CHAPTER XIII
THE VALUE OF LIFE (OPTIMISM AND PESSIMISM)
A COUNTERPART
of the question concerning the purpose and
destination of life (cp. pp. 147 ff.) is the question concerning its
value. We meet here with two mutually opposed views, and between them
with all conceivable attempts at compromise. One view says that this
world is the best conceivable which could exist at all, and that to
live and act in it is a good of inestimable value. Everything
that exists displays harmonious and purposive co-operation and is
worthy of admiration. Even what is apparently bad and evil may, from
a higher point of view, be seen to be good, for it represents an
agreeable contrast with the good; we are the more able to appreciate
the good when it is clearly contrasted with evil. Moreover, evil is
not genuinely real: it is only that we perceive as evil a lesser
degree of good. Evil is the absence of good, it has no positive
import of its own.
The other view
maintains that life is full of misery and agony. Everywhere pain
outweighs pleasure, sorrow outweighs joy. Existence is a burden, and
non-existence would, from every point of view, be preferable to
existence.
The chief
representatives of the former view, i.e., Optimism, are
Shaftesbury and Leibnitz; the chief representatives of the second,
i.e., Pessimism, are Schopenhauer and Eduard von
Hartmann.
Leibnitz says the world
is the best of all possible worlds. A better one is impossible. For
God is good and wise.
A good God wills to
create the best possible world, a wise God knows which is the best
possible. He is able to distinguish the best from all other and worse
possibilities. Only an evil or an unwise God would be able to create
a world worse than the best possible.
Whoever starts from
this point of view will find it easy to lay down the direction which
human action must follow, in order to make its contribution to the
greatest good of the universe. All that man need do will be to find
out the counsels of God and to behave in accordance with them. If he
knows what God's purposes are concerning the world and mankind, he
will be able to do what is right. And he will be happy in the feeling
that he is adding his share to the other good in the world. From this
optimistic standpoint, then, life is worth living. It is such as to
stimulate us to interest and co-operation.
Quite different is the
picture Schopenhauer paints. He thinks of the foundation of the world
not as an all-wise and all-beneficent being, but as blind striving
or will. Eternal striving, ceaseless craving for satisfaction
which yet is ever beyond reach, this is the fundamental
characteristic of all will. For as soon as we have attained what
we want, a fresh need springs up, and so on. Satisfaction, when it
occurs, endures always only for an infinitesimal time. The
whole rest of our lives in unsatisfied craving, i.e.,
dissatisfaction and suffering. When at last blind craving is dulled,
every definite content is gone from our lives. Existence is filled
with nothing but an endless ennui. Hence the best we can do is to
throttle all desires and needs within us and exterminate the will.
Schopenhauer's Pessimism leads to complete inactivity; his moral
aim is universal idleness.
By a very different
argument von Hartmann attempts to establish Pessimism and to make use
of it for Ethics. He attempts, in keeping with the favourite trend of
our age, to base his world-view on experience. By observation of life
he hopes to discover whether there is more pain or more pleasure in
the world. He passes in review before the tribunal of reason whatever
men consider to be happiness and a good, in order to show that all
apparent satisfaction turns out, on closer inspection, to be nothing
but illusion. It is illusion when we believe that in health, youth,
freedom, sufficient income, love (sexual satisfaction), pity,
friendship and family life, honour, reputation, glory, power,
religious edification, pursuit of science and of art, hope of a life
after death, participation in the advancement of civilization, that
in all these we have sources of happiness and satisfaction.
Soberly considered, every enjoyment brings much more evil and misery
than pleasure into the world. The disagreeableness of “the
morning after” is always greater than the agreeableness of
intoxication. Pain far outweighs pleasure in the world. No man, even
though relatively the happiest, would, if asked, wish to live through
this miserable life a second time. Now, since Hartmann does not deny
the presence of an ideal factor (wisdom) in the world, but, on the
contrary, grants to it equal rights with blind striving (will), he
can attribute the creation of the world to his Absolute Being only on
condition that He makes the pain in the world subserve a
world-purpose that is wise. But the pain of created beings is nothing
but God's pain itself, for the life of the world as a whole is
identical with the life of God. An All-wise Being can aim only at
release from pain, and since all existence is pain, at release from
existence. Hence the purpose of the creation of the world is to
transform existence into the non-existence which is so much better.
The world-process is nothing but a continuous battle against God's
pain, a battle which ends with the annihilation of all existence. The
moral life for men, therefore, will consist in taking part in the
annihilation of existence. The reason why God has created the world
is that through the world He may free Himself from His infinite pain.
The world must be regarded, “as it were, as an itching eruption
on the Absolute,” by means of which the unconscious healing
power of the Absolute rids itself of an inward disease: or it may be
regarded “as a painful drawing-plaster which the All-One
applies to itself in order first to divert the inner pain outwards,
and then to get rid of it altogether.” Human beings are members
of the world. In their sufferings God suffers. He has created them in
order to split up in them His infinite pain. The pain which each one
of us suffers is but a drop in the infinite ocean of God's pain
(Hartmann, Phaenomenologie des sittlichen Bewusstseins, pp.
866 ff.).
It is man's duty to
permeate his whole being with the recognition that the pursuit of
individual satisfaction (egoism) is a folly, and that he ought to be
guided solely by the task of assisting in the redemption of God by
unselfish service of the world-process. Thus, in contrast with the
Pessimism of Schopenhauer, that of von Hartmann leads us to devoted
activity in a sublime cause.
