CHAPTER IX
THE IDEA OF FREEDOM
THE
concept “tree” is conditioned for our knowledge by the
percept “tree.” When faced with a determinate percept I
can select only one determinate concept from the general system of
concepts. The connection of concept and percept is mediately and
objectively determined by thinking in conformity with the percept.
The connection between a percept and its concept is recognized after
the act of perception, but the relevance of the one to the other is
determined by the thing itself.
The procedure is
different when we examine knowledge, or rather the relation of man to
the world which arises within knowledge. In the preceding chapters
the attempt has been made to show that an unprejudiced observation of
this relation is able to throw light on its nature. A correct
understanding of this observation leads to the insight that thinking
may be intuitively apprehended in its self-contained nature. Those
who find it necessary, for the explanation of thinking as such, to
invoke something else, e.g., physical brain-processes, or
unconscious spiritual-processes lying behind the conscious thinking
which they observe, fail to grasp the facts which an unprejudiced
observation of thinking yields. When we observe our thinking, we live
during the observation immediately within the essence of a spiritual,
self-sustaining activity. Indeed we may even affirm that if we want
to grasp the essential nature of Spirit in the form in which it
immediately presents itself to man, we need but look at our own
self-sustaining thinking.
For the study of
thinking two things coincide which elsewhere must always appear
apart, viz., concept and percept. If we fail to see this, we shall be
unable to regard the concepts which we have elaborated in response to
percepts as anything but shadowy copies of these percepts, and we
shall take the percepts as presenting to us reality as it really is.
We shall, further, build up for ourselves a metaphysical world after
the pattern of the perceived world. We shall, each according to his
habitual thought-pictures, call this world a world of atoms, or of
will, or of unconscious spirit, and so on. And we shall fail to
notice that all the time we have been doing nothing but erecting
hypothetically a metaphysical world modeled on our perceived world.
But if we clearly apprehend what thinking consists in, we shall
recognize that percepts present to us only a portion of reality, and
that the complementary portion which alone imparts to reality its
full character as real, is experienced by us in the permeation of
percepts by thinking. We shall regard that which enters into
consciousness as thinking, not as a shadowy copy of reality, but as a
self-sustaining spiritual essence. We shall be able to say of it,
that it is revealed to us in consciousness through intuition.
Intuition is the purely spiritual conscious experience of a purely
spiritual content. It is only through an intuition that we can grasp
the essence of thinking.
Only if one wins
through, by means of unprejudiced observation, to the recognition of
this truth of the intuitive essence of thinking will one succeed in
clearing the way for a conception of the psycho-physical organization
of man. One recognizes that this organization can produce no effect
whatever on the essential nature of thinking. At first sight this
seems to be contradicted by patent and obvious facts. For ordinary
experience, human thinking occurs only in connection with, and by
means of, such an organization. This dependence on psycho-physical
organization is so prominent that its true bearing can be
appreciated by us only if we recognize, that in the essential nature
of thinking this organization plays no part whatever. Once we
appreciate this, we can no longer fail to notice how peculiar is the
relation of human organization to thinking. For this organization
contributes nothing to the essential nature of thought, but recedes
whenever the activity of thinking appears. It suspends its own
activity, it yields ground. And the ground thus set free is occupied
by thinking. The essence which is active in thinking has a two-fold
function: first it restricts the human organization in its own
activity; next, it steps into the place of it. Yes, even the former,
the restriction of the physical organization, is an effect of the
activity of thinking, and more particularly that part of this
activity which prepares the manifestation of thinking. This explains
the sense in which thinking has its counterpart in the organization
of the body. Once we perceive this, we can no longer misapprehend the
significance for thinking of this physical counterpart. When we walk
over soft ground our feet leave impressions in the soil. We shall not
be tempted to say that the forces of the ground, from below, have
formed these footprints. We shall not attribute to these forces any
share in the production of the footprints. Just so, if without
prejudice we observe the essential nature of thinking, we shall not
attribute any share in that nature to the traces in the physical
organism which thinking produces in preparing its manifestation
through the body. [The way in
which the above view has influenced psychology, physiology, etc., in
various directions has been set forth by the author in works
published after this book. Here he is concerned only with
characterizing the results of an unbiased observation of thinking
itself.]
