. He does not want it as a gift from outside. He wants his
happiness to consist only in his action. Hartmann's pessimism
dissolves before (Hartmann's own) higher thinking. Because the
world leaves us dissatisfied, we create for ourselves the most
beautiful happiness in our own activity.
Thus Hartmann's philosophy is yet another proof of how people
starting from different points of departure arrive at the same goal;
Hartmann takes his start from different presuppositions than Goethe
does, but in his development of them, the Goethean train of thought
confronts us at every turn. We have presented this here because we
wanted to show the deep inner soundness of the Goethean world view.
It lies so deeply founded in the being of the world that we must meet
its basic features wherever energetic thinking penetrates to the
sources of knowledge. Within Goethe everything was so very original,
so totally free from the incidental, fashionable views of the time,
that even his opponent must think in his sense. The eternal
riddle of the world expresses itself, in fact, in single individuals;
in Goethe most significantly of all in recent time; therefore one can
even say that the level of a person's view can be measured today
by the relationship in which it stands to the Goethean view.
|