V
THE WORLD AS PERCEPT
HE
products of thinking are concepts and ideas. What a concept is cannot
be expressed in words. Words can do no more than draw our attention
to the fact that we have concepts. When some one perceives a tree,
the perception acts as a stimulus for thought. Thus an ideal element
is added to the perceived object, and the perceiver regards the
object and its ideal complement as belonging together. When the
object disappears from the field of his perception, the ideal
counterpart alone remains. This latter is the concept of the object.
The wider the range of our experience, the larger becomes the number
of our concepts. Moreover, concepts are not by any means found in
isolation one from the other. They combine to form an ordered and
systematic whole. The concept “organism,” e.g., combines
with those of “development according to law,”
“growth,” and others. Other concepts based on particular
objects fuse completely with one another. All concepts formed from
particular lions fuse in the universal concept “lion.” In
this way, all the separate concepts combine to form a closed,
conceptual system within which each has its special place. Ideas do
not differ qualitatively from concepts. They are but fuller, more
saturated, more comprehensive concepts. I attach special importance
to the necessity of bearing in mind here, that I make thought my
starting-point, and not concepts and ideas which are first gained by
means of thought. These latter presuppose thought. My remarks
regarding the self-dependent, self-sufficient character of thought
cannot, therefore, be simply transferred to concepts. (I make special
mention of this, because it is here that I differ from Hegel, who
regards the concept as something primary and ultimate.)
Concepts
cannot be derived from perception. This is apparent from the fact
that, as man grows up, he slowly and gradually builds up the concepts
corresponding to the objects which surround him. Concepts are added
to perception.
A
philosopher, widely read at the present day (Herbert Spencer),
describes the mental process which we perform upon perception as
follows: “If, when walking through the fields some day in
September, you hear a rustle a few yards in advance, and on observing
the ditch-side where it occurs, see the herbage agitated, you will
probably turn towards the spot to learn by what this sound and motion
are produced. As you approach there flutters into the ditch a
partridge; on seeing which your curiosity is satisfied — you
have what you call an explanation of the appearances. The
explanation, mark, amounts to this — that whereas throughout
life you have had countless experiences of disturbance among small
stationary bodies, accompanying the movement of other bodies among
them, and have generalized the relation between such disturbances and
such movements, you consider this particular disturbance explained on
finding it to present an instance of the like relation”
(First Principles,
Part I, par. 23). A closer analysis leads
to a very different description from that here given. When I hear a
noise my first demand is for the concept which fits this percept.
Without this concept the noise is to me a mere noise. Whoever does
not reflect further, hears just the noise and is satisfied with that.
But my thought makes it clear to me that the noise is to be regarded
as an effect. Thus it is only when I combine the concept of effect
with the percept of a noise that I am led to go beyond the particular
percept and seek for its cause. The concept of “effect”
calls up that of “cause,” and my next step is to look for
the agent, which I find, say, in a partridge. But these concepts,
cause and effect, can never be gained through mere perception,
however many instances we bring under review. Perception evokes
thought, and it is this which shows me how to link separate
experiences together.
If one
demands of a “strictly objective science” that it should
take its data from perception alone, one must demand also that it
abandon all thought. For thought, by its very nature, transcends the
objects of perception.
It is
time now to pass from thought to the thinker. For it is through the
thinker that thought and perception are combined. The human mind is
the stage on which concept and percept meet and are linked to one
another. In saying this, we already characterize this (human)
consciousness. It mediates between thought and perception. In
perception the object appears as given, in thought the mind seems to
itself to be active. It regards the thing as object and itself as the
thinking subject. When thought is directed upon the perceptual world
we have consciousness of objects; when it is directed upon itself we
have self-consciousness. Human consciousness must, of necessity, be
at the same time self-consciousness, because it is a consciousness
which thinks. For when thought contemplates its own activity it makes
an object for study of its own essential nature, it makes an object
of itself as subject.
It is
important to note here that it is only by means of thought that I am
able to determine myself as subject and contrast myself with objects.