An important question,
however, emerges here. If the human organization has no part in the
essential nature of thinking, what is the function of this
organization within the whole nature of man? The effects of thinking
upon this organization have no bearing upon the essence of thinking,
but they have a bearing upon the origin of the I-consciousness,
through this thinking. Thinking, in its own character, contains the
real “I,” but it does not contain, as such, the
I-consciousness. To see this we have but to observe thinking with an
open mind. The “I” is to be found in thinking. The
“I-consciousness” arises through the traces which, in the
sense above explained, the activity of thinking impresses upon our
general consciousness. (The I-consciousness thus arises through the
bodily organization. This view must not, however, be taken to imply
that the I-consciousness, once it has arisen, remains dependent on
the bodily organization. Once arisen it is taken up into thinking and
shares henceforth the spiritual being of the latter.)
The “I-consciousness”
is built upon the human organization. The latter is the source of the
acts of will. Following out the direction of the preceding
exposition, we can gain insight into the connection of thinking,
conscious I, and act of will, only by studying first how an act of
will issues from the human organization. [The
passage from p. 111 down to this point was added, or rewritten for
the Revised Edition (1918).]
In a particular act of
will we must distinguish two factors: the motive and the spring of
action. The motive is a factor of the nature of concept or
representation; the spring of action is the factor in will which is
directly conditioned in the human organization. The conceptual
factor, or motive, is the momentary determining cause of an act of
will; the spring of action is the permanent determining factor in the
individual. The motive of an act of will may be a pure concept, or
else a concept with a definite relation to perception, i.e.,
a representation. General and individual concepts (representations)
become motives of will by influencing the human individual and
determining him to action in a particular direction. One and the same
concept however, or one and the same representation, influence
different individuals differently. They impel different men to
different actions. An act of will is, therefore, not merely the
outcome of the concept or the representation, but also of the
individual make-up of human beings. This individual make-up we will
call, following Eduard von Hartmann, the “characterological
disposition.” The manner in which concept and representation
act on the characterological disposition of a man gives to his life a
definite moral or ethical stamp. [Students
of modern science may care to turn at once to the Editor's Note on p.
135.]
The characterological
disposition is formed by the more or less permanent content of the
individual's life, that is, of the content of his representations and
feelings. Whether a representation which enters my mind at this
moment stimulates me to an act of will or not, depends on its
relation to the rest of my representations, and also to my peculiar
modes of feeling. The content of my representations in turn, is
conditioned by the sum total of those concepts which have, in the
course of my individual life, come in contact with percepts, that is,
have become representations. This sum, again, depends on my greater
or lesser capacity for intuition, and on the range of my
observations, that is, on the subjective and objective factors of my
experiences, on my inner nature (development) and place in life,
and on my environment. My life of feeling more especially determines
my characterological disposition. Whether I shall make a certain
representation or concept the motive for action will depend on
whether it gives me pleasure or pain.
These are the elements
which we have to consider in an act of will. The immediately present
representation or concept, which becomes the motive, determines the
aim or the purpose of my will; my characterological disposition
determines me to direct my activity towards this aim. The
representation of taking a walk in the next half-hour determines the
aim of my action. But this representation is raised to the level of a
motive only if it meets with a suitable characterological
disposition, that is, if during my past life I have formed the
representations of the wholesomeness of walking and the value of
health; and, further, if the representation of walking is accompanied
in me by a feeling of pleasure.
We must, therefore,
distinguish (1) the possible subjective dispositions which are likely
to turn given representations and concepts into motives, and (2) the
possible representations and concepts which are capable of so
influencing my characterological disposition that an act of will
results. The former are for morality the springs of action, the
latter its aims.
The springs of action
in the moral life can be discovered by finding out the elements of
which individual life is composed.
The first level of
individual life is that of perception, more particularly
sense-perception. This is the stage of our individual lives in which
a perceiving translates itself into will immediately, without the
intervention of either a feeling or a concept. The spring of action
here involved may be called simply instinct. Our lower, purely
animal, needs (hunger, sexual intercourse, etc.), find their
satisfaction in this way. The main characteristic of instinctive
life is the immediacy with which the percept releases the act of
will. This kind of determination of the will, which belongs
originally only to the life of the lower senses, may, however, become
extended also to the percepts of the higher senses. We may
react to the percept of a certain event in the external world without
reflecting on what we do, without any special feeling connecting
itself with the percept. We have examples of this especially
in our ordinary conventional intercourse. The spring of this kind of
action is called tact or moral good taste. The more often such
immediate reactions to a percept occur, the more the agent
will prove himself able to act purely under the guidance of tact;
that is, tact becomes his characterological disposition.
The second level of
human life is feeling. Definite feelings accompany the percepts of
the external world. These feelings may become springs of action. When
I see a hungry man, my pity for him may become the spring of my
action. Such feelings, for example, are shame, pride, sense of
honour, humility, remorse, pity, revenge, gratitude, piety, loyalty,
love, and duty. [A complete
catalogue of the principles of morality (from the point of view of
Metaphysical Realism) may be found in Eduard von Hartmann's
Phaenomenologie des sittlichen Bewusstseins.]