But what of the claim
that this view is based on experience?
To strive after
satisfaction means that our activity reaches out beyond the actual
content of our lives. A creature is hungry, i.e., it
desires satiety, when its organic functions demand for their
continuation the supply of fresh means of life in the form of
nourishment. The pursuit of honour requires that a man does not
regard what he personally does or leaves undone as valuable unless it
is endorsed by the approval of others from without. The striving for
knowledge arises when a man is not content with the world which he
sees, hears, etc., so long as he has not understood it. The
fulfilment of the striving causes pleasure in the individual who
strives, failure causes pain. It is important here to observe that
pleasure and pain are attached only to the fulfilment or
non-fulfilment of my striving. The striving itself is by no means to
be regarded as a pain. Hence, if we find that, in the very moment in
which a striving is fulfilled, at once a new striving arises, this is
no ground for saying that pleasure had given birth to pain, because
enjoyment in every case gives rise to a desire for its repetition, or
for a fresh pleasure. I can speak of pain only when desire runs up
against the impossibility of fulfilment. Even when an enjoyment that
I have had causes in me the desire for the experience of a greater,
or more refined pleasure, I have no right to speak of this desire as
a pain caused by the previous pleasure until the means fail me to
gain the greater or more refined pleasure. I have no right to regard
pleasure as the cause of pain unless pain follows on pleasure as its
consequence by natural law, e.g., when a woman's sexual
pleasure is followed by the suffering of child-birth and the cares of
nursing. If striving by itself caused pain, then the removal of
striving ought to be accompanied by pleasure. But the very reverse is
true. To have no striving in one's life causes boredom, and boredom
is always bound up with displeasure. Now, since it may be a long time
before striving meets with fulfilment, and since, in the interval, it
is content with the hope of fulfilment, we must acknowledge that
there is no connection between pain and striving as such, but that
pain depends solely on the non-fulfilment of the striving.
Schopenhauer, then, is wrong, in any case, in regarding desire or
striving (will) as being in principle the source of pain.
In
truth, the very reverse of this is correct. Striving (desire) is in
itself pleasurable. Who does not know the pleasure which is caused by
the hope of a remote but intensely desired aim? This pleasure is the
companion of all labour, the results of which will be enjoyed by us
only in the future. It is a pleasure which is wholly independent of
the attainment of the end. For when the aim has been attained, the
pleasure of satisfaction is added as something new to the pleasure of
striving. If anyone were to argue that the pain caused by the
non-attainment of an aim is increased by the pain of disappointed
hope, and that thus, in the end, the pain of non-fulfilment will
eventually outweigh the possible pleasure of fulfilment, we shall
have to reply that the reverse may be the case, and that the
recollection of past pleasure at a time of unsatisfied desire will as
often mitigate the displeasure of non-satisfaction. Whoever at the
moment when his hopes suffer shipwreck exclaims, “I have done
my part,” proves thereby my assertion. The blessed feeling of
having willed the best within one's powers is ignored by all who make
every unsatisfied desire an occasion for asserting that, not only has
the pleasure of fulfilment been lost, but that the enjoyment of the
striving itself has been destroyed.
The satisfaction of a
desire causes pleasure and its non-satisfaction causes pain. But we
have no right to infer from this fact that pleasure is the
satisfaction of a desire, and pain its non-satisfaction. Both
pleasure and pain may be experienced without being the consequence of
desire. Illness is pain not preceded by any desire. If anyone were to
maintain that illness is unsatisfied desire for health, he would
commit the error of regarding the inevitable and unconscious wish not
to fall ill as a positive desire. When someone receives a legacy from
a rich relative of whose existence he had not the faintest idea, he
experiences a pleasure without having felt any preceding desire.
Hence, if we set out to
inquire whether the balance is on the side of pleasure or of pain, we
must allow in our calculation for the pleasure of striving, the
pleasure of the satisfaction of striving, and the pleasure which
comes to us without any striving whatever. On the debit side we shall
have to enter the displeasure of boredom, the displeasure of
unfulfilled striving, and, lastly, the displeasure which comes to us
without any striving on our part. Under .this last heading we shall
have to put also the displeasure caused by work that has been forced
upon us, not chosen by ourselves.
This leads us to the
question: What is the right method for striking the balance between
the credit and the debit columns? Eduard von Hartmann asserts that
reason holds the scales. It is true that he says (Philosophie des
Unbewussten, 7th edition, vol. ii, p. 290): “Pain and
pleasure exist only in so far as they are actually being felt.”
It follows that there can be no standard for pleasure other than the
subjective standard of feeling. I must feel whether the sum of my
disagreeable feelings, contrasted with my agreeable feelings, results
in me in a balance of pleasure or of pain. But,
notwithstanding this, von Hartmann maintains that “though the
value of the life of every being can be set down only according to
its own subjective measure, yet it follows by no means that every
being is able to compute the correct algebraic sum of all that
affects its life — or, in other words, that its total estimate
of its own life, with regard to its subjective feelings, should be
correct.” But this means that rational estimation of feelings
is reinstated as the standard of value. [Those
who want to settle by calculation whether the sum total of pleasure
or that of pain is bigger, ignore that they are subjecting to
calculation something which is nowhere experienced. Feeling does not
calculate, and what matters for the real valuing of life is what we
really experience, not what results from an imaginary calculation.]
