Part 3
Friedrich Nietzsche's Personality and Psychotherapy
From the
Wiener Klinische Rundschau,
14th Year, No. I, 1900
I.
S THE PSYCHIC
processes act parallel with the brain
stimulae, so physiological psychology goes side by side with brain physiology.
Where the latter does not as yet offer sufficient knowledge, physiological
psychology may make purely provisional investigation into psychic appearances,
but always accompanied by the thought that for these psychic appearances
the possibilityof a parallelism with cerebral processes must
also be proved.” Even if one does not fully endorse this statement
of Theodor Ziehen, (compare his
Leitfaden der Physiologischen Psychologie,
Guide to Physiological Psychology, p. 2)
one will have to admit that
it has proved itself exceptionally fruitful for the methods of psychology.
Under the influence of his point of view which he expresses, this science
has attained truly scientific knowledge. But one must be quite clear
about the significant light which the observation of the pathological
soul appearances throws upon the connection between psychic appearances
and the corresponding physiological processes. Pathological experimentation
has rendered great service to psychology as well as to physiology. The
abnormal facts of the soul life clarify the normal ones for us. But
it must be especially important to follow abnormal manifestations into
those realms where the soul activity intensifies to the point of the
highest spiritual achievements.
A personality like Nietzsche
offers special points of interest for such observation. A morbid kernel
in his personality gave him occasion to return to the physiological
groundwork of his reflections. He alternately sounded all notes from
poetic diction to the highest points of conceptional abstraction. He
expressed himself very sharply over the connection of his ideas with
his physical condition. “In the year 1879 I completed my professorship
in Basle, during the summer lived like a shadow in St. Moritz, and the
next winter, the most sunless of my whole life, I existed like a shadow
in Naumburg. This was my minimum. I reached the lowest point of vitality
in my thirty-sixth year; I still lived, but without seeing three steps
ahead of me.
Der Wanderer und sein Schatten,
The Wanderer and his Shadow,
came to existence during this time. Without doubt, I then
had an understanding for shadows; ... The following winter, my first
winter in Genoa, brought about that sweetening and spiritualization
which is conditioned by an extreme poverty of blood and muscle; the
Morgenröte,
Dawn;
the perfect clarity and joyousness,
even exuberance of spirit, which the latter work reflects, is compatible
with me, not only with the deepest physiological weakness, but also with
an excess of painfulness. In the midst of my torment, which an uninterrupted
three-day headache, together with the most wretched vomiting of slime
brings with it, I possessed a dialectic clarity par excellence,
and thought through things very cold-bloodedly, for which, in a
more healthy condition, I was not sufficiently a climber nor sufficiently
crafty, nor sufficiently cold. My readers know perhaps to what
extent I consider dialectic as a symptom of decadence, for example,
in the most famous instance: in the case of Socrates” (Compare
M. G. Conrad,
Ketzerblut,
page 186,
and Elizabeth Foerster-Nietzsche,
The Life of Friedrich Nietzsche,
Volume II, page 328).
(See also
Nietzsche's Works, German Edition, 1911, Vol. XV. p. 9 – 12)
Nietzsche considered the change
of his ways of thinking to be absolutely the result of the changeability
of his physical condition. “A philosopher who has passed through
many states of health, and will do so again and again, has also passed
through many philosophies; he simply cannot do otherwise each time than
to transpose his condition into a spiritual form and, perspective; this
art of transfiguration is his philosophy.”
(Nietzsche's Works, Volume V, page 8)
In his recollections written in 1888, his
Ecce Homo,
Nietzsche tells how from his sickness he received the impulse
to develop within himself an optimistic world conception: “For
once, pay attention to this: the years of my lowest vitality were those
when I ceased to be a pessimist; the instinct for self-reconstruction
forbade me a philosophy of poverty and discouragement.” (Elizabeth
Foerster-Nietzsche,
The Life of Friedrich Nietzsche,
Volume II, page 338)
The contradictory in
Nietzsche's world of ideas is understandable from
this point of view. His physical nature moved in contrasts. “Provided
one is a person, by necessity one also has the philosophy of a person;
yet there is a substantial difference. In the one instance there are
his deficiencies, which philosophize; in the other, his riches and his
strength.” (Nietzsche's Works, Volume V, page 5) In Nietzsche himself
the two conditions alternated: one time the one, one time the other
was dominant. As long as he was in full possession of his youthful forces,
he considered the “pessimism of the nineteenth century as a symptom
of a higher power of thought, a victorious fullness of life;” he
considered the tragic knowledge, which he found in Schopenhauer,
to be “the most beautiful luxury of our culture, its most costly,
most aristocratic, most dangerous kind of waste, but always on the basis
of its over-richness, as its permitted luxury.” He could
no longer see such a permitted luxury in the tragic knowledge, when
the morbid in his life held the upper hand. For that reason, from now
on, he creates for himself a philosophy of the greatest possible life-affirmation.