The third and last
level of life is to think and to form representations. A
representation or a concept may become the motive of an action
through mere reflection. Representations become motives because,
in the course of my life, I regularly connect certain aims of my will
with percepts which recur again and again in a more or less modified
form. Hence it is that with men who are not wholly without
experience, the occurrence of certain percepts is always accompanied
also by the consciousness of representations of actions, which
they have themselves carried out in a similar case or which they have
seen others carry out. These representations float before their minds
as determining models in all subsequent decisions; they become parts
of their characterological disposition. We may give the name of
practical experience to the spring of action just described.
Practical experience merges gradually into purely tactful behaviour.
That happens, when definite typical pictures of actions have become
so closely connected in our minds with representations of certain
situations in life, that, in any given instance, we omit all
deliberation based on experience and pass immediately from the
percept to the action.
The highest level of
individual life is that of conceptual thinking without reference to
any definite perceptual content. We determine the content of a
concept through pure intuition from the ideal sphere. Such a concept
contains, at first, no reference to any definite percepts. When an
act of will comes about under the influence of a concept which refers
to a percept, i.e., under the influence of a representation,
then it is this percept which determines our action indirectly by way
of the conceptual thinking. But when we act under the influence of
intuitions, the spring of our action is pure thinking. As it is the
custom in philosophy to call the faculty of pure thinking “reason,”
we may perhaps be justified in giving the name of practical reason to
the moral spring of action characteristic of this level of life. The
clearest account of this spring of action has been given by
Kreyenbuehl (Philosophische Monatshefte, Vol. xviii, No. 3).
[Ethical-Spiritual Activity in Kant — e.Ed.]
In my opinion his article on this subject is one of the most
important contributions to present-day philosophy, more especially to
Ethics. Kreyenbuehl calls the spring of action, of which
we are treating, the practical a priori, i.e., a spring of
action issuing immediately from my intuition.
It is clear that such a
spring of action can no longer be counted in the strictest sense as a
characterological disposition. For what is here effective in me as a
spring of action is no longer something purely individual, but the
ideal, and hence universal, content of my intuition. As soon as I
regard the validity of this content as the basis and starting-point
of an action, I pass over into willing, irrespective of whether the
concept was already in me beforehand, or whether it only enters my
consciousness immediately before the action, that is, irrespective of
whether it was present in the form of a disposition in me or
not.
A real act of will
results only when a present impulse to action, in the form of a
concept or representation, acts on the characterological disposition.
Such an impulse thereupon becomes the motive of the will.
The motives of moral
conduct are representations and concepts. There are Moralists who see
in feeling also a motive of morality; they assert, e.g., that
the aim of moral conduct is to secure the greatest possible quantity
of pleasure for the acting individual. Pleasure itself, however,
cannot become a motive; only its representation can. The
representation of a future feeling, but not the feeling itself, can
act on my characterological disposition. For the feeling does not yet
exist in the moment of action; it has first to be produced by
the action.
The representation of
one's own or another's well-being is, however, rightly regarded as a
motive of the will. The principle of producing the greatest quantity
of pleasure for oneself through one's action, that is, to attain
individual happiness, is called Egoism. The attainment of this
individual happiness is sought either by thinking ruthlessly only of
one's own good, and striving to attain it even at the cost of the
happiness of other individuals (Pure Egoism), or by promoting the
good of others, either because one anticipates indirectly a
favourable influence on one's own person through the happiness of
others, or because one fears to endanger one's own interest by
injuring others (Morality of Prudence). The special content of the
egoistical principles of morality will depend on the representations
which we form of what constitutes our own, or others', happiness. A
man will determine the content of his egoistical striving in
accordance with what he regards as one of life's good things (luxury,
hope of happiness, deliverance from different evils, etc.).
Further, the purely
conceptual content of an action is to be regarded as yet
another kind of motive. This content has no reference, like the
representation of one's own pleasures, solely to the particular
action, but to the deduction of an action from a system of moral
principles. These moral principles, in the form of abstract concepts,
may guide the individual's moral life without his worrying himself
about the origin of his concepts. In that case, we feel merely the
moral necessity of submitting to a moral concept which, in the form
of law, overhangs our actions. The justification of this necessity we
leave to those who demand from us moral subjection, that is, to those
whose moral authority over us we acknowledge (the head of the family,
the state, social custom, the authority of the church, divine
revelation). We meet with a special kind of these moral principles
when the law is not proclaimed to us by an external authority, but
comes from our own inner life (moral autonomy). In this case we hear
the voice, to which we have to submit ourselves, in our own souls.