Anyone who more or less
adopts this view of thinkers like Eduard von Hartmann may think it
necessary, in order to arrive at a correct valuation of life, to
clear out of the way those factors which falsify our judgment about
the balance of pleasure and of pain. He can try to do this in two
ways: first, by showing that our desire (instinct, will) operates as
a disturbing factor in the sober estimation of feeling-values, e.g.,
whereas we ought to judge that sexual enjoyment is a source of evil,
we are beguiled by the fact that the sexual instinct is very strong
in us into anticipating a pleasure which does not occur in the
alleged intensity at all. We are bent on indulging ourselves, hence
we do not confess to ourselves that the indulgence makes us suffer.
Secondly, von Hartmann subjects feelings to a criticism designed to
show that the objects to which our feelings attach themselves reveal
themselves as illusions when examined by reason, and that they are
destroyed from the moment that our constantly growing intelligence
sees through the illusions.
He, then, can conceive
the matter as follows. Suppose an ambitious man wants to determine
clearly whether, up to the moment of his inquiry, there has been a
surplus of pleasure or of pain in his life. He has to eliminate two
sources of error that may affect his judgment. Being ambitious, this
fundamental feature of his character will make him see the pleasures
of the public recognition of his achievements larger than they are,
and the offences suffered through rebuffs smaller than they are. At
the time when he suffered the rebuffs he felt the offences just
because he is ambitious, but in recollection they appear to him in a
milder light, whereas the pleasures of recognition to which he is so
much more susceptible leave a far deeper impression. Undeniably, it
is a real benefit to an ambitious man that it should be so. The
deception diminishes his pain in the moment of self-analysis. But,
none the less, his judgment is misled. The sufferings which he now
reviews as through a veil were actually experienced by him in all
their intensity. Hence he enters them at a wrong valuation on the
debit side of his life account. In order to arrive at a correct
estimate, an ambitious man would have to lay aside his ambition for
the time of his inquiry. He would have to review his past life
without any distorting glasses before his mind's eye, else he will
resemble a merchant who, in making up his books, enters among the
items on the credit side his own zeal in business.
But the holder of this
view can go even further. He can say the ambitious man must make
clear to himself that the public recognition which he craves is a
thing without value. By himself, or with the guidance of others, he
must attain the insight that rational beings cannot attach any value
to recognition by others, seeing that “in all matters which are
not vital questions of development, or which have not been definitely
settled by science,” it is always as certain as anything can be
“that the majority is wrong and the minority right.”
“Whoever makes ambition the lode-star of his life puts the
happiness of his life at the mercy of so fallible a judgment”
(Philosophie des Unbewussten, vol. ii, p. 332). If the
ambitious man acknowledges all this to himself, he is bound to regard
all the imaginary realities of his ambition as illusions, including
even the feelings which attach themselves to the illusions produced
by his ambition. This is the reason why it-could be said that we must
also strike out of the balance-sheet of our life-values whatever is
produced by illusions in our feelings of pleasure. What remains after
that represents the sum-total of pleasure in life deprived of
illusions, and this sum is so small compared with the sum-total of
pain that life is no enjoyment and non-existence preferable to
existence.
But whilst it is
immediately evident that the interference of the instinct of ambition
produces self-deception in striking the balance of pleasures and thus
leads to a false result, we must none the less challenge what is said
here concerning the illusory character of the objects to which
pleasure is attached. For the elimination, from the credit side of
life, of all pleasurable feelings which accompany actual or supposed
illusions would positively falsify the balance of pleasure and of
pain. An ambitious man has genuinely enjoyed the acclamations of the
multitude, irrespective of whether subsequently he himself, or some
other person, recognizes that this acclamation is an illusion. The
pleasure, once enjoyed, is not one whit diminished by such
recognitions. Consequently the elimination of all these “illusory”
feelings from life's balance, so far from making our judgment about
our feelings more correct, actually cancels out of life feelings
which were genuinely there.
And why are these
feelings to be eliminated? He who has them derives pleasure from
them; he who has overcome them, gains through the experience of
self-conquest (not through the vain emotion: What a noble fellow I
am! but through the objective sources of pleasure which lie in the
self-conquest) a pleasure which is, indeed, spiritualized, but none
the less valuable for that. If we strike feelings from the credit
side of pleasure in our account, on the ground that they are attached
to objects which turn out to have been illusory, we make the value of
life dependent, not on the quantity, but on the quality of pleasure,
and this, in turn, on the value of the objects which cause the
pleasure. But if I am to determine the value of life only by the
quantity of pleasure or pain which it brings, I have no right to
presuppose something else by which first to determine the positive or
negative value of pleasure. If I say I want to compare quantity of
pleasure and quantity of pain, in order to see which is greater, I am
bound to bring into my account all pleasures and pains in their
actual intensities, regardless of whether they are based on illusions
or not. If I credit a pleasure which rests on an illusion with a
lesser value for life than one which can justify itself before the
tribunal of reason, I make the value of life dependent on factors
other than mere quantity of pleasure.
Whoever puts down
pleasure as less valuable when it is attached to a worthless object,
is like a merchant who enters the considerable profits of a
toy-factory at only one-quarter of their real value on the ground
that the factory produces nothing but playthings for children.
If the point is simply
to weigh quantity of pleasure against quantity of pain, we ought to
leave the illusory character of the objects of some pleasures
entirely out of account.