Now he needed a world conception of “ego affirmation, ego glorification,”
a master morality; he needed the philosophy; of “eternal return.”
“I shall return again with this sun, with this earth, with this
eagle, with this serpent — not to a new life, or to a better life,
or to a similar life: I shall come back eternally to this identical,
this self-same life in the greatest and also in the smallest.”
“For the earth is a god's table, trembling with new, creative work
and divine plans; Oh, how ardently I long for eternity and for the marriage
ring of rings, the ring of the return!”
(Zarathustra,
Third Part)
The uncertain information
we possess about Nietzsche's ancestry unfortunately makes it impossible
to judge properly how much of Nietzsche's spiritual peculiarity is to
be traced to inheritance. It is often incorrectly stated that his father
died of a brain sickness. The latter contracted this illness through
an accident only after Nietzsche's birth. However, it does not seem
unimportant that Nietzsche himself points to a morbid element in his
father. “My father died at thirty-six years; he was delicate, gracious
and morbid, like a being destined only for a moment, or like a kind
of recollection of life, rather than life itself.” (M. G. Conrad,
Ketzerblut,
p. 179)
When Nietzsche speaks of the fact that
within himself lived something decadent next to something healthy; he
apparently considers that the former is derived from his father, the
latter from his mother, who was a thoroughly sound woman.
We find in Nietzsche's
soul life a series of traits bordering on the pathological, which remind
one of Heinrich Heine and of Leopardi, who also are similar to him in
other respects. Heine was tortured by gloomy melancholia from his youth,
and suffered from dream-like conditions; later, out of the most pitiful
physical constitution and increasing ill-health he knew how to create
ideas which were not far removed from those of Nietzsche. Indeed, in
Heine one finds almost a predecessor of Nietzsche, in the sense of the
contrast between the Apollonian, or quietly observing attitude toward
life, and the Dionysian, the dithyrambic life-affirmation. Heine's spiritual
life also remains inexplicable from the psychological point of view
if one does not take into consideration the pathological essence of
his nature which he had inherited from his father, who was a weak personality,
creeping through life like a shadow.
The similarities in
the physiological characteristics of Leopardi and Nietzsche are especially
remarkable. The same sensitivity toward weather and seasons, toward
place and environment, are found in both. Leopardi feels the slightest
change in the thermometer and barometer. He could create only during
the summer; he traveled about, always looking for the most suitable
location for his creative activity. Nietzsche expresses himself about
such peculiarities of his nature in the following manner: “Now
after long practice, when I observe the effects of climatic and meteorological
nature upon myself, as upon a very delicate and reliable instrument,
and after a short journey, perhaps from Turin to Milan, calculate the
change in the degree of humidity calculated physiologically in myself,
then I look with horror at the sinister fact that my life until
the last ten years, the most dangerous years, has always been spent
in locations treacherous and absolutely forbidden to me. Naumburg,
Schulpforta, Thuringia, in fact, Bonn, Liepzig, Basel, Venice, — all
of them places of misfortune for my physiology. ...” Connected
with this unusual sensitivity in Leopardi as well as in Nietzsche, is
a contempt for all altruistic feelings. Both of them had to overcome
this in order to be able to tolerate mankind. From Nietzsche's own words
one can see that his shyness in presence of strong impressions, of attractions
which demand too much of his sensitivity, fill him with suspicion toward
selfless impulses. He says: “I accuse those sympathetic people
in that it is easy for them to lose the modesty, the awe,
the delicate feeling for distances.” For Leopardi also,
it was certain that a bearable human being was very seldom found; he
encountered misery with irony and bitterness, just as Nietzsche had
adopted as one of his principles: “As first tenet of our
love for mankind, the weak and misformed shall be destroyed. And one
should even assist them in this.”