This voice expresses itself as conscience.
It is a great moral
advance when a man no longer takes as the motive of his action the
commands of an external or the internal authority, but tries to
understand the reason why a given maxim of action ought to be
effective as a motive in him. This is the advance from morality based
on authority to action from moral insight. At this level of morality,
a man will try to discover the demands of the moral life, and will
let his action be determined by this knowledge. Such demands are (1)
the greatest possible happiness of humanity as a whole purely for its
own sake; (2) the progress of civilization, or the moral development
of mankind towards ever greater perfection; (3) the realization of
individual moral aims conceived by an act of pure intuition.
The greatest possible
happiness of humanity as a whole will naturally be differently
conceived by different people. The above-mentioned maxim does not
refer to any definite representation of this happiness, but rather
means that everyone who acknowledges this principle strives to do all
that, in his opinion, most promotes the good of the whole of
humanity.
The progress of
civilization is seen to be a special application of the moral
principle just mentioned, at any rate for those to whom the goods
which civilization produces bring feelings of pleasure. They will
only have to pay the price in the decay and annihilation of several
things which also contribute to the happiness of humanity. It is,
however, also possible that some men look upon the progress of
civilization as a moral necessity, quite apart from the feelings of
pleasure which it brings. If so, the progress of civilization will be
a new moral principle for them, different from the previous one.
Both the principle of
the public good, and that of the progress of civilization alike, are
based on the representation, i.e., on the way in which we
apply the content of our moral Ideas to particular experiences
(percepts). The highest principle of morality which we can think of,
however, is that which contains, to start with, no such reference to
particular experiences, but which springs from the source of pure
intuition and does not seek until later any connection with percepts,
i.e., with life. The determination of what ought to be willed
issues here from an arbiter very different from that of the previous
two principles. Who accepts the principle of the public good will in
all his actions ask first what his ideals contribute to this public
good. The upholder of the progress of civilization as the principle
of morality will act similarly. There is, however, a still higher
mode of conduct which, in a given case, does not start from any
single limited moral ideal, but which sees a certain value in all
moral principles, always asking whether this or that principle is
more important in a particular case. It may happen that a man
considers in certain circumstances the promotion of the public good,
in others that of the progress of civilization, and in yet others the
furthering of his own good, to be the right course, and makes that
the motive of his action. But when all other grounds of determination
take second place, then we rely, in the first place, on conceptual
intuition itself. All other motives now yield place, and the ideal
content of an action alone becomes its motive.
Among the levels of
characterological disposition, we have singled out as the highest
that which manifests itself as pure thinking, or practical reason.
Among the motives, we have just singled out conceptual intuition as
the highest. On nearer consideration, we now perceive that at this
level of morality the spring of action and the motive coincide, i.e.,
that neither a predetermined characterological disposition, nor an
external moral principle accepted on authority, influences our
conduct. The action, therefore, is neither a merely stereotyped one
which follows certain rules, nor is it automatically performed in
response to an external impulse. Rather it is determined solely
through its ideal content. [Cf.
Editor's Note on p. 135.]
For such an action to
be possible, we must first be capable of moral intuitions. Whoever
lacks the capacity to experience for himself the moral principle that
applies in each particular case, will never rise to the level of
genuine individual willing.
Kant's principle of
morality: Act so that the principle of your action may be valid for
all men — is the exact opposite of ours. His principle would
mean death to all individual impulses of action. The norm for me can
never be what all men would do, but rather what it is right for me to
do in each special case.
A superficial criticism
might urge against these arguments: How can an action be
individually adapted to the special case and the special situation,
and yet at the same time be ideally determined by pure intuition?
This objection rests upon a confusion of the moral motive with the
perceptual content of an action. The latter, indeed, may be a motive,
and is actually a motive when we act for the progress of culture, or
from pure egoism, etc., but in action based on pure moral intuition
it never is a motive. Of course, my “I” takes notice of
these perceptual contents, but it does not allow itself to be
determined by them. The content is used only to construct a cognitive
concept, but the corresponding moral concept is not derived from the
object. The cognitive concept of a given situation which faces me, is
a moral concept also only if I adopt the standpoint of a particular
moral principle. If I base all my conduct on the principle of the
progress of civilization, then my way through life is tied down to a
fixed route. From every occurrence which I perceive and which
attracts my interest there springs a moral duty, viz., to do my tiny
share towards using this occurrence in the service of the progress of
civilization. In addition to the concept which reveals to me the
connections of events or objects according to the laws of
nature, there is also a moral label attached to them which contains
for me, as a moral agent, ethical directions as to how I have to
conduct myself. Such a moral label is justified on its own ground; at
a higher level it coincides with the Idea which reveals itself to
me prompted by the concrete instance.