The method, then, which
von Hartmann recommends, viz., rational consideration of the
quantities of pleasure and pain produced by life, has taught us so
far how we are to get the data for our calculation, i.e., what
we are to put down on the one side of our account and what on the
other. But how are we to make the actual calculation? Is reason able
also to strike the balance?
A merchant has made a
miscalculation when the gain calculated by him does not agree with
the profits which he has demonstrably enjoyed from his business or is
still expecting to enjoy. Similarly, the philosopher will undoubtedly
have made a mistake in his estimate, if he cannot demonstrate in
actual feeling the surplus of pleasure or, as the case may be, of
pain which his manipulation of the account has yielded.
For the present I shall
not criticize the calculations of those Pessimists who support their
estimate of the value of the world by an appeal to reason. But if we
are to decide whether to carry on the business of life or not, we
shall demand first to be shown where the alleged surplus of pain is
to be found.
Here we touch the point
where reason is not in a position by itself to determine the surplus
of pleasure or of pain, but where it must demonstrate this surplus in
life as percept. For man reaches reality not through concepts by
themselves, but through the interpenetration of concepts and percepts
(and feelings are percepts) which thinking brings about (cp. pp. 78
ff.). A merchant will give up his business only when the loss of
goods, as calculated with his accountant, is actually confirmed by
the facts. If the facts do not bear out the calculation, he asks his
accountant to check the account once more. That is exactly what a man
will do in the business of life. If a philosopher wants to prove to
him that the pain is far greater than the pleasure, but that he does
not feel it so, then he will reply: “You have made a mistake in
your theorizings: repeat your analysis once more.” But if there
comes a time in a business when the losses are really so great that
the firms' credit no longer suffices to satisfy the creditors,
bankruptcy results, even though the merchant may avoid keeping
himself informed by careful accounts about the state of his affairs.
Similarly, supposing the quantity of pain in a man's life became at
any time so great that no hope (credit) of future pleasure could help
him to get over the pain, the bankruptcy of life's business would
inevitably follow.
Now the number of those
who commit suicide is relatively small compared with the number of
those who live bravely on. Only very few men give up the business of
life because of the pain involved. What follows? Either that it is
untrue to say that the quantity of pain is greater than the quantity
of pleasure, or that we do not make the continuation of life
dependent on the quantity of felt pleasure or pain.
In a very curious way,
Eduard von Hartmann's Pessimism, having concluded that life is
valueless because it contains a surplus of pain, yet affirms the
necessity of going on with life. This necessity lies in the
fact that the world-purpose mentioned above (p. 167) can be achieved
only by the ceaseless, devoted labour of human beings. But so long as
men still pursue their egotistical appetites they are unfit for this
devoted labour. It is not until experience and reason have
convinced them that the pleasures which egoism pursues are incapable
of attainment, that they give themselves up to their proper task. In
this way the pessimistic conviction is offered as the fountain of
unselfishness. An education based on Pessimism is to
exterminate Egoism by convincing it of the hopelessness of achieving
its aims.
According to this view,
then, the striving for pleasure is fundamentally inherent in human
nature. It is only through the insight into the impossibility of
satisfaction that the striving abdicates in favour of higher tasks of
humanity.
It is, however,
impossible to say of this ethical conception, which expects from the
establishment of Pessimism a devotion to unselfish ends in life, that
it really overcomes Egoism in the proper sense of the word. The moral
ideals are said not to be strong enough to dominate the will until
man has learnt that the selfish striving after pleasure cannot lead
to any satisfaction. Man, whose selfishness desires the grapes of
pleasure, finds them sour because he cannot attain them, and so he
turns his back on them and devotes himself to an unselfish life.
Moral ideals, then, according to the opinion of Pessimists, are too
weak to overcome Egoism, but they establish their kingdom on the
territory which previous recognition of the hopelessness of Egoism
has cleared for them.
If men by nature strive
after pleasure but are unable to attain it, it follows that
annihilation of existence and salvation through non-existence are the
only rational goal. And if we accept the view that the real bearer of
the pain of the world is God, it follows that the task of men
consists in helping to bring about the salvation of God. To commit
suicide does not advance, but hinders, the realization of this aim.
God must rationally be conceived as having created men for the sole
purpose of bringing about his salvation through their action, else
would creation be purposeless. And such a world conception envisages
extra-human purposes. Every one of us has to perform his own definite
task in the general work of salvation. If he withdraws from the task
by suicide, another has to do the work which was intended for him.
Somebody else must bear in his stead the agony of his existence. And
since in every being it is, fundamentally, God who is the ultimate
bearer of all pain, it follows that to commit suicide does not in the
least diminish the quantity of God's pain, but rather imposes upon
God the additional difficulty of providing a substitute.
This whole theory
presupposes that pleasure is the standard of value for life. Now life
manifests itself through a number of instincts (needs). If the value
of life depended on its producing more pleasure than pain, an
instinct would have to be called valueless which brought to its owner
a balance of pain. Let us, if you please, inspect instinct and
pleasure, in order to see whether the former can be measured by the
latter. And lest we give rise to the suspicion that life does not
begin for us below the sphere of the “aristocrats of the
intellect,” we shall begin our examination with a “purely
animal” need, viz., hunger.
