XIII
Goethe's Basic Geological Principle
Goethe is
very often sought where he is absolutely not to be found. Among the
many other areas where this has happened is the way the geological
research of the poet has been judged. But here more than anywhere it
is necessary for everything that Goethe wrote about details to recede
into the background before the wonderful intention from which he took
his start. He must be judged here above all according to his own
maxim: “In the works of man, as in those of nature, it is
actually the intentions that are primarily worthy of attention”
and “The spirit out of which we act is the highest
thing.” Not what he achieved but rather how he strove
for it is what is exemplary for us. We are dealing, not with a
doctrine, but rather with a method to be communicated. Goethe's
doctrine depends upon the scientific means of the times and can be
superseded; his method sprang from his great spiritual endowment and
stands up even though scientific instruments are being perfected and
our experience broadened.
Goethe was introduced into geology through his occupation with the
Ilmenau mine, which was one of his official duties. When Karl August
became ruler, he devoted himself with great earnestness to this mine,
which had been neglected for a long time. First, the reasons for its
decline were to be thoroughly investigated by experts and then
everything possible was to be done to revive the operation. Goethe
stood by Duke Karl August in his undertaking. He pressed on most
energetically with this matter. This led him often into the Ilmenau
mine. He wanted to familiarize himself completely with the state of
affairs. He was in Ilmenau for the first time in May 1776 and often
thereafter.
In the midst of this practical concern, there now arose in him
the scientific need to arrive at the laws of those phenomena
which he was in a position to observe there. The comprehensive view
of nature that worked its way up in his spirit to ever greater
clarity (see his essay Nature) compelled him to explain, in
his sense, what was spread out there before his eyes.
Here right away a deep-lying characteristic of Goethe's nature
manifests itself. He has an essentially different need than many
investigators. Whereas, for the latter, the main thing is knowledge
of the particulars, whereas they are usually interested in an edifice
of ideas, in a system, only insofar as it is helpful in observing the
particulars, for Goethe, the particulars are only intermediaries to a
comprehensive, total view of existence. We read in the essay Nature:
“Nature consists solely of children, and the mother,
where is she?” We also find in Faust (“See all the
working power and seeds”) the same striving to know not only
the immediately existing, but also its deeper foundations. In this
way, what he observes upon and beneath the surface of the earth also
becomes for him a means It of penetrating into the riddle of how the
world is formed. What he writes to the Duchess Luise on December 23,
1786, ensouls all his research: “The works of nature are always
like a word that has just been spoken by God: and what is
experiencable to the senses becomes for him a writing from which he
must read that word of creation. In this vein he writes to Frau v.
Stein on August 22. 1784: “The great and beautiful writing
is always legible and is indecipherable only when people want to
transfer their own petty images and their own narrow-mindedness onto
the infinite beings.” We find the same tendency in
Wilhelm Meister:
“But if I were now to treat precisely these cracks
and fissures as letters, had to decipher them, were to form them into
words, and learned to read them fully, would you have anything
against that?”
Thus, from the end of the 1770's on, we see the poet engaged in an
unceasing effort to decipher this writing. The goal of his striving
was to work his way up to a view such that what he saw separated
would appear to him in inner, necessary relationship. His method was
“one that develops and unfolds things, by no means one that
compiles and orders them.” It did not suffice for him to see
granite here and porphyry there, etc., and then simply to arrange
them according to external characteristics; he strove for a law that
underlay all rock formation and that he needed only to hold before
himself in spirit in order to understand how granite had to arise
here and porphyry there. He went back from that which differentiates,
to that which is held in common. On June 12, 1784, he writes to Frau
v. Stein: “The simple thread that I have spun for myself is
leading me beautifully through all these subterranean labyrinths, and
is giving me an overview even in the confusion.” He seeks the
common principle that, according to the different conditions under
which it comes to manifestation, at one time brings forth this
kind of rock and another time brings forth that. Nothing in the realm
of experience is a constant for him at which one could remain; only
the principle, which underlies everything, is something of
that kind. Goethe therefore also endeavors always to find the
transitions from rock to rock. One can recognize much better
from them, in fact, the intention, the tendency of their genesis,
than from a product that has already developed in a definite
way, where nature in fact reveals its being only in a one-sided way,
indeed very often “goes astray into a blind alley by
specializing.”