Men vary greatly in
their capacity for intuition. In some, Ideas bubble up
like a spring, others acquire them with much labour. The situations
in which men live, and which are the scenes of their actions, are no
less widely different. The conduct of a man will depend, therefore,
on the manner in which his faculty of intuition works in a
given situation. The aggregate of Ideas which are effective in us,
the concrete content of our intuitions, constitute that which is
individual in each of us, notwithstanding the universal character of
the world of Ideas. In so far as this intuitive content has reference
to action, it constitutes the moral content of the individual. To let
this content express itself in his life is the highest moral spring
of action and at the same time, the highest motive of the man who
regards all other moral principles as subordinate. We may call this
point of view Ethical Individualism.
The decisive factor of
an intuitively determined action in any concrete instance, is the
discovery of the corresponding purely individual intuition. At
this level of morality, there can be no question of general moral
concepts (norms, laws), except in so far as these result from the
generalization of the individual impulses. General norms always
presuppose concrete facts from which they can be deduced. But
facts have first to be created by human action.
When we investigate the
leading principles (the conceptual principles guiding the actions of
individuals, peoples, epochs), we obtain a science of Ethics which
is, however, not a science of moral norms, but rather a natural
science of morality. Only, the laws discovered in this way are
related to human action as the laws of nature are related to a
particular phenomenon. These laws, however, are very far from being
identical with the impulses on which we base our actions. If we want
to understand how a man's action arises from his moral will, we must
first study the relation of this will to the action. For this purpose
we must single out for study those actions in which this relation is
the determining factor. When I, or another, subsequently review my
action we may discover what moral principles come into play in it. So
long as I am acting, I am influenced by the principle of morality in
so far as it lives in me intuitively; it is united with my love for
the object which I want to realize through my action. I ask of no man
and of no moral code, whether I shall perform this action or not. I
carry it out as soon as I have formed the Idea of it. This alone
makes it my action. If a man acts only because he accepts
certain moral norms, his action is the outcome of the principles
which compose his moral code. He merely carries out orders. He is a
superior kind of automaton. Inject some stimulus to action into his
mind, and at once the clockwork of his moral principles will begin to
work and run its prescribed course, so as to issue in an action which
is Christian, or humane, or seemingly unselfish, or calculated to
promote the progress of culture. It is only when I follow solely my
love for the object, that it is I, myself, who act. At this level of
morality, I acknowledge no lord over me, neither an external
authority, nor my so-called inner voice. I acknowledge no external
principle of my action, because I have found in myself the ground for
my action, viz., my love of the action. I do not examine with my
intellect whether my action is good or bad; I perform it, because I
am in love with it. My action is “good” when my
intuition, immersed in love, inserts itself in the right way into the
world-nexus as I experience it intuitively; it is “bad”
when this is not the case. Neither do I ask myself how another man
would act in my position. I act as I, this unique individuality, feel
impelled to act. No general usage, no common custom, no general maxim
current among men, no moral norm is my immediate guide, but my love
for the action. I feel no compulsion, neither the compulsion
of nature which dominates me through my instincts, nor the compulsion
of the moral commandments. My will is simply to realize what in me
lies.
Those who defend
general moral norms will reply to these arguments that, if
everyone strives to live his own life and do what he pleases, there
can be no distinction between a good action and a crime; every
fraudulent impulse in me has the same right to issue in action as the
intention to serve the general good. It is not the mere fact of my
having conceived the Idea of an action which ought to determine me as
a moral being, but the examination of whether it is a good or an evil
action. Only if it is good shall I carry it out.
This objection is
easily intelligible, and yet it had its root in what is but a
misapprehension of my meaning. My reply to it is this: If we want to
get at the essence of human volition we must distinguish between the
path along which volition attains to a certain degree of
development, and the unique character which volition assumes as
it approaches its goal. It is on the path towards the goal that the
norms play a legitimate part. The goal consists of the realization of
moral aims which are apprehended by pure intuition. Man attains such
aims in proportion as he is able to rise at all to the level at which
intuition grasps the Idea-content of the world. In any
particular volition, other elements will, as a rule, be mixed up, as
springs of action or motives, with such moral aims. But, for all
that, intuition may be, wholly or in part, the determining factor in
human volition. What one should do, that one does. One supplies the
stage upon which, what one should do, becomes action. One's own
action is what one lets come forth from oneself. The impulse, here,
can only be wholly individual. And, in fact, only an action which
issues out of intuition can be individual. To regard evil, the deed
of a criminal, as a manifestation of the human individuality in the
same sense as the embodiment of pure intuition, is a confusion which
only becomes possible when blind instincts are reckoned as part of
the human individuality.