Therefore thoughts must never be regarded as a merely subjective
activity. Thinking transcends the distinction of subject and object.
It produces these two concepts just as it produces all others. When,
therefore, I, as thinking subject, refer a concept to an object, we
must not regard this reference as something purely subjective. It is
not the subject, but thought, which makes the reference. The subject
does not think because it is a subject, rather it conceives itself to
be a subject because it can think. The activity of consciousness, in
so far as it thinks, is thus not merely subjective. Rather it is
neither subjective nor objective; it transcends both these concepts.
I ought never to say that I, as an individual subject, think, but
rather that I, as subject, exist myself by the grace of thought.
Thought thus takes me out of myself and relates me to objects. At the
same time it separates me from them, inasmuch as I, as subject, am
set over against the objects.
It is
just this which constitutes the double nature of man. His thought
embraces himself and the rest of the world. But by this same act of
thought he determines himself also as an individual, in contrast with
the objective world.
We must
next ask ourselves how the other element, which we have so far simply
called the perceptual object and which comes, in consciousness, into
contact with thought, enters into thought at all?
In order
to answer this question we must eliminate from the field of
consciousness everything which has been imported by thought. For, at
any moment, the content of consciousness is always shot through with
concepts in the most various ways.
Let us
assume that a being with fully developed human intelligence
originated out of nothing and confronted the world. All that it there
perceived before its thought began to act would be the pure content
of perception. The world so far would appear to this being as a mere
chaotic aggregate of sense-data, colours, sounds, sensations of
pressure, of warmth, of taste, of smell, and, lastly, feelings of
pleasure and pain. This mass constitutes the world of pure unthinking
perception. Over against it stands thought, ready to begin its
activity as soon as it can find a point of attack. Experience shows
that the opportunity is not long in coming. Thought is able to draw
threads from one sense-datum to another. It brings definite concepts
to bear on these data and thus establishes a relation between them.
We have seen above how a noise which we hear is connected with
another content by our identifying the first as the effect of the
second.
If now we
recollect that the activity of thought is on no account to be
considered as merely subjective, then we shall not be tempted to
believe that the relations thus established by thought have merely
subjective validity.
Our next
task is to discover by means of thought what relation the
above-mentioned immediate sense-data have to the conscious
subject.
The
ambiguity of current speech makes it advisable for me to come to an
agreement with my readers concerning the meaning of a word which I
shall have to employ in what follows. I shall apply the name
“percepts” to the immediate sense-data enumerated above,
in so far as the subject consciously apprehends them. It is, then,
not the process of perception, but the object of this process which I
call the “percept.”
I reject
the term “sensation,” because this has a definite meaning
in Physiology which is narrower than that of my term
“percept.” I can speak of feeling as a percept, but not
as a sensation in the physiological sense of the term. Before I can
have cognisance of my feeling it must become a percept for me. The
manner in which, through observation, we gain knowledge of our
thought-processes is such that when we first begin to notice thought,
it too may be called a percept.
The
unreflective man regards his percepts, such as they appear to his
immediate apprehension, as things having a wholly independent
existence. When he sees a tree he believes that it stands in the form
which he sees, with the colours of all its parts, etc., there on the
spot towards which his gaze is directed. When the same man sees the
sun in the morning appear as a disc on the horizon, and follows the
course of this disc, he believes that the phenomenon exists and
occurs (by itself) exactly as he perceives it. To this belief he
clings until he meets with further percepts which contradict his
former ones. The child who has as yet had no experience of distance
grasps at the moon, and does not correct its first impression as to
the real distance until a second percept contradicts the first. Every
extension of the circle of my percepts compels me to correct my
picture of the world. We see this in everyday life, as well as in the
mental development of mankind. The picture which the ancients made
for themselves of the relation of the earth to the sun and other
heavenly bodies, had to be replaced by another when Copernicus found
that it contradicted percepts which in those early days were unknown.
