ULTIMATE QUESTIONS
THE CONSEQUENCES OF MONISM
WNAT IS
here called monism, this unitary explanation of the world, derives
from human experience
[ 62 ]
the principles it uses for explaining the world. The source of activity
also is sought within the world to be observed, that is, in human nature
accessible to self-knowledge, more particularly in moral imagination. Monism
refuses to seek the origin of the world accessible to perceiving and thinking,
outside of that world, by means of abstract conclusions. For monism,
the unity that thinking observation — which can be experienced —
brings to the manifold plurality of perceptions is, at the same
time, just what the human need for knowledge demands, and by means of which
entry into physical and spiritual realms is sought. One looking for another
unity behind the one sought by thinking observation, thereby shows only that
he does not recognize the agreement between what is found by thinking and
what the urge for knowledge demands. The single human individual actually is
not separated from the universe. He is part of it, and the connection of
this part with the rest of the cosmos is present in reality; it is broken
only for our perception. At first we see this part as a being existing by
itself because we do not see the cords and ropes by which the fundamental
forces of the cosmos sustain our life. One remaining at this standpoint sees
the part of the whole as a truly independently existing being, as a monad,
who somehow receives information about the rest of the world from outside.
But monism, as meant here, shows that one can believe in this independence
only so long as what is perceived is not woven by thinking into the network
of the world of concepts. When this happens, separate existence of parts is
revealed as a mere appearance due to perceiving. Man can find his
self-enclosed total existence within the universe only through the intuitive
experience of thinking. Thinking destroys the appearance due to perceiving,
inserting our individual existence into the life of the cosmos. The unity of
the world of concepts, which contains the objective perceptions, also
embraces the content of our subjective personality. Thinking shows us
reality in its true character as a self-enclosed unity, whereas the
manifoldness of perceptions is only its appearance determined by our
organization. (cp. p. 29 ff.). Recognition of the reality in contrast to the
appearance resulting from perceiving has always been the goal of human
thinking. Science has striven to recognize perceptions as realities by
discovering the laws that connect them. But where the view was held that
connections ascertained by human thinking had only a subjective
significance, the real reason for the unity of things was sought in some
entity existing beyond the world to be experienced (an inferred God, will,
absolute Spirit, etc.). And on this basis, in addition to knowledge of the
connections that are recognizable through experience, one strove to attain a
second kind of knowledge which would go beyond experience and would reveal
the connection between experience and the ultimate entities existing beyond
experience (metaphysics arrived at by drawing conclusions and not by
experience). From this standpoint, it was thought that the reason we can
grasp the connection of things through strictly applied thinking is that an
original creator built up the world according to logical laws, and the
source of our deeds was thought to be contained in the will of the creator.
It was not realized that thinking encompasses both subjective and objective
in one grasp, and that in the union of perception with concept full reality
is mediated. Only as long as we consider in the abstract form of concepts
the laws pervading and determining perceptions, do we deal in actual fact
with something purely subjective. But the content of the concept, which is
attained — with the help of thinking — in order to add it to
perception, is not
subjective. This content is not derived from the subject but from reality.
It is that part of reality that our perceiving cannot reach. It is
experience, but not experience mediated through perceiving. One unable to
recognize that the concept is something real, thinks of it only in that
abstract form in which he grasps it in his consciousness. But this
separation is due to our organization, just as the separateness of
perceptions is due to our organization. The tree that one perceives, has no
existence by itself. It is only a part of the great organism of nature, and
its existence is possible only in a real connection with nature. An abstract
concept has no reality in itself, any more than a perception, taken by
itself, has any reality. The perception is the part of reality that is given
objectively, the concept is the part that is given subjectively (through
intuition, cp. p. 32 ff.). Our spiritual organization tears reality into
these two factors. One factor appears to perception, the other to intuition.
Only the union of the two, that is, the perception fitted systematically
into the universe, is full reality. If we consider the mere perception by
itself, we do not have reality, but a disconnected chaos; if we consider by
itself the law that connects perceptions, we are dealing with mere abstract
concepts. The abstract concept does not contain reality, but thinking
observation which considers neither concept nor perception one-sidedly, but
the union of both, does.