But the blind impulse
which drives a man to a criminal act does not spring from intuition,
and does not belong to what is individual in him, but rather to that
which is most general in him, to that which is equally present in all
individuals and from which man finds his way out with the help of his
individual part. The individual part in me is not my organism with
its instincts and feelings, but rather the unified world of Ideas
which reveals itself through this organism. My instincts, cravings,
passions, justify no further assertion about me than that I belong to
the general species man. The fact that something ideal expresses
itself in a particular way through these instincts, passions, and
feelings, provides the foundation of my individuality. My instincts
and cravings make me the sort of man of whom there are twelve to the
dozen. The unique character of the Idea, by means of which I
distinguish myself within the dozen as “I,” makes of me
an individual. Only a being other than myself could distinguish me
from others by the difference in my animal nature. Through my
thinking, i.e., by the active grasping of the Ideal-element
working itself out through my organism, I distinguish myself from
others. Hence it is impossible to say of the action of a criminal
that it issues from the Idea within him. Indeed, the characteristic
feature of criminal actions is precisely that they spring from the
non-ideal elements in man.
An act the grounds for
which lie in the ideal part of my individual nature is felt to be
free. Every other part of an act, whether done under the compulsion
of nature or under the obligation imposed by a moral norm, is felt to
be unfree.
Man is free in so far
as, in every moment of his life, he is able to obey only
himself. A moral act is my act only when it can be called free in
this sense. So far we are concerned here with the presuppositions
under which an act of will is felt to be free; the sequel will show
how this purely ethical Idea of freedom becomes realized in the
essential nature of man.
Action on the basis of
freedom does not at all exclude, but includes, the moral laws. Only,
it shows that it stands on a higher level than actions which are
dictated by these laws. Why should my act serve the general good less
well when I do it from pure love of it, than when I perform it only
because I feel it is a duty to serve the general good? The concept of
mere duty excludes freedom, because it will not acknowledge the
individual element, but demands the subjection of the latter to a
general norm. Freedom of action is conceivable only from the
standpoint of Ethical Individualism.
But how about the
possibility, of social life for men, if each aims only at asserting
his own individuality? This question expresses yet another objection
on the part of Moralism wrongly understood. The Moralist believes
that a social community is possible only if all men are held together
by a commonly fixed moral order. This shows that the Moralist does
not understand the identity of the world of Ideas. He does not grasp
that the world of Ideas which inspires me is no other than that which
inspires my fellow-man. This unity is, indeed, but a result of the
experience of the world. It cannot be anything else. For if we could
recognize it in any other way than by observation, it would follow
that not individual experience, but universal norms, were dominant in
its sphere. Individuality is possible only if every individual
being knows of others only through individual observation. I differ
from my neighbour, not at all because we are living in two entirely
different spiritual worlds, but because from our common world of
Ideas we receive different intuitions. He desires to live out his
intuitions, I mine. If we both draw our intuitions really from the
world of Ideas, and do not obey mere external impulses (physical or
spiritual), then we cannot but meet one another in striving for the
same aims, in having the same intentions. A moral misunderstanding,
a clash is impossible between men who are morally free. Only the
morally unfree who follow their natural instincts or the accepted
commands of duty, turn their backs on their neighbours, if these do
not obey the same instincts and the same laws as themselves. To live
in love of action and to let live in understanding of the other's
volition, this is the fundamental maxim of the free man. He knows no
other “ought” than that with which his will intuitively
puts itself in harmony. How he shall will in any given case, that
will be determined for him by his faculty of conceiving Ideas.
If sociability were not
deeply rooted in human nature, no external laws would be able to
inoculate us with it. It is only because human beings are one in
spirit that they can live out their lives side by side. The free man
lives out his life in the full confidence that all other free men
belong to one spiritual world with himself, and that their intentions
will harmonize with his. The free man does not demand accord from his
fellow-man, but he expects it none the less, because it is inherent
in human nature. I am not referring here to the necessity for this or
that external institution. I refer to the disposition, the attitude
of soul, through which a man, aware of himself among his fellow-men
for whom he cares, comes nearest to living up to the ideal of
human dignity.