It is an error to believe that one has refuted this method of Goethe
by indicating that present-day geology does not know of any such
transition of one rock into another. Goethe, in fact, never
maintained that granite actually passes over into something
different. What is once granite is a finished, complete product and
no longer has the inner driving power to become something else out of
itself. What Goethe was seeking, however, is in fact lacking in
present-day geology, and that is the idea, the principle that
constitutes granite before it has become granite, and this
idea is the same one that also underlies all other formations. When
Goethe speaks therefore of the transition of one rock into a
different one he does not mean by this a factual
transformation but rather a development of the objective idea that
takes shape in the individual forms, that now holds fast to one form
and becomes granite, and then again develops another possibility out
of itself and becomes slate, etc. Also in this realm Goethe's view is
not a barren theory of metamorphosis but rather concrete idealism.
But that rock-forming principle can come to full expression, with all
that lies in this expression, only within the whole body of the
earth. Therefore the history of the formation of the earth's body
becomes the main thing for Goethe, and all the particulars have to
fit into it. The important thing for him is the place a given rock
occupies in the totality of the earth; the particular thing interests
him only as a part of the whole. Ultimately, that
mineralogical-geological system seems to him to be the correct one
which recreates the processes in the earth, which shows why precisely
this had to arise at this place and that had to arise in another.
Geological deposits become of decisive importance for him. He
therefore criticizes Werner's teachings, which he otherwise reveres
so highly, for not arranging the minerals according to the way they
are deposited, which informs us about how they arose, but rather
according to incidental external features. It is not the
investigator who makes the perfect system, but rather nature itself
which has done that.
It should be borne in mind that Goethe saw in the whole of nature one
great realm, a harmony. He maintains that all natural things are
ensouled with one tendency. What is therefore of the same kind had to
appear to him as determined by the same lawfulness. He could not
grant that other forces are at work in geological phenomena —
which are in fact nothing more than inorganic entities — than
in the rest of inorganic nature. The extending into geology of the
laws of inorganic activity is Goethe's first geological deed. It
was this principle which guided him in his explanation of the
Bohemian mountains and in his explanation of the phenomena observed
at the temple of Serapis at Pozzuoli. He sought to bring principle
into the dead earth crust by thinking of it as having arisen through
those laws which we always see at work before our eyes in physical
phenomena. The geological theories of a Hutton, an Elie de Beaumont
were deeply repugnant to him. What was he supposed to do with
explanations that violate all natural order? It is banal to
repeat so often the empty remark that it was Goethe's peaceful
nature which was repelled by the theory of rising and sinking,
etc. No, this theory affronted his sense for a unified view of
nature. He could not insert this theory into what is in accordance
with nature. And he owes it to this sense that he early on (in 1782
already) arrived at a view that professional geologists attained only
decades later: the view that fossilized animal and plant remains
stand in a necessary relationship with the rock in which they are
found. Voltaire had still spoken of them as freaks of nature,
because he had no inkling of the consistency of natural lawfulness.
Goethe could make sense of a thing in one place or other only if a
simple, natural connection existed between this thing and its
environment. It is also the same principle that led Goethe to the
fruitful idea of an ice age. (see
Geological Problems and an Attempt at their Solution)
[ 69 ]
He sought a simple explanation, in accordance with nature, for deposits
of granite masses widely separated over large areas. He had indeed to
reject the explanation that they had been hurled there by a tumultuous
upheaval of mountains lying far behind them, because this explanation
did not trace a fact of nature back to the existing working laws of
nature but rather derived this fact from an exception, from an
abandonment, in fact, of these laws. He assumed that northern Germany
had once had, under conditions of extreme cold, a general water level
of a thousand feet, that a large part was covered with a layer of
ice, and that those granite blocks were left lying after the ice had
melted away With this, a view was expressed that is based upon known
laws experiencable by us. Goethe's significance for geology is to be
sought in his establishment of a general lawfulness of nature. How
he explained the Kammerberg, whether or not he was correct in his
opinion about the springs of Karlsbad, is unimportant. “It is a
question here not of an opinion to be disseminated, but rather of a
method to be communicated that anyone may make use of in his own way
as a tool” (Goethe to Hegel, October 7, 1820).
|