Hunger arises when our
organs are unable to continue their proper function without a fresh
supply of food. What a hungry man desires, in the first instance, is
to have his hunger stilled. As soon as the supply of nourishment has
reached the point where hunger ceases, everything has been attained
that the food-instinct craves. The pleasure which is connected with
satiety consists, to begin with, in the removal of the pain which is
caused by hunger. But to the mere food-instinct there is added a
further need. For man does not merely desire to restore, by the
consumption of food, the disturbance in the functioning of his
organs, or to get rid of the pain of hunger, but he seeks to effect
this to the accompaniment of pleasurable sensations of taste. When he
feels hungry, and is within half an hour of a meal to which he looks
forward with pleasure, he may even avoid spoiling his enjoyment of
the better food by taking inferior food which might satisfy his
hunger sooner. He needs hunger in order to get the full enjoyment out
of his meal. Thus hunger becomes for him at the same time a cause of
pleasure. Supposing all the hunger in the world could be satisfied,
we should get the total quantity of pleasure which we owe to the
existence of the desire for nourishment. But we should still have to
add the additional pleasure which gourmets gain by cultivating the
sensibility of their taste-nerves beyond the common measure.
The greatest
conceivable value of this quantity of pleasure would be reached, if
no need remained unsatisfied which in any way aims at this
kind of pleasure, and if with the smooth of pleasure we had not at
the same time to take a certain amount of the rough of pain.
Modern Science holds
the view that nature produces more life than it can maintain, i.e.,
that nature also produces more hunger than it is able to satisfy. The
surplus of life thus produced is condemned to perish in pain in the
struggle for existence. Granted that the needs of life are, at every
moment of the world-process, greater than the available means of
satisfaction, and that the enjoyment of life is correspondingly
diminished, yet such enjoyment as actually occurs is not one whit
reduced thereby. Wherever a desire is satisfied, there the
corresponding quantity of pleasure exists, even though in the
creature itself which desires, or in its fellow-creatures, there are
a large number of unsatisfied instincts. What is hereby diminished
is, not the quantity, but the “value” of the enjoyment of
life. If only a part of the needs of a living creature finds
satisfaction, it experiences a corresponding pleasure. This pleasure
is inferior in value in proportion as it is inadequate to the total
demand of life within the desires in question. We might represent
this value as a fraction, the numerator of which is the actually
experienced pleasure, whilst the denominator is the sum-total of
needs. This fraction has the value 1 when the numerator and the
denominator are equal, i.e., when all needs are also
satisfied. The fraction becomes greater than 1 when a creature
experiences more pleasure than its desires demand. It becomes smaller
than 1 when the quantity of pleasure falls short of the sum-total of
desires. But the fraction can never have the value 0 so long as the
numerator has any value at all, however small. If a man were to make
up the account before his death and to distribute in imagination over
the whole of life the quantity belonging to a particular instinct
(e.g., hunger), including all its demands, then the total
pleasure which he has experienced might have only a very small value,
but this value would never become altogether nil. If the
quantity of pleasure remains constant, then, with every increase in
the needs of the creature, the value of the pleasure diminishes. The
same is true for the totality of life in nature. The greater the
number of creatures in proportion to those which are able fully to
satisfy their instincts, the smaller is the average pleasure-value of
life. The cheques on life's pleasure which are drawn in our favour in
the form of our instincts, become increasingly less valuable in
proportion as we cannot expect to cash them at their full face value.
Suppose I get enough to eat on three days and am then compelled to go
hungry for another three days, the actual pleasure on the three days
of eating is not thereby diminished. But I have now to think of it as
distributed over six days, and this reduces its “value”
for my food-instinct by half. The same applies to the quantity of
pleasure as measured by the degree of my need. Suppose I have hunger
enough for two sandwiches and can only get one, the pleasure which
this one gives me has only half the value it would have had if the
eating of it had stilled my hunger. This is the way in which we
determine the value of a pleasure in life. We determine it by the
needs of life. Our desires supply the measure; pleasure is what is
measured. The pleasure of stilling hunger has value only because
hunger exists, and it has determinate value through the proportion
which it bears to the intensity of the hunger.
Unfulfilled demands of
our life throw their shadow even upon fulfilled desires, and thus
detract from the value of pleasurable hours. But we may speak also of
the present value of a feeling of pleasure. This value is the
smaller, the more insignificant the pleasure is in proportion to the
duration and intensity of our desire.
A quantity of pleasure
has its full value for us when its duration and degree exactly
coincide with our desire. A quantity of pleasure which is smaller
than our desire diminishes the value of the pleasure. A quantity
which is greater produces a surplus which has not been demanded and
which is felt as pleasure only so long as, whilst enjoying the
pleasure, we can correspondingly increase the intensity of our
desire. If we are not able to keep pace in the increase of our desire
with the increase in pleasure, then pleasure turns into displeasure.
The object which would otherwise satisfy us, when it assails us
unbidden makes us suffer. This proves that pleasure has value for us
only so long as we have desires by which to measure it. An excess of
pleasurable feeling turns into pain. This may be observed especially
in those men whose desire for a given kind of pleasure is very small.
In people whose desire for food is dulled, eating easily produces
nausea. This again shows that desire is the measure of value for
pleasure.