There are many who will
say that the concept of the free man which I have here developed, is
a chimera nowhere to be found realized, and that we have got to deal
with actual human beings, from whom we can expect morality only if
they obey some moral law, i.e., if they regard their moral
task as a duty and do not simply follow their inclinations and
loves. I do not doubt this. Only a blind man could do that. But away
with all this hypocrisy of morality if this is the final conclusion!
Let us then say simply that human nature must be compelled to act as
long as it is not free. Whether the compulsion of man's unfree nature
is effected by physical force or through moral laws, whether man is
unfree because he indulges his unmeasured sexual desire, or because
he is bound tight in the bonds of conventional morality, is quite
immaterial from a certain point of view. Only let us not assert that
such a man can rightly call his actions his own, seeing that he is
driven to them by a force which is not his own. But in the midst of
all this network of compulsion, there arise free spirits who, in all
the welter of customs, legal codes, religious observances, etc.,
learn to find themselves. They are free in so far as they obey only
themselves; unfree in so far as they submit to control. Which of us
can say that he is really free in all his actions? Yet in each of us
there dwells some deeper being in which the free man finds
expression.
Our life is made up of
free and unfree actions. We cannot, however, form a
final concept of human nature without coming upon the free spirit as
its purest expression. After all, we are men in the fullest sense
only in so far as we are free.
This is an ideal, many
will say. Doubtless; but it is an ideal which is a real element in us
working its way to the surface of our nature. It is no ideal born of
mere imagination or dream, but one which has life, and which
announces itself clearly even in the least perfect form of its
existence. If men were nothing but beings of nature, the search for
ideals, that is, for Ideas which as yet are not actual but the
realization of which we demand, would be an impossibility. In dealing
with external objects the Idea is determined by the percept. We have
done our share when we have recognized the connection between Idea
and percept. But with the human being the case is different. The
content of his existence is not determined without him. His true
concept as a moral being (free spirit) is not a priori united
objectively with the percept-picture “man,” so that
knowledge need only register the fact subsequently. Man must by his
own act unite his concept with the percept “man.” Concept
and percept coincide with one another in this instance only in so far
as man himself makes them coincide. This he can do only if he has
found the concept of the free spirit, that is, if he has found his
own concept. In the objective world, a boundary-line is drawn by our
organization between percept and concept. Knowledge breaks down this
barrier. In our subjective nature this barrier is no less present.
Man overcomes it in the course of his development, by unfolding his
concept in his outward existence. Hence man's intellectual as well as
his moral life lead alike to his two-fold nature, perception
(immediate experience) and thinking. The intellectual life overcomes
his two-fold nature by means of knowledge, the moral life succeeds
through the actual realization of the free spirit. Every being has
its inborn concept (the law of its existence and action), but in
external objects this concept is indissolubly bound up with the
percept, and separated from it only in our spiritual organization. In
man concept and percept are, at first, actually separated, to be just
as actually reunited by him.
Someone might object
that to our percept of a man there corresponds at every moment of his
life a definite concept, just as with every other object. I can form
for myself the concept of an average man, and I may also find such a
man given to me as percept. Suppose now I add to this the
concept of a free spirit, then I have two concepts for the same
object.
Such an objection is
one-sided. As object of perception I am subject to perpetual
change. As a child I was one thing, another as a youth, yet another
as a man. Moreover, at every moment I am different, as a
percept-picture, from what I was the moment before. These changes may
take place in such a way that either it is always only the
same (average) man who exhibits himself in them, or that they
represent the expression of a free spirit. To such changes my action,
as object of perception, is subjected.
In the perceptual
object “man” there is given the possibility of
transformation, just as in the plant-seed there lies the possibility
of growth into a fully developed plant. The plant transforms itself
in growth, because of the objective law which is inherent in it. The
human being remains in his imperfected state, unless he takes hold of
the material for transformation within him and transforms himself
through his own force. Nature makes of man merely a natural being;
society makes of him a being who acts according to law; only he
himself can make a free man of himself. At a definite stage in his
development nature releases man from her fetters; society carries his
development a step farther; he alone can give himself the final
polish.
From the standpoint of
free morality, then, it is not asserted that the free spirit is the
only form in which a man can exist. The freedom of the spirit is
looked upon only as the last stage in man's evolution. This is not to
deny that conduct according to norms has its legitimate place as a
stage in development. The point is that we cannot acknowledge it to
be the absolute standpoint in morality. For the free spirit
transcends norms, in the sense that he recognizes as motives not
commands alone, but he regulates his conduct in accordance with his
impulses (intuitions).