A man who had been born blind said, when operated on by Dr. Franz,
that the idea of the size of objects which he had formed before his
operation by his sense of touch was a very different one. He had to
correct his tactual percepts by his visual percepts.
How is it
that we are compelled to make these continual corrections in our
observations?
A single
reflection supplies the answer to this question. When I stand at one
end of an avenue, the trees at the other end, away from me, seem
smaller and nearer together than those where I stand. But the scene
which I perceive changes when I change the place from which I am
looking. The exact form in which it presents itself to me is,
therefore, dependent on a condition which inheres, not in the object,
but in me, the percipient. It is all the same to the avenue where I
stand. But the picture of it which I receive depends essentially on
my standpoint. In the same way it makes no difference to the sun and
the planetary system that human beings happen to perceive them from
the earth; but the picture of the heavens which human beings have is
determined by the fact that they inhabit the earth. This dependence
of our percepts on our points of observation is the easiest kind of
dependence to understand. The matter becomes more difficult when we
realize further that our perceptual world is dependent on our bodily
and mental organization. The physicist teaches us that within the
space in which we hear a sound there are vibrations of the air, and
that there are vibrations also in the particles of the body which we
regard as the cause of the sound. These vibrations are perceived as
sounds only if we have normally constructed ears. Without them the
whole world would be for us for ever silent. Again, the physiologist
teaches us that there are men who perceive nothing of the wonderful
display of colours which surrounds us. In their world there are only
degrees of light and dark. Others are blind only to one colour, e.g.,
red. Their world lacks this colour tone, and hence it is actually a
different one from that of the average man. I should like to call the
dependence of my perceptual world on my point of observation
“mathematical,” and its dependence on my organization
“qualitative.” The former determines proportions of size
and mutual distances of my percepts, the latter their quality. The
fact that I see a red surface as red — this qualitative
determination — depends on the structure of my eye.
My
percepts, then, are in the first instance subjective. The recognition
of the subjective character of our percepts may easily lead us to
doubt whether there is any objective basis for them at all. When we
know that a percept, e.g., that of a red colour or of a certain tone,
is not possible without a specific structure of our organism, we may
easily be led to believe that it has no being at all apart from our
subjective organization, that it has no kind of existence apart from
the act of perceiving of which it is the object. The classical
representative of this theory is George Berkeley, who held that from
the moment we realize the importance of a subject for perception, we
are no longer able to believe in the existence of a world apart from
a conscious mind. “Some truths there are so near and obvious to
the mind that man need only open his eyes to see them. Such I take
this important one to be, viz., that all the choir of heaven and the
furniture of the earth — in a word, all those bodies which
compose the mighty frame of the world — have not any
subsistence without a mind; that their being is to be perceived or
known; that consequently, so long as they are not actually perceived
by me, or do not exist in my mind or that of any other created
spirit, they must either have no existence at all or else subsist in
the mind of some Eternal Spirit”
(Berkeley,
Of the Principles of Human Knowledge,
Part I, Section 6).
On this
view, when we take away the act of perceiving, nothing remains of the
percept. There is no colour when none is seen, no sound when none is
heard. Extension, form, and motion exist as little as colour and
sound apart from the act of perception. We never perceive bare
extension or shape. These are always joined with colour, or some
other quality, which is undoubtedly dependent on the subject. If
these latter disappear when we cease to perceive, the former, being
connected with them, must disappear likewise.
If it is
urged that, even though figure, colour, sound, etc., have no
existence except in the act of perception, yet there must be things
which exist apart from perception and which are similar to the
percepts in our minds, then the view we have mentioned would answer,
that a colour can be similar only to a colour, a figure to a figure.
Our percepts can be similar only to our percepts and to nothing else.
Even what we call a thing is nothing but a collection of percepts
which are connected in a definite way. If I strip a table of its
shape, extension, colour, etc. — in short, of all that is
merely my percepts — then nothing remains over. If we follow
this view to its logical conclusion, we are led to the assertion that
the objects of my perceptions exist only through me, and that only in
as far as, and as long as, I perceive them. They disappear with my
perceiving and have no meaning apart from it. Apart from my percepts
I know of no objects and cannot know of any.