Now Pessimism might
reply that an unsatisfied desire for food produces, not only the pain
of a lost enjoyment, but also positive pains, agony, and misery in
the world. It appeals for confirmation to the untold misery of all
who are harassed by anxieties about food, and to the vast amount of
pain which for these unfortunates results indirectly from their lack
of food. And if it wants to extend its assertion also to non-human
nature, it can point to the agonies of animals which, in certain
seasons, die from lack of food. Concerning all these evils the
Pessimist maintains that they far outweigh the quantity of pleasure
which the food-instinct brings into the world.
There is no doubt that
it is possible to compare pleasure and pain one with another, and
determine the surplus of the one or the other as we determine
commercial gain or loss. But if Pessimists think that a surplus on
the side of pain is a ground for inferring that life is valueless,
they fall into the mistake of making a calculation which in actual
life is never made.
Our desire, in any
given case, is directed to a particular object. The value of the
pleasure of satisfaction, as we have seen, will be the greater in
proportion as the quantity of the pleasure is greater relatively to
the intensity of our desire. [We
disregard here the case where excessive increase of pleasure turns
pleasure into pain.] It depends, further, on this intensity
how large a quantity of pain we are willing to bear in order to gain
the pleasure. We compare the quantity of pain, not with the quantity
of pleasure, but with the intensity of our desire. He who finds great
pleasure in eating will, by reason of his pleasure in better times,
be more easily able to bear a period of hunger than one who does not
derive pleasure from the satisfaction of the instinct for food. A
woman who wants a child compares the pleasures resulting from the
possession of a child, not with the quantities of pain due to
pregnancy, birth, nursing, etc., but with her desire for the
possession of the child.
We never aim at a
certain quantity of pleasure in the abstract, but at concrete
satisfaction in a perfectly definite way. When we are aiming at a
pleasure which must be satisfied by a definite object or a definite
sensation, it will not satisfy us to be offered some other object or
some other sensation, even though they give the same amount of
pleasure. If we desire satisfaction of hunger, we cannot substitute
for the pleasure which this satisfaction would bring a pleasure
equally great but produced by a walk. Only if our desire were, quite
generally, for a certain quantity of pleasure, would it have to die
away at once if this pleasure were unattainable except at the price
of an even greater quantity of pain. But because we desire a
determinate kind of satisfaction, we experience the pleasure of
realization even when, along with it, we have to bear an even greater
pain. The instincts of living beings tend in a determinate direction
and aim at concrete objects, and it is just for this reason that it
is impossible, in our calculations, to set down as an equivalent
factor the quantities of pain which we have to bear in the pursuit of
our object. Provided the desire is sufficiently intense to be still
to some degree in existence even after having overcome the pain —
however great that pain, taken by itself, may be — the pleasure
of satisfaction may still be enjoyed to its full extent. The desire,
therefore, does not measure the pain directly against the pleasure
which we attain, but indirectly by measuring its own intensity
proportionately against the pain. The question is not whether the
pleasure to be gained is greater than the pain, but whether the
desire for the object at which we aim is greater than the inhibitory
effect of the pain which we have to face. If the inhibition is
greater than the desire, the latter yields to the inevitable,
slackens, and ceases to strive. But inasmuch as we strive after a
determinate kind of satisfaction, the pleasure we gain thereby
acquires an importance which makes it possible, once satisfaction has
been attained, to allow in our calculation for the inevitable
quantity of pain only in so far as it has diminished the intensity of
our desires. If I am passionately fond of beautiful views, I never
calculate the amount of pleasure which the view from the mountain-top
gives me as compared directly with the pain of the toilsome ascent
and descent; but I reflect whether, after having overcome all
difficulties, my desire for the view will still be sufficiently
intense. Thus pleasure and pain can be made commensurate only
mediately through the intensity of the desire. Hence the question is
not at all whether there is a surplus of pleasure or of pain, but
whether the desire for pleasure is sufficiently intense to overcome
the pain.
A proof for the
accuracy of this view is to be found in the fact that we put a higher
value on pleasure when it has to be purchased at the price of great
pain than when it simply falls into our lap like a gift from heaven.
When sufferings and agonies have toned down our desire and yet after
all our aim is attained, then the pleasure is all the greater in
proportion to the intensity of the desire that has survived. Now it
is just this proportion which, as I have shown (p. 181), represents
the value of the pleasure. A further proof is to be found in the fact
that all living creatures (including men) develop their instincts as
long as they are able to bear the opposition of pains and agonies.
The struggle for existence is but a consequence of this fact. All
living creatures strive to fulfil themselves, and only those abandon
the struggle whose desires are throttled by the overwhelming
magnitude of the difficulties with which they meet. Every living
creature seeks food until sheer lack of food destroys its life. Man,
too, does not turn his hand against himself until, rightly or
wrongly, he believes that he cannot attain those aims in life which
alone seem to him worth striving for. So long as he still believes in
the possibility of attaining what he thinks worth striving for, he
will battle against all pains and miseries. Philosophy would have to
convince man that willing is rational only when pleasure outweighs
pain, for it is his nature to strive for the attainment of the
objects which he desires, so long as he can bear the inevitable
incidental pain, however great that may be. Such a philosophy,
however, would be mistaken, because it would make the human will
dependent on a factor (the surplus of pleasure over pain) which, at
first, is foreign to man's point of view. The original measure of his
will is his desire, and desire asserts itself as long as it can. The
balance between pleasure and pain which is struck in life, though not
in intellectualistic philosophy, can be compared with the following.