(Nietzsche's Works, Volume VIII, page 218)
About life, Nietzsche said that it is “Essentially appropriation,
injury, overwhelming of strangers and weaker ones, suppression, hardness,
forcing upon others one's own forms, incorporation, and, in its least
and mildest form, exploitation.”
(Jenseits von Gut und Böse,
Beyond Good and Evil, p. 259)
For Leopardi also, life is an unfeasible,
frightful struggle, in which some trample others.
The extent to which both
these thoughts play over into the pathological is shown in the completely
rational way these men arrive at their ideas. They were not impelled
to thoughts about the struggle for existence through logical reflection,
as, for example, the national economist, Malthus, and the philosopher,
Hobbes, or through careful observation as with Darwin, but through the
high-strung sensitivity already mentioned, with the result that every
external stimulus is regarded as a hostile attack, and is answered with
violent rejection. One can prove this quite clearly in Nietzsche. In
Darwin he finds the thought about the struggle for existence. He does
not reject it, but he re-interprets it in such a way that it accords
with his enhanced sensitivity: “But provided there is this struggle
— and, in effect, it does happen — it comes about unfortunately in
reverse from the way the Darwinian school wants it, as with them one
may perhaps wish, namely, to the disadvantage of the strong, the privileged,
the fortunate exceptions. The species does not grow in perfection; ever
and again the weak become masters over the strong because they are in
the majority, and because they are also cleverer. ... Darwin has forgotten
the spirit (that is English!) the weak have more spirit
... the strong sacrifice the spirit” (Nietzsche's Works, Volume VIII,
p. 128).
Without, doubt his heightened
sensitivity and impulses impel him to a certain extent to direct his
observations by choice upon his own personality. Entirely sound and
harmonious natures, like Goethe, for example, find something questionable
in far-reaching self-observation. In complete contrast to Nietzsche's
way of reflection stands Goethe's point of view: “We must not interpret
the significant saying, Know thou thyself, in an ascetic sense.
With this by no means is meant the auto-gnosis of our modern hypochondriacs,
humorists, and self-tormentors, but it means quite simply, take heed
of yourself to a certain extent, observe yourself so that you become
aware how you; stand in relation to others like yourself, and in relation
to the world. No psychological torments are necessary for this; every
capable human being knows and experiences what this should mean; it
is good advice, which is of the greatest practical advantage to everyone.
... How can one learn to know oneself? We can never get to know each
other through observations, but through action. Try to do your duty,
and immediately you will know how things are with you.” Now we
know that Goethe also possessed a fine sensibility. But at the same
time he possessed the necessary counter-balance, the capacity which,
in regard to others, he himself described in the most direct way, in
a conversation with Eckermann on the 20th of December, 1829: “The
extraordinary” things that exceptional talents have achieved, “presupposes
a very delicate organization, which makes them capable of rarer feelings.
... Now such an organization, in conflict with the world and with
the elements, is easily disturbed and injured: and the one who, like
Voltaire, does not possess an extraordinary toughness, is easily subject
to constant sickliness.” This toughness is lacking in natures like
Nietzsche and Leopardi. They would lose themselves completely in their
impressions, in irritations, if they could not shut themselves off artistically
against the outer world; indeed, if they could not oppose themselves
to it in a hostile way. One compares this overcoming which Nietzsche
required in his intercourse with mankind, with Goethe's pleasure in
this intercourse, which he describes in these words: “Sociability
was in my nature; thus I won co-workers for myself in my manifold undertakings,
educated myself to be a co-worker with them, and so attained the good
fortune to see myself live on, I in them and they in me.”
II.
The most noticeable phenomenon
in Nietzsche's spiritual life is the always latent, but at times clearly
evident, schizophrenic quality of his ego-consciousness. That “two
souls live, Alas, within my breast,” bordered upon the pathological
in him. He could not bring about the reconciliation between the “two
souls.” His polemics are hardly, to be understood except from this
point of view. He hardly ever really hits his opponent with his judgments.
He first arranges what he wants to attack in the strangest way, and
then struggles with the illusion, which is quite remote from reality.