No
objection can be made to this assertion as long as we take into
account merely the general fact that the percept is determined in
part by the organization of the subject. The matter would be far
otherwise if we were in a position to say what part exactly is played
by our perceiving in the occurrence of a percept. We should know then
what happens to a percept whilst it is being perceived, and we should
also be able to determine what character it must possess before it
comes to be perceived.
This
leads us to turn our attention from the object of a perception to the
subject of it. I am aware not only of other things but also of
myself. The content of my perception of myself consists, in the first
instance, in that I am something stable in contrast with the ever
coming and going flux of percepts. The awareness of myself
accompanies in my consciousness the awareness of all other percepts.
When I am absorbed in the perception of a given object I am, for the
time being, aware only of this object. Next I become aware also of
myself. I am then conscious, not only of the object, but also of my
Self as opposed to and observing the object. I do not merely see a
tree, I know also that it is I who see it. I know, moreover, that
some process takes place in me when I observe a tree. When the tree
disappears from my field of vision, an after-effect of this process
remains, viz., an image of the tree. This image has become associated
with my Self during my perception. My Self has become enriched; to
its content a new element has been added. This element I call my idea
of the tree. I should never have occasion to talk of ideas, were I
not aware of my own Self. Percepts would come and go; I should let
them slip by. It is only because I am aware of my Self, and observe
that with each perception the content of the Self is changed, that I
am compelled to connect the perception of the object with the changes
in the content of my Self, and to speak of having an idea.
That I
have ideas is in the same sense matter of observation to me as that
other objects have colour, sound, etc. I am now also able to
distinguish these other objects, which stand over against me, by the
name of the outer world, whereas the contents of my perception of my
Self form my inner world. The failure to recognize the true relation
between idea and object has led to the greatest misunderstandings in
modern philosophy. The fact that I perceive a change in myself, that
my Self undergoes a modification, has been thrust into the
foreground, whilst the object which causes these modifications is
altogether ignored. In consequence it has been said that we perceive
not objects, but only our ideas. l know, so it is said, nothing of
the table in itself, which is the object of my perception, but only
of the changes which occur within me when I perceive a table. This
theory should not be confused with the Berkeleyan theory mentioned
above. Berkeley maintains the subjective nature of my perceptual
contents, but he does not say that I can know only my own ideas. He
limits my knowledge to my ideas because, on his view, there are no
objects other than ideas. What I perceive as a table no longer
exists, according to Berkeley, when I cease to look at it. This is
why Berkeley holds that our percepts are created directly by the
omnipotence of God. I see a table because God causes this percept in
me. For Berkeley, therefore, nothing is real except God and human
spirits. What we call the “world” exists only in spirits.
What the naïve man calls the outer world, or material nature, is
for Berkeley non-existent. This theory is confronted by the now
predominant Kantian view which limits our knowledge of the world to
our ideas, not because of any conviction that nothing beyond these
ideas exists, but because it holds that we are so organized that we
can have knowledge only of the changes within our own selves, not of
the things-in-themselves, which are the causes of these changes. This
view concludes from the fact that I know only my own ideas, not that
there is no reality independent of them, but only that the subject
cannot have direct knowledge of such reality. The mind can merely
“through the medium of its subjective thoughts imagine it,
conceive it, know it, or perhaps also fail to know it”
(O. Liebmann,
Zur Analysis der Wirklichkeit,
p. 28).
Kantians believe that their
principles are absolutely certain, indeed immediately evident,
without any proof. “The most fundamental principle which the
philosopher must begin by grasping clearly, consists in the
recognition that our knowledge, in the first instance, does not
extend beyond our ideas. Our ideas are all that we immediately have
and experience, and just because we have immediate experience of them
the most radical doubt cannot rob us of this knowledge. On the other
hand, the knowledge which transcends my ideas — taking ideas
here in the widest possible sense, so as to include all psychical
processes — is not proof against doubt. Hence, at the very
beginning of all philosophy we must explicitly set down all knowledge
which transcends ideas as open to doubt.” These are the opening
sentences of Volkelt's book on
Kant's Theory of Knowledge.