If I am compelled, in purchasing a certain quantity of apples, to
take twice as many rotten ones as sound ones — because the
seller wishes to clear out his stock — I shall not hesitate a
moment to take the bad apples as well, if I put so high a value on
the smaller quantity of good apples that I am prepared, in addition
to the purchase price, to bear also the expense of the transportation
of the rotten goods. This example illustrates the relation between
the quantities of pleasure and of pain which are caused by a given
instinct. I determine the value of the good apples not by subtracting
the sum of the good from that of the bad ones, but by the fact that,
in spite of the presence of the bad ones, I still attach a value to
the good ones.
Just as I leave out of
account the bad apples in the enjoyment of the good ones, so I
surrender myself to the satisfaction of a desire after having shaken
off the inevitable pains.
Supposing even
Pessimism were in the right with its assertion that the world
contains more pain than pleasure, it would nevertheless have no
influence upon the will, for living beings would still strive after
such pleasure as remains. The empirical proof that pain overbalances
pleasure (if such proof could be given) is indeed effective for
showing up the futility of that school of philosophy, which sees the
value of life in a surplus of pleasure (Eudæmonism), but not
for exhibiting the will, as such, as void of reason. For the will is
not set upon a surplus of pleasure, but on whatever quantity of
pleasure remains after subtracting the pain. This remaining pleasure
still appears always as an object worth pursuing.
An attempt has been
made to refute Pessimism by asserting that it is impossible to
determine by calculation the surplus of pleasure or of pain in the
world. The possibility of every calculation depends on our being able
to compare the things to be calculated in respect of their quantity.
Every pain and every pleasure has a definite quantity (intensity and
duration). Further, we can compare pleasurable feelings of different
kinds one with another, at least approximately, with regard to their
intensity. We know whether we derive more pleasure from a good cigar
or from a good joke. No objection can be raised against the
comparability of different pleasures and pains in respect of their
intensity. The investigator who sets himself the task of determining
the surplus of pleasure or pain in the world, starts from
presuppositions which are undeniably legitimate. It is possible to
maintain that the Pessimistic results are false, but it is not
possible to doubt that quantities of pleasure and pain can be
scientifically estimated, and that the balance of pleasure can
thereby be determined. It is incorrect, however, to assert that from
the experience of this calculation any consequences arise for the
human will. The cases in which we really make the value of our
activity dependent on whether pleasure or pain shows a surplus, are
those in which the objects towards which our activity is directed are
indifferent to us. If it is a question whether, after the day's work,
I am to amuse myself by a game or by light conversation, and if I am
totally indifferent what I do so long as it fulfils the purpose, then
I simply ask myself: What gives me the greatest surplus of pleasure?
And I abandon the activity altogether if the scales incline towards
the side of displeasure. If we are buying a toy for a child we
consider, in selecting, what will give him the greatest pleasure, but
in all other cases we are not determined exclusively by
considerations of the balance of pleasure.
Hence, if Pessimistic
thinkers believe that they are preparing the ground for an unselfish
devotion to the work of civilization, by demonstrating that there is
a greater quantity of pain than of pleasure in life, they forget
altogether that the human will is so constituted that it cannot be
influenced by this insight. The whole striving of men is given its
direction by the measure of satisfaction attainable after overcoming
all difficulties. The hope of this satisfaction is the basis of all
human activity. The work of every single individual and the whole
achievement of civilization have their roots in this hope. The
Pessimistic theory of Ethics thinks it necessary to represent the
pursuit of pleasure as impossible, in order that man may devote
himself to his proper moral tasks. But these moral tasks are nothing
but the concrete natural and spiritual instincts; and he strives to
satisfy these notwithstanding all incidental pain. The pursuit of
pleasure, then, which the Pessimist sets himself to eradicate is
nowhere to be found. But the tasks which man has to fulfil are
fulfilled by him because from his very nature he wills to fulfil them
after he has clearly recognized their nature. The Pessimistic system
of Ethics maintains that a man cannot devote himself to what he
recognizes as his task in life until he has first given up the desire
for pleasure. But no system of Ethics can ever invent other tasks
than the realization of those satisfactions which human desires
demand, and the fulfilment of man's moral Ideas. No Ethical
theory can deprive him of the pleasure which he experiences in the
realization of what he desires. When the Pessimist says, “Do
not strive after pleasure, for pleasure is unattainable; strive
instead after what you recognize to be your task,” we must
reply that it is human nature to strive to do one's tasks, and that
philosophy has gone astray in inventing the principle that man
strives for nothing but pleasure. He aims at the satisfaction of what
his being demands, and he has in mind the concrete objects of his
striving — not an abstract “happiness.” The
fulfilment of his striving is to him a pleasure. Pessimistic Ethics,
in demanding that we should strive, not after pleasure, but after the
realization of what we recognize as our task in life, lays its finger
on the very thing which man wills in virtue of his own nature. There
is no need for man to be turned inside out by philosophy, there
is no need for him to discard his nature, in order to be moral.
Morality means striving for an end recognized as justified; it is
human nature to pursue it so long as the pain connected with this
striving does not inhibit the desire for the end altogether; and this
is the essence of all genuine will. Ethics is not founded on the
eradication of all desires for pleasure, in order that, in its place,
bloodless moral Ideas may set up their rule where no strong desire
for enjoyment stands in their way, but it is based on the strong
will, sustained by ideal intuitions, which attains its end even when
the path to it is full of thorns.