When Kant apostrophizes
duty: “Duty! Thou sublime and mighty name, that dost embrace
nothing charming or insinuating, but requirest submission,”
thou that “holdest forth a law ... before which all
inclinations are dumb, even though they secretly counter-work it,”
[Translation by Abbott, Kant's
Theory of Ethics, p. 180; Critique of Practical Reason,
chap. iii.] then the free spirit replies: “Freedom! thou
kindly and humane name, which dost embrace within thyself all that is
morally most beloved, all that my manhood most prizes, and which
makest me the servant of nobody, which settest up no mere law, but
waitest what my moral love itself will recognize as law, because it
feels itself unfree in presence of every law that is forced upon it.”
This is the contrast
of morality according to law and according to
freedom.
The philistine who
looks upon an external code as embodied morality is sure to look upon
the free spirit even as a danger to society. But that is only because
his view is narrowly focused on a limited period of time. If he were
able to look beyond, he would soon find that the free spirit needs to
go beyond the laws of his state as seldom as the philistine himself,
and that he never needs to confront them with any real contradiction.
For the laws of the state, one and all, have had their origin in the
intuitions of free spirits, just like all other objective laws of
morality. There is no traditional law enforced by the authority of a
family, which was not, once upon a time, intuitively conceived and
laid down by an ancestor. Similarly the conventional laws of morality
are first of all established by particular men, and the laws of the
state are always born in the brain of a statesman. These free spirits
have set up laws over the rest of mankind, and only he is unfree who
forgets this origin and makes them either extra-human commands, or
objective moral duties independent of the human content, or —
falsely mystical — the compelling voice of his own conscience.
He, on the other hand,
who does not forget the origin of laws, but looks for it in man, will
respect them as belonging to the same world of Ideas which is the
source also of his own moral intuitions. If he thinks his intuitions
better than those already existing, he will try to put them into the
place of the latter. If he thinks the latter justified, he will act
in accordance with them as if they were his own intuitions.
We must not coin the
formula: Man exists only in order to realize a moral world-order
which is independent of him. Anyone who maintains that he does
stands, in his science of man, still at that same point at which
natural science stood when it believed that a bull has horns in order
that it may butt. Scientists, happily, have cast the concept of
objective purposes in nature into the limbo of dead theories. For
Ethics, it is more difficult to achieve the same emancipation. But
just as horns do not exist for the sake of butting, but butting
because of horns, so man does not exist for the sake of morality, but
morality exists through man. The free man acts morally because he has
a moral Idea, he does not act in order that morality may come into
being. Human individuals, with the moral Ideas belonging to their
nature, are the presupposition of a moral world-order.
The human individual is
the fountain of all morality and the centre of earthly life. State
and society exist only because they have necessarily grown out of the
life of individuals. That state and society, in turn, should react
upon the lives of individuals, is no more difficult to comprehend,
than that the butting which is the result of the existence of horns,
reacts in turn upon the further development of the horns of the bull,
which would become atrophied by prolonged disuse. Similarly, the
individual must degenerate if he leads an isolated existence outside
human society. That is just the reason why the social order arises,
viz., that it may react favourably upon the individual.
———————————
EDITOR'S NOTE
The
distinction here drawn by Dr. Steiner between “motive”
and “spring of action” is of fundamental importance and
is implicit in the common English usage of these terms. But because
this distinction has been blurred in recent scientific works the
word “motive” has come to have a different technical
usage which may confuse some readers of this book.
An example
of the psychological usage is R. Woodworth's definition of
“motive” as “a state or set of the individual which
disposes him for certain behaviour and for seeking certain goals.”
This does not bring out the important difference, to which Steiner
draws attention, between having a goal, purpose or task, which a man
finds by the characteristically human activity of thinking and adopts
as the right thing to do in the particular circumstances, and being
stimulated by a percept or feeling to an impulsive or emotional act.
Steiner uses the term “motive” only when the act of will
comes about under the influence of a concept or representation, and
he traces a progressive ascent in this direction to the point where
action is determined by the content of pure intuition.
An
instance of contemporary ethical usage is A. C. Ewing's alternative
definitions of “motive” as “(i) Desires causing
action or (ii) Circumstances relevant to an action to which attention
is directed at the time.” Here, also, recognition of the unique
character of a motive grasped out of pure intuition is precluded.
In the
first part of this book Dr. Steiner has shown how a concept can be
grasped by the Ego from the thought-content of the world in a fully
conscious act of intuition. In this chapter and the subsequent
discussion of moral imagination he shows how such a freely grasped
concept can be imprinted on the world as deed without losing the
element of freedom. Thus it is shown how the spirit can work
creatively in a human act of free will.
Upon the
recognition of this fact depends a clear understanding of the
essential difference between man, who can develop the power to create
freely out of the spirit, and the animal.
|