What is here put forward as an immediate and self-evident truth is,
in reality, the conclusion of a piece of argument which runs as
follows. Naïve common sense believes that things, just as we
perceive them, exist also outside our minds. Physics, Physiology, and
Psychology, however, teach us that our percepts are dependent on our
organization, and that therefore we cannot know anything about
external objects except what our organization transmits to us. The
objects which we perceive are thus modifications of our organization,
not things-in-themselves. This line of thought has, in fact, been
characterized by Ed. von Hartmann as the one which leads necessarily
to the conviction that we can have direct knowledge only of our own
ideas (cp. his
Grundproblem der Erkenntnistheorie,
pp. I 6–40).
Because outside our
organisms we find vibrations of particles and of air, which are
perceived by us as sounds, it is concluded that what we call sound is
nothing more than a subjective reaction of our organisms to these
motions in the external world. Similarly, colour and heat are
inferred to be merely modifications of our organisms. And, further,
these two kinds of percepts are held to be the effects of motions in
an infinitely fine material, ether, which fills all interstellar
space. When the vibrations of this ether stimulate the nerves in the
skin of my body, I perceive heat; when they stimulate the optical
nerve I perceive light and colour. Light, colour, and heat, then, are
the reactions of my sensory nerves to external stimuli. Similarly,
the sense of touch reveals to me, not the objects of the outer world,
but only states of my own body. The physicist holds that bodies are
composed of infinitely small particles called molecules, and that
these molecules are not in direct contact with one another, but have
definite intervals between them. Between them, therefore, is empty
space. Across this space they act on one another by attraction and
repulsion. If I put my hand on a body, the molecules of my hand by no
means touch those of the body directly, but there remains a certain
distance between body and hand, and what I experience as the body's
resistance is nothing but the effect of the force of repulsion which
its molecules exert on my hand. I am absolutely external to the body
and experience only its effects on my organism.
The
theory of the so-called Specific Nervous Energy, which has been
advanced by J. Müller, supplements these speculations. It
asserts that each sense has the peculiarity that it reacts to all
external stimuli in only one definite way. If the optic nerve is
stimulated, light sensations result, irrespective of whether the
stimulation is due to what we call light, or to mechanical pressure,
or an electrical current. On the other hand, the same external
stimulus applied to different senses gives rise to different
sensations. The conclusion from these facts seems to be, that our
sense-organs can give us knowledge only of what occurs in themselves,
but not of the external world. They determine our percepts, each
according to its own nature.
Physiology shows, further, that there can be no direct knowledge even
of the effects which objects produce on our sense-organs. Through his
study of the processes which occur in our own bodies, the
physiologist finds that, even in the sense-organs, the effects of the
eternal process are modified in the most diverse ways. We can see
this most clearly in the case of eye and ear. Both are very
complicated organs which modify the external stimulus considerably,
before they conduct it to the corresponding nerve. From the
peripheral end of the nerve the modified stimulus is then conducted
to the brain. Here the central organs must in turn be stimulated. The
conclusion is, therefore, drawn that the external process undergoes a
series of transformations before it reaches consciousness. The brain
processes are connected by so many intermediate links with the
external stimuli, that any similarity between them is out of the
question. What the brain ultimately transmits to the soul is neither
external processes, nor processes in the sense-organs, but only such
as occur in the brain. But even these are not apprehended immediately
by the soul. What we finally have in consciousness are not brain
processes at all, but sensations. My sensation of red has absolutely
no similarity with the process which occurs in the brain when I sense
red. The sensation, again, occurs as an effect in the mind, and the
brain process is only its cause. This is why Hartmann
(Grundproblem der Erkenntnistheorie,
p. 37)
says, “What the subject
experiences is therefore only modifications of his own psychical
states and nothing else.” However, when I have sensations, they
are very far as yet from being grouped in those complexes which I
perceive as “things.” Only single sensations can be
transmitted to me by the brain. The sensations of hardness and
softness are transmitted to me by the organ of touch, those of colour
and light by the organ of sight. Yet all these are found united in
one object. This unification must, therefore, be brought about by the
soul itself; that is, the soul constructs things out of the separate
sensations which the brain conveys to it. My brain conveys to me
singly, and by widely different paths, the visual, tactual, and
auditory sensations which the soul then combines into the idea of a
trumpet. Thus, what is really the result of a process (i.e.,
the idea of a trumpet), is for my consciousness the primary datum. In
this result nothing can any longer be found of what exists outside of
me and originally stimulated my sense-organs. The external object is
lost entirely on the way to the brain and through the brain to the
soul.