One understands this only when one considers that fundamentally he never
fights against an external enemy, but against himself. And he fights
in a more violent way when at another time he himself has stood at the
point which he now regards with antagonism, or when at least this point
of view played a definite role in his soul life. His campaign against
Wagner is only a campaign against himself. He had half inadvertently
united himself with Wagner at a time when he was thrown back and forth
between contrary paths of ideas. He became the personal friend of Wagner.
In his eyes Wagner grew to the immeasurable. He called him his “Jupiter,”
with whom from time to time he breathes, “a fruitful, rich, stirring
life, quite different from and unheard of in mediocre mortals! Therefore
he stands there, deeply rooted in his own strength, his glance always
over and above the ephemeral; eternal in the most beautiful sense.”
(E. Foerster-Nietzsche,
Das Leben Friedrich Nietzsches,
The Life of Friedrich Nietzsche, Volume II, page 16)
Nietzsche was now developing
a philosophy within himself, about which he could say to himself that
it was entirely identical with Wagner's artistic tendencies and conception
of life. He identifies himself completely with Wagner. He regards him
as the first great renewer of the tragic culture which had experienced
an important beginning in ancient Greece, but which was subordinated
through the sophisticated, intellectual wisdom of Socrates, and through
the one-sidedness of Plato, and in the age of the Renaissance had experienced
a brief rejuvenation. Out of what he believed he recognized as Wagner's
mission, Nietzsche formed the content of his own creating. But in his
posthumous writings one can now see how he completely subordinates his
second ego under the influence of Wagner. Among these writings are found
dissertations from the time before and during his
Wagner enthusiasm, which moved in directions completely opposite to
his feelings and thinking. In spite of this he forms for himself an
ideal picture of Wagner, which does not live in reality at all, but
only in his fantasy. And in this ideal picture, his own ego vanishes
completely. Later, in this ego appears a way of reflection which is
the opposite of Wagner's method of conception. Now, in the true sense
of the word, he becomes the most violent opponent of his own thought
world. For he does not attack the Wagner of reality; he attacks the
picture of Wagner which previously he had made for himself. His passion,
his injustice, is only understandable when one realizes that he became
so violent because he fought against something which had ruined him,
according to his opinion, and which had taken him away from his own
true path. If, like another contemporary of Wagner's, he had faced this
objectively, perhaps he also might have become Wagner's opponent. But
he would have faced the whole situation in a more quiet, calm attitude.
It also comes to his consciousness that he does not wish to be freed
from Wagner, but rather from his own “I” as it had developed
itself at a certain time. He says: “To turn my back to Wagner was
a tribulation for me; to like something again later was a victory for
me. No one perhaps was more dangerously ingrown with this Wagner business,
no one rebelled against it more strongly, no one rejoiced more to be
free of it; it is a long story! Does one want a word for it? Were I
a moralist, who knows what I should call it! Perhaps a self-conquering.
What is it that a philosopher asks of himself at the beginning and at the
end? To overcome his age in himself, to become ‘timeless.’ Against
what does he have to wage his hardest struggle? With that in which he
is exactly the child of his age. Well I like Wagner as a child of this
age; that is to say, a decadent: only that I comprehended it, only that
I rebelled against it. The philosopher in me defended himself against
it.” (Nietzsche's Works, Volume VIII, page 1)
In the following words
he more clearly describes his inner experience of the dividing of his
ego and the immediate contrast of his world of thoughts: “He who
attacks his time can only attack himself; what can he see otherwise,
if not himself? So in another, one can glorify only one's self.