Not even the most subjective orthodox idealist will deny that we live within
a reality (that we are rooted in it with our real existence). He only
questions whether we also reach ideally, i.e., in our cognition, what we
actually experience. By contrast, monism shows that thinking is neither
subjective nor objective, but is a principle embracing both sides of
reality. When we observe with thinking, we carry out a process that in
itself belongs in the sequence of real occurrences. By means of thinking we
overcome — within experience itself — the one-sidedness of mere
perceiving. We
are not able through abstract conceptual hypotheses (through pure conceptual
reflection) to devise the nature of reality, but when we find the ideas that
belong to the perceptions we live within reality. The monist does not try to
add something to our experience that cannot be experienced (a Beyond), but
in concept and perception sees the real. He does not spin metaphysics out of
mere abstract concepts; he sees in the concept, as such, only one side of
reality, namely, that side which remains hidden from perceiving but having
meaning only in union with perceptions. Monism calls forth in man the
conviction that he lives in a world of reality and does not have to go
beyond this world for a higher reality that cannot be experienced. The
monist does not look for Absolute Reality anywhere but in experience,
because he recognizes that the content of experience is the reality. And he
is satisfied by this reality, because he knows that thinking has the power
to guarantee it. What dualism looks for only behind the world of
observation, monism finds within it. Monism shows that in our cognition we
grasp reality, not in a subjective image which slips in between man and
reality, but in its true nature. For monism the conceptual content of the
world is the same for every human individual (cp. 33 p. ff.). According to
monistic principles, the reason one human individual regards another as akin
to himself is because it is the same world content that expresses itself in
the other also. In the unitary world of concepts there are not as many
concepts of lions as there are individuals who think of a lion, but only one
concept, lion. And the concept which “A” adds to his perception of a lion is
the same concept as “B” adds to his, only apprehended by a different
perceiving subject (cp. p. 32). Thinking leads all perceiving subjects to
the common ideal unity of all multiplicity. The one world of ideas expresses
itself in them as in a multiplicity of individuals. As long as man
apprehends himself merely by means of self-perception, he regards himself as
this particular human being; as soon as he looks toward the idea-world that
lights up within him and embraces all particulars, he sees absolute reality
living and shining forth within him. Dualism defines the divine primordial
Being as pervading and living in all men. Monism sees this common divine
life in reality itself. The ideal content of another human being is also my
content, and I regard it as a different content only so long as I perceive,
but no longer when I think. In his thinking each man embraces only a part of
the total idea-world, and to that extent individuals differ one from another
by the actual content of their thinking. But these contents are within one
self-enclosed whole, which encompasses the content of all men's thinking. In
his thinking therefore, man takes hold of the universal primordial Being
pervading all humanity. A life within reality filled with the content of
thought is at the same time a life within God. The merely inferred, not to
be experienced Beyond is based on a misunderstanding on the part of those
who believe that the world in which we live does not contain within itself
the cause and reason for its existence. They do not recognize that through
thinking they find what they need to explain the perceptions. This is also
why no speculation has ever brought to light any content that has not been
borrowed from the reality that is given us. The God that is assumed through
abstract conclusions is nothing but a human being transplanted into the
Beyond; Schopenhauer's will is the power of human will made absolute.
Hartmann's unconscious primordial Being. composed of idea and will. is a
combination of two abstractions drawn from experience. Exactly the same is
true of all other transcendent principles that are not based on thinking
which is experienced.
In truth, the human spirit never goes beyond the reality in which we live,
nor is there any need to do so, since everything we require in order to
explain the world is within the world. If philosophers eventually declare
that they are satisfied when they have deduced the world from principles
they borrow from experience and transplant into an hypothetical Beyond, then
the same satisfaction must also be possible, if the borrowed content is
allowed to remain in this world where, for thinking to be experienced, it
belongs. All attempts to transcend the world are purely illusory, and the
principles transplanted from this world into the Beyond do not explain the
world any better than those within it. And thinking, properly understood,
does not demand any such transcendence at all, because a thought-content can
seek a perceptual content, together with which it forms a reality only
within the world, not outside it. The objects of imagination, too, are
contents which are valid only if they become representations that refer to a
perceptual content. Through this perceptual content they become part of
reality. A concept that is supposed to be filled with a content from beyond
the world given us, is an abstraction to which no reality corresponds. We can
think out only concepts of reality; in order actually to find
reality itself, we must also perceive. An absolute Being for which a content is
devised is an impossible assumption when thinking is properly understood.
The monist does not deny the ideal; in fact he considers a perceptual
content, lacking its ideal counterpart, not to be a complete reality; but in
the whole sphere of thinking he finds nothing that could make it necessary
to deny the objective spiritual reality of thinking and therefore leave the
realm which thinking can experience. Monism regards science that limits
itself to a description of perceptions without penetrating to their ideal
complements, as being incomplete. But it regards as equally incomplete all
abstract concepts that do not find their complements in perceptions and
nowhere fit into the network of concepts embracing the world to be observed.
Therefore it can acknowledge no ideas that refer to objective factors lying
beyond our experience, which are supposed to form the content of purely
hypothetical metaphysics. All ideas of this kind which humanity has
produced, monism recognizes as abstractions borrowed from experience; it is
simply that the fact of the borrowing has been overlooked.
Just as little, according to monistic principles, could the aims of our
action be derived from a Beyond outside mankind. Insofar as they are
thought, they must originate from human intuition. Man does not make the
purposes of an objective (existing beyond) primordial Being into his own
individual purposes; he pursues his own, given him by his moral imagination.