Moral ideals have their
root in the moral imagination of man. Their realization depends on
the desire for them being sufficiently intense in man to overcome
pains and agonies. They are his intuitions, the springs of action
which his spirit manipulates. He wills them, because their
realization is his highest pleasure. He needs no Ethical theory first
to forbid him to strive for pleasure and then to prescribe to him
what he shall strive for. He will, of himself, strive for moral
ideals provided his moral imagination is sufficiently active to
provide him with the intuitions, which give strength to his will to
overcome all the obstacles which lie in his own organization,
including the unavoidable pain.
If a man strives
towards sublimely great ideals, it is because their
realization will bring him an enjoyment compared with which the
pleasure which inferior spirits draw from the satisfaction of their
commonplace needs is a mere nothing. Idealists revel in
spirit in translating their ideals into reality.
Anyone who wants to
eradicate the pleasure which the fulfilment of human desires brings,
will have first to degrade man to the position of a slave who does
not act because he wills, but because he must. For the attainment of
the object of will gives pleasure. What we call the good is not what
a man must do, but what he wills to do when he unfolds the fullness
of his nature. Anyone who does not acknowledge this must deprive man
of all the objects of his will, and then prescribe to him from
without what he is to make the content of his will.
Man values the
satisfaction of a desire because the desire springs from his own
nature. What he attains is valuable because it is the object of his
will. If we deny any value to the aim of human willing, then we shall
have to look for the aims that are valuable among objects which men
do not will.
A system of Ethics,
then, which is built up on Pessimism has its root in the contempt for
man's moral imagination. Only he who does not consider the individual
human spirit capable of determining for itself the content of its
striving, can look for the totality of will in the craving for
pleasure. A man without imagination does not create moral Ideas; they
must be imparted to him. Physical nature sees to it that he seeks the
satisfaction of his lower desires; but for the development of the
whole man the desires which have their origin in the spirit are fully
as necessary. Only those who believe that man has no such spiritual
desires at all can maintain that they must be imparted to him from
without. On that view it will also be correct to say that it is man's
duty to do what he does not will to do. Every Ethical system which
demands of man that he should suppress his will in order to fulfil
tasks which he does not will, reckons, not with the whole man, but
with a stunted being who lacks the faculty of spiritual desires. For
a man who has been harmoniously developed, the so-called Ideas of the
Good lie, not without, but within the sphere of his own being. Moral
action consists, not in the extirpation of a one-sided individual
will, but in the full development of human nature. To regard moral
ideals as attainable only on condition that man destroys his
individual will, is to ignore the fact that these ideals are as much
rooted in man's will as the satisfaction of the so-called animal
instincts.
It cannot be denied
that the views here outlined may easily be misunderstood. Immature
persons without any moral imagination like to look upon the instincts
of their half-developed natures as the full content of humanity, and
reject all moral Ideas which they have not themselves originated, in
order that they may “live themselves out” without
restriction. But it goes without saying that a truth which holds for
a fully developed human being does not hold for half-developed human
natures. Anyone who still requires to be brought by education to the
point where his moral nature breaks through the shell of his lower
passions, cannot expect to be measured by the same
standard as a mature man. But it was not my intention to set down
what an undeveloped man requires to be taught, but what is contained
in the essential nature of a mature human being. My intention was to
demonstrate the possibility of freedom, and freedom is manifested,
not in actions performed under sensual or soul constraint, but in
actions sustained by Spiritual intuitions.
The mature man is the
maker of his own value. He does not aim at pleasure, which comes to
him as a gift of grace on the part of nature or of the Creator; nor
does he live for the sake of what he recognizes as abstract duty,
after he has put away from him the desire for pleasure. He acts as he
wills, that is, in accordance with his moral intuitions: and he finds
in the attainment of what he wills the true enjoyment of life. He
determines the value of his life by measuring his attainments against
his aims. An Ethical system which puts “ought” in the
place of “will,” duty in the place of inclination, is
consistent in determining the value of man by the ratio between the
demands of duty and his actual achievements. It applies to man a
measure that is external to his own nature. The view which I have
here developed points man back to himself. It recognizes as the true
value of life nothing except what each individual regards as such by
the measure of his own will. A value of life which the individual
does not recognize is as little acknowledged by my views as a purpose
of life which does not spring from the value thus recognized. My view
looks upon the individual who recognizes his own being in all its
parts as his own master and the assessor of his own value.
ADDITION TO THE REVISED EDITION, 1918
The
argument of this chapter is open to misapprehension by those
who obstinately insist on the apparent objection, that the will, as
such, is the factor in man which is void of reason, and that its lack
of reason should be exhibited in order to make man see that the goal
of his moral endeavour ought to be his ultimate emancipation from
will. Precisely such an illusory objection has been brought against
me by a competent critic who urged that it is the business of the
philosopher to make good what animals and most men thoughtlessly
forget, viz., to strike a genuine balance of life's account. But the
objection ignores precisely the main point. If freedom is to be
realized, the will in human nature must be sustained by intuitive
thinking. At the same time we find that the will may also be
determined by factors other than intuition, and that morality and its
worth can have no other root than the free realization of intuition
issuing from man's essential nature. Ethical Individualism is well
fitted to exhibit morality in its full dignity, for it does not
regard true morality as the outward conformity of the will to a norm.
Morality, for it, consists in what issues from the unfolding of man's
moral will as an integral part of his whole nature, so that to do
what is not moral appears to man as a stunting and crippling of his
nature.
|