Self-destruction, self-deification, self-contempt: that is our judging,
our loving, our hating.” (Nietzsche's Works, German Edition, 1897,
Volume XI, page 92)
In the autumn of 1888,
Nietzsche cannot come to any agreement at all with himself about the
content of his book,
Richard Wagner in Bayreuth,
other than that he tries to justify himself in that he did not mean Wagner
at all, but himself. “A psychologist might add that what I had heard
in Wagner's music in my youth had absolutely nothing to do with Wagner;
that when I described the Dionysian music, I described that which I
had heard; that instinctively I had to translate and transfigure everything
into the new spirit which I bore within me. The proof for it, as
strong as proof can be, is my book,
Wagner in Bayreuth;
in all psychologically decisive places the question is only about me;
at will, one may put my name, or the name ‘Zarathustra,’
wherever the text mentions the name Wagner. The whole picture of the
dithyrambic artist is the picture of the pre-existentialist
poet of Zarathustra, drawn with profound depth and without touching the
reality of Wagner for a single moment. Wagner himself had an idea of this,
for he did not recognize himself in the book.” (E. Foerster-Nietzsche,
Das Leben Friedrich Nietzsches,
The Life of Friedrich Nietzsche,
Volume II, page 259)
Whenever Nietzsche fights,
he almost always fights against himself. When, during the first period
of his creative writing, he entered into active warfare against philology,
it was the philologist in himself against whom he fought, this outstanding
philologist, who, even before completing his doctorate, had already
been appointed a Professor at the University. When, from 1876 onward,
he began his struggle against ideals, he had his own idealism in view.
And, at the end of his writing career, when he wrote his
Antichrist,
again unparalleled in violence, this was nothing but the secret Christian
element in himself through which he was challenged. It had not been
necessary for him to wage a special battle in himself in order to free
himself from Christianity. But he was freed only in the intellect, in
one side of his being; in his heart, in his world of emotions, he remained
faithful to the Christian ideals in his practical life. He acted as
the passionate opponent of one side of his own being. “One must
have seen this doom near by; one must have been almost destroyed with
it to understand that here is no joke. The skepticism of our natural
scientists and physiologists is a joke in my eyes; they are lacking in
passion for these things, in suffering for them.” The extent to which
Nietzsche felt the conflict within himself, and the extent to which he
recognized himself as powerless to bring the different forces within him
into a unity of consciousness, is shown at the end of a poem in the summer
of 1888, that is, from the period shortly before the catastrophe. “Now,
incarcerated between two nothingnesses, a question mark, a tired riddle, a
riddle for predatory birds ... they will ‘free’ you, they
are already longing for your ‘freeing,’ they are already
fluttering about you, you riddles, about you, the hanged one! ...
Oh Zarathustra! ... self-knower! ... self-executioner!”
(Nietzsche's Works, Volume VIII, page 424)
This insecurity in regard
to himself is also expressed in Nietzsche in that at the end of his
career, he gives an absolutely new interpretation to his entire development.
His world conception has one of its sources in ancient Greece. Everywhere
in his writing one can point out what great influence the Greeks had
upon him. He never tires of continually emphasizing the greatness of
Greek culture. In 1875 he writes, “The Greeks are the only talented
nation of world history; as learners they are very talented; they understand
this best, and do not only know how to decorate and to refine the borrowed,
as the Romans do. Genius makes all half-talented, tributary; thus the
Persians themselves sent their messengers to the Greek oracle. How those
Romans with their dry seriousness contrast with these talented Greeks!”
(Nietzsche's Works, Volume X, page 352) And what beautiful words he
found in 1873 for the first Greek philosophers: “Every nation is
shamed when one points to such a wonderfully idealistic community of
philosophers as those of the old Greek masters, Thales and Anaximander,
Heraclitus, Parmenides, Anaxagoras, Empedocles, Democritus, and Socrates.
All these people are hewn entirely from one stone. Between their thinking
and their character strong necessity reigns. ... Thus together they
formed what Schopenhauer called a talent republic in contrast to the
scholar republic; one giant calls to the other through the empty halls
of the ages, and, undisturbed by the mischievous noisy ways of dwarfs
who crawl beneath them, they continue the lofty conversation of spirits.
... The first experience of philosophy on Greek soil, the sanction
of the Seven Wise Ones, is at once a clear and unforgettable line in
the picture of the Hellenic. Other nations have saints; the Greeks have
Wise Ones. ... The judgment of those philosophers about life and existence
says altogether so much more than a modern opinion because they had
life before them in luxuriant perfection, and because in them the feeling
of the thinker did not go astray, as in us, in the conflict between
the desire for freedom, beauty, largeness of life, and the impulse for
truth, which asks only, What is life really worth?” (Nietzsche's
Works, Volume VIII, page 7) This Greek wise one always stood before
Nietzsche's eyes as an ideal. He tries to emulate him with the one side
of his being, but with the other side he denies him. In the
Götzendämmerung,
