FIRST APPENDIX
(Addition to the Revised Edition of 1918)
Various
objections brought forward by philosophers immediately after this
book was first published induce me to add the following brief statement to
this revised edition. I can well understand that there are readers for whom
the rest of the book is of interest, but who will regard the following as
superfluous, as a remote and abstract spinning of thoughts. They may well
leave this short description unread. However, problems arise within
philosophical world views which originate in certain prejudices on the part
of the philosophers, rather than in the natural sequence of human thinking
in general. What has so far been dealt with here appears to me to be a task
that confronts every human being who is striving for clarity about man's
being and his relationship to the world. What follows, however, is rather a
problem which certain philosophers demand should be considered when such
questions are under discussion as those dealt with here, because through
their whole way of thinking, they have created difficulties which do not
otherwise exist. If one simply ignores such problems, certain people will
soon come forward with accusations of dilettantism and so on. And the
opinion arises that the author of a discussion such as this book contains
has not thought out his position in regard to those views he does not
mention in the book.
The problem to which I refer is this: There are thinkers who are of the
opinion that a particular difficulty exists when it is a question of
understanding how the soul life of another person can affect one's own (the
soul life of the observer). They say: My conscious world is enclosed within
me; the conscious world of another person likewise is enclosed within him. I
cannot see into the world of another's consciousness. How, then, do I come
to know that we share the same world? A world view which considers that from
a conscious sphere it is possible to draw conclusions about an unconscious
sphere that can never become conscious, attempts to solve this difficulty in
the following way. This world view says: The content of my consciousness is
only a representative of a real world which I cannot consciously reach. In
that real world lies the unknown cause of the content of my consciousness.
In that world is also my real being, of which likewise I have in my
consciousness only a representative. And in it exists also the being of the
other person who confronts me. What is experienced consciously by him has
its corresponding reality in his real being, independent of his
consciousness. This reality reacts on my fundamental but unconscious being
in the sphere that cannot become conscious, and in this way a representative
that is quite independent of my conscious experience is produced in my
consciousness. One sees here that to the sphere accessible to my
consciousness, hypothetically is added another sphere, inaccessible to my
consciousness, and this is done because it is believed that we would
otherwise be forced to maintain that the whole external world which seems to
confront me is only a world of my consciousness, and this would result in
the — solipsistic — absurdity that the other persons also exist
only in my consciousness.
It is possible to attain clarity about this problem, which has been created
by several of the more recent approaches to a theory of knowledge, if one
endeavors to survey the matter from the point of view that observes facts in
accordance with their spiritual aspect, as presented in this book. To begin
with, what do I have before me when I confront another personality? Let us
consider what the very first impression is. The first impression is the
physical, bodily appearance of the other person, given me as perception,
then the audible perception of what he is saying, and so on. I do not merely
stare at all this; it sets my thinking activity in motion. To the extent that
I confront the other personality with my thinking, the perceptions become
transparent to my soul. To the extent that I grasp the perceptions in
thinking, I am obliged to say that they are not at all what they appear to
be to the external senses. Within the perceptions as they appear directly to
the senses something else is revealed, namely what they are indirectly. The
fact that I bring them before me means at the same time their extinction as
mere appearances to the senses. But what, in their extinction, they
bring to revelation, this, for the duration of its effect on me, forces
me — as a thinking being — to extinguish my own thinking and to put
in its place the thinking of what is revealed. And this thinking
I grasp as an experience that is like the experience of my own thinking. I have
really perceived the thinking of the other. For the direct perceptions, which
extinguish themselves as appearances to the senses, are grasped by my thinking,
and this is a process that takes place completely within my consciousness; it
consists in the fact that the thinking of the other takes the place of my
thinking. The division between the two spheres of consciousness is actually
canceled out through the extinction of the appearances to the senses. In my
consciousness this expresses itself in the fact that in experiencing the
content of the other's consciousness I am aware of my own consciousness as
little as I am aware of it in dreamless sleep. Just as my day-consciousness
is excluded in dreamless sleep, so in the perceiving of the foreign content
of consciousness, the content of my own is excluded. There are two reasons
why one tends to be deluded about these facts; one is that in perceiving the
other person, the extinction of the content of one's own consciousness is
replaced not by unconsciousness as in sleep, but by the content of the
other's consciousness; the other reason is that the alternation between
extinction and re-appearance of self-consciousness occurs too quickly to be
noticed in ordinary life. — This whole problem cannot be solved by an
artificial construction of concepts which draws conclusions from what is
conscious to what can never become conscious, but by actual experience of
what occurs in the union of thinking with perception. Instances like the
above often occur in regard to many problems which appear in philosophical
literature. Thinkers should seek the path to unprejudiced observation in
accordance with facts, both physical and spiritual, but instead they erect
an artificial construction of concepts, inserting this between themselves
and reality.
Eduard von Hartmann, in an essay
[ 63 ]
includes my
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
among philosophical works which are based on “epistemological
monism.” And this theory is rejected by him as one that cannot even be
considered. The reason for this is as follows. According to the viewpoint
expressed in the essay mentioned above, only three possible epistemological
standpoints exist. The first is when a person remains at the naive
standpoint and takes perceived phenomena to be realities existing outside of
human consciousness. In this case critical insight is lacking. It is not
recognized that after all one remains with the content of one's
consciousness merely within one's own consciousness. It is not realized that
one is not dealing with a table-in-itself but only with the object of one's
own consciousness. One remaining at this standpoint, or returning to it for
any reason, is a naive realist. However, this standpoint is impossible, for
it overlooks the fact that consciousness has no other object than itself.