It would
be hard to find in the history of human speculation another edifice
of thought which has been built up with greater ingenuity, and which
yet, on closer analysis, collapses into nothing. Let us look a little
closer at the way it has been constructed. The theory starts with
what is given in naïve consciousness, i.e., with things
as perceived. It proceeds to show that none of the qualities which we
find in these things would exist for us, had we no sense-organs. No
eye — no colour. Therefore, the colour is not, as yet, present
in the stimulus which affects the eye. It arises first through the
interaction of the eye and the object. The latter is, therefore,
colourless. But neither is the colour in the eye, for in the eye
there is only a chemical, or physical, process which is first
conducted by the optic nerve to the brain, and there initiates
another process. Even this is not yet the colour. That is only
produced in the soul by means of the brain process. Even then it does
not yet appear in consciousness, but is first referred by the soul to
a body in the external world. There I finally perceive it, as a
quality of this body. We have travelled in a complete circle. We are
conscious of a coloured object. That is the starting-point. Here
thought begins its construction. If I had no eye the object would be,
for me, colourless. I cannot, therefore, attribute the colour to the
object. I must look for it elsewhere. I look for it, first, in the
eye — in vain; in the nerve — in vain; in the brain
— in vain once more; in the soul — here I find it indeed,
but not attached to the object. I recover the coloured body only on
returning to my starting-point. The circle is completed. The theory
leads me to identify what the naïve man regards as existing
outside of him, as really a product of my mind.
As long
as one stops here everything seems to fit beautifully. But we must go
over the argument once more from the beginning. Hitherto I have used,
as my starting-point, the object, i.e., the external percept
of which up to now, from my naïve standpoint, I had a totally
wrong conception. I thought that the percept, just as I perceive it,
had objective existence. But now I observe that it disappears with my
act of perception, that it is only a modification of my mental state.
Have I, then, any right at all to start from it in my arguments? Can
I say of it that it acts on my soul? I must henceforth treat the
table of which formerly I believed that it acted on me, and produced
an idea of itself in me, as itself an idea. But from this it follows
logically that my sense-organs, and the processes in them are also
merely subjective. I have no right to talk of a real eye but only of
my idea of an eye. Exactly the same is true of the nerve paths, and
the brain processes, and even of the process in the soul itself,
through which things are supposed to be constructed out of the chaos
of diverse sensations. If assuming the truth of the first circle of
argumentation, I run through the steps of my cognitive activity once
more, the latter reveals itself as a tissue of ideas which, as such,
cannot act on one another. I cannot say my idea of the object acts on
my idea of the eye, and that from this interaction results my idea of
colour. But it is necessary that I should say this. For as soon as I
see clearly that my sense-organs and their activity, my nerve- and
soul-processes, can also be known to me only through perception, the
argument which I have outlined reveals itself in its full absurdity.