The idea that realizes itself in a deed, man detaches from the unitary
idea-world, making it the foundation of his will. Consequently, what come to
expression in his action are not commands projected from a Beyond into the
world, but human intuitions that are within the world. For monism
acknowledges no world ruler who sets our aims and directs our activity from
outside. Man will find no such foundation of existence, whose decisions he
must fathom in order to discover the aims toward which he is to guide his
activity. He is referred back to himself. He himself must give content to
his activity. If he seeks for the determining causes of his will outside the
world in which he lives, then his search will be in vain. When he goes
beyond the satisfaction of his natural instincts, for which Mother Nature
has provided, then he must seek these causes in his own moral imagination,
unless he finds it more convenient to let himself be determined by the moral
imagination of others. This means: either he must give up being active
altogether, or must act according to determinations he gives himself out of
his world of ideas, or which others give him from that world. When he gets
beyond his bodily life of instincts, and beyond carrying out the commands of
others, then he is determined by nothing but himself. He must act according
to an impulse produced by himself and determined by nothing else. This
impulse is indeed determined ideally in the unitary idea world, but in
actual fact it is only through man that it can be taken from that world and
translated into reality. The reason for the actual translation of an idea
into reality through man, monism finds only in man himself. For idea to
become deed, man must first will before it can happen. Such will then has
its foundation only in man himself. Therefore ultimately it is man who
determines his own deed. He is free.
1st Addition to the Revised Edition, 1918:
In the second part of this book
the attempt has been made to give proof that freedom (spiritual activity) is
to be found in the reality of human deeds. To do this it was necessary to
separate from the total sphere of human deeds those actions that can be
deemed free by unbiased self-observation. They are the deeds which prove to
be the realization of ideal intuitions. No other deeds, if considered
without prejudice, can be regarded as free. But unbiased self observation
will lead man to recognize that it is inherent in his nature to progress
along the path toward ethical intuitions and their realization. Yet this
unprejudiced observation of man's ethical nature cannot arrive at an
ultimate conclusion about freedom by itself. For if intuitive thinking had
its source in some other being, if its being were not such as had its origin
in itself, then the consciousness of freedom, which springs from morality,
would prove to be an illusion. But the second part of this book finds its
natural support in the first part, where intuitive thinking is presented as
an inner, spiritual activity of man, which is experienced. To understand
this nature of thinking in living experience is at the same time
to recognize the freedom of intuitive thinking. And if one knows that
this thinking is free, then one also recognizes that sphere of the will to
which freedom can be ascribed. Acting human beings will consider that will as
free to which the intuitive life in thinking, on the basis of inner
experience, can attribute a self-sustaining essence. One unable to do this
cannot discover any altogether indisputable argument for the acceptance of
freedom. The experience which is referred to here finds intuitive thinking in
consciousness, which has reality not only in consciousness. And thereby
it is discovered that freedom is the characteristic feature of all deeds that
have their source in the intuitions of consciousness.
*
2nd Addition to the Revised Edition, 1918:
The content of this book is built
upon intuitive thinking, of which the experience is purely spiritual, and
through which, in cognition, every single perception is placed within
reality. This book intends to present no more than can be surveyed through
the experience of intuitive thinking. But it also intends to present the
kind of thought which this experienced thinking requires. It requires that
in the process of knowledge thinking is not denied as a self dependent
experience. It requires that one does not deny its ability to experience
reality in union with perceptions, instead of looking for reality only in a
world lying outside this experience, an inferred world in relation to which
the human activity of thinking would be something merely subjective. —
This characterizes thinking as the element through which man gradually
enters spiritually into reality. (It ought not to be possible to confuse
this world view, based on experienced thinking, with a mere rationalism.) On
the other hand, it should be evident from the whole spirit of this
presentation that for human knowledge, the perceptual element contains a
reality-content only if it is grasped by thinking. What characterizes reality
as reality cannot lie outside thinking. Therefore it must not be
imagined that the physical kind of perceiving guarantees the only reality.
What comes to meet us as perception is something man must simply
expect on his life journey. All he can ask is: Is one justified
in expecting, from the point of view resulting from the intuitively
experienced thinking, that it is possible for man to perceive not only
physically but also spiritually? This can be expected. For even though
on the one hand intuitively experienced thinking is an active process
taking place in the human spirit, on the other hand it is also spiritual
perception grasped without a physical organ. It is a perception in which the
perceiver is himself active, and it is an activity of the self which is also
perceived. In intuitively experienced thinking man is transferred into a
spiritual world as perceiver. What comes to meet him as perceptions within
this world in the same way as the spiritual world of his own thinking comes to
meet him, man recognizes as a world of spiritual perception. This world
of perception has the same relationship to thinking as the world of physical
perception has on the physical side. When man experiences the world of
spiritual perception it will not appear foreign to him, because in intuitive
thinking he already has an experience which is of a purely spiritual
character. A number of my writings which have been published since this book
first appeared, deal with such a world of spiritual perception. The
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity lays the philosophical foundation for
these later writings. For here the aim is to show that a properly understood
experience of thinking is already an experience of spirit. For this reason
it appears to the author that one able in all earnestness to enter into the
point of view of The Philosophy of Spiritual Activity will not come to
a standstill at the entry into the world of spiritual perception. It is true
that by drawing conclusions from the content of this book it is not possible
to derive logically what is presented in my later books. But from a living
grasp of what in this book is meant by intuitive thinking, the further step
will result quite naturally: the actual entry into the world of spiritual
perception.
|