The second standpoint is when all this is recognized and is taken into
account fully. Then to begin with, one becomes a transcendental idealist. As
transcendental idealist one has to give up hope that anything from a
“thing-in-itself” could ever reach human consciousness. And if one is
consistent, then it is impossible not to become an absolute illusionist. For
the world one confronts is transformed into a mere sum of objects of
consciousness, and indeed only objects of one's own consciousness. One is
forced to think of other people too — absurd though it is — as
being present only as the content of one's own consciousness. According to von
Hartmann the only possible standpoint is the third one, transcendental realism.
This view assumes that “things-in-themselves” exist, but our consciousness
cannot have direct experience of them in any way. Beyond human consciousness
— in a way that remains unconscious — they are said to cause
objects of consciousness to appear in human consciousness. All we can do is to
draw conclusions about these “things-in-themselves” from the merely represented
content of our consciousness which we experience. In the essay mentioned
above, Eduard von Hartmann maintains that “epistemological monism” — and
this he considers my standpoint to be — would in reality have to confess
to one of the three standpoints just mentioned; this is not done, because the
epistemological monist does not draw the actual conclusion of his
presuppositions. The essay goes on to say:
“If one wants to find out what position a supposed monist occupies in regard
to a theory of knowledge, it is only necessary to ask him certain questions
and compel him to answer them. Voluntarily he will not give any opinion on
these points, and he will go to any length to avoid answering direct
questions on them, because each answer will show that as a monist his claim
to belong to some other standpoint than one of the above three, in relation
to a theory of knowledge, is out of the question. These questions are as
follows: 1) Are things continuous or intermittent in their
existence? If the answer is: They are continuous, then we are dealing with one
form or another of naive realism. If the answer is: They are intermittent,
then we have transcendental idealism. But if the answer is: They are on the one
hand continuous (as content of the absolute consciousness, or as unconscious
representations, or existing as possibilities of perceptions), on the other
hand they are intermittent (as content of limited consciousness), then we
recognize transcendental realism. — 2) If three persons sit at a table,
how many examples of the table are present? He who answers: One, is a
naive realist; he who answers: Three, is a transcendental idealist; but he who
answers: Four, is a transcendental realist. This last answer does indeed
presuppose that it is legitimate to put under the one heading, 'examples of
the table' something so dissimilar as the one table as thing-in-itself, and the
three tables as perceptual objects in the three consciousnesses. Whoever finds
this too much will have to answer 'one and three' instead of 'four.' —
3) If two persons are in a room by themselves, how many examples of these
persons are present? One answering: Two, is a naive realist; one answering:
Four (namely, one 'I' and one 'other' in each of the two consciousnesses),
is a transcendental idealist; but one answering: Six (namely, two persons as
'things-in-themselves' and four objects of representation of persons in the
two consciousnesses), is a transcendental realist. One wishing to prove that
epistemological monism is a different standpoint from any of these three,
would have to answer each of the above questions differently, and I cannot
imagine what such answers could be.”
The answers of
The Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
would be: 1) He who
only grasps the perceptual content and takes this to be the reality, is
a naive realist; he does not make it clear to himself that he can actually
regard the perceptual content as enduring only so long as he is looking at it
and he must, therefore, think of what he has before him as intermittent.
However, as soon as he realizes that reality is present only when the
perceptual content is permeated by thought, he reaches the insight that the
perceptual content that comes to meet him as intermittent, is revealed as
continuous when it is permeated with what thinking elaborates. Therefore:
the perceptual content, grasped by a thinking that is also experienced, is
continuous, whereas what is only perceived must be thought of as intermittent
— that is, if it were real, which is not the case. — 2) When three
persons are sitting at a table, how many examples of the table are present?
One table only is present; but as long as the three persons remain at
their perceptual pictures they will have to say: These perceptual pictures are
no reality at all. And as soon as they pass over to the table as grasped in
their thinking, there is revealed to them the one reality of the table;
with their three contents of consciousness they are united in this one reality.
— 3) When two persons are in a room by themselves, how many examples of
these persons are present? There are most definitely not six examples present
— not even in the sense of transcendental realism — there are two.
Only to begin with, each of the two persons has merely the unreal perceptual,
picture of himself as well as that of the other person. Of these pictures
there are four, and the result of their presence in the thinking-activity of the
two persons is that reality is grasped. In their thinking-activity each
of the persons goes beyond the sphere of his own consciousness; within each of
them lives the sphere of the other person's consciousness, as well as his own.
At moments when this merging takes place, the persons are as little confined
within their own consciousness as they are in sleep. But the next moment,
consciousness of the merging with the other person returns, so that the
consciousness of each person — in his experience of thinking —
grasps himself and the other. I know that the transcendental realist describes
this as a relapse into naive realism. But then I have already pointed out in
this book that naive realism retains its justification when applied to a
thinking that is experienced. The transcendental realist does not enter into
the actual facts concerned in the process of knowledge; he excludes himself
from them by the network of thoughts in which he gets entangled. Also, the
monism which is presented in the
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
should not be called “epistemological,” but rather, if a name is wanted, a
monism of thought. All this has been misunderstood by Eduard von Hartmann. He
did not enter into the specific points raised in the
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity,
but maintained that I had made an attempt to combine Hegel's universalistic
panlogism
[ 64 ]
with Hume's
[ 65 ]
individualistic phenomenalism
[ 66 ]
whereas in actual fact the
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
has no similarity with
these two views it is supposed to combine. (This is also the reason I did
not feel inclined to compare my view with the “epistemological monism” of
Johannes Rehmke,
[ 67 ]
for example. In fact, the viewpoint of the
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
is utterly different from what Eduard von Hartmann and
others call epistemological monism.)
|