It is quite true that I can have no percept without the corresponding
sense-organ. But just as little can I be aware of a sense-organ
without perception. From the percept of a table I can pass to the eye
which sees it, or the nerves in the skin which touches it, but what
takes place in these I can, in turn, learn only from perception. And
then I soon perceive that there is no trace of similarity between the
process which takes place in the eye and the colour which I see. I
cannot get rid of colour sensations by pointing to the process which
takes place in the eye whilst I perceive a colour. No more can I
re-discover the colour in the nerve- or brain-processes. I only add a
new percept, localized within the organism, to the first percept
which the naïve man localizes outside of his organism. I only
pass from one percept to another.
Moreover,
there is a break in the whole argument. I can follow the processes in
my organism up to those in my brain, even though my assumptions
become more and more hypothetical as I approach the central processes
of the brain. The method of external observation ceases with the
process in my brain, more particularly with the process which I
should observe, if I could treat the brain with the instruments and
methods of Physics and Chemistry. The method of internal observation,
or introspection, begins with the sensations, and includes the
construction of things out of the material of sense-data. At the
point of transition from brain process to sensation, there is a break
in the sequence of observation.
The
theory which I have here described, and which calls itself Critical
Idealism, in contrast to the standpoint of naïve common sense
which it calls Naïve Realism, makes the mistake of
characterizing one group of percepts as ideas, whilst taking another
group in the very same sense as the Naïve Realism which it
apparently refutes. It establishes the ideal character of percepts by
accepting naïvely, as objectively valid facts, the percepts
connected with one's own body, and, in addition, it fails to see that
it confuses two spheres of observation, between which it can find no
connecting link.
Critical
Idealism can refute Naïve Realism only by itself assuming, in
naïve-realistic fashion, that one's own organism has objective
existence. As soon as the Idealist realizes that the percepts
connected with his own organism stand on exactly the same footing as
those which Naïve Realism assumes to have objective existence,
he can no longer use the former as a safe foundation for his theory.
He would, to be consistent, have to regard his own organism also as a
mere complex of ideas. But this removes the possibility of regarding
the content of the perceptual world as a product of the mind's
organization. One would have to assume that the idea
“colour” was only a modification of the idea
“eye.” So-called Critical Idealism can be established
only by borrowing the assumptions of Naïve Realism. The apparent
refutation of the latter is achieved only by uncritically accepting
its own assumptions as valid in another sphere.
This
much, then, is certain: Analyses within the world of percepts cannot
establish Critical Idealism, and, consequently, cannot strip percepts
of their objective character.
Still
less is it legitimate to represent the principle that “the
perceptual world is my idea” as self-evident and needing no
proof. Schopenhauer begins his chief work,
The World as Will and Idea,
with the words: “The world is my idea — This
is a truth which holds good for everything that lives and knows,
though man alone can bring it into reflective and abstract
consciousness. If he really does this, he has attained to
philosophical wisdom. It then becomes clear and certain to him that
what he knows is not a sun and an earth, but only an eye that sees a
sun, a hand that feels an earth; that the world which surrounds him
is there only in idea, i.e., only in relation to something
else, the consciousness which is himself. If any truth can be
asserted a priori, it is this: for it is the expression of
the most general form of all possible and thinkable experience, a
form which is more general than time, or space, or causality, for
they all presuppose it ...”
(The World as Will and Idea,
Book I, par. 1). This whole theory is wrecked by the fact
already mentioned above, that the eyes and the hand are just as much
percepts as the sun and the earth. Using Schopenhauer's vocabulary in
his own sense, one might maintain against him that my eye which sees
the sun, and my hand which feels the earth, are my ideas just like
the sun and the earth themselves. That, put in this way, the whole
theory cancels itself, is clear without further argument. For only my
real eye and my real hand, but not my ideas “eye” and
“hand,” could own the ideas “sun” and
“earth” as modifications.
Critical
Idealism is totally unable to gain an insight unto the relation of
percept to idea. It cannot make the separation, mentioned on p. 76,
between what happens to the percept in the process of perception and
what must be inherent in it prior to perception. We must therefore
attempt this problem in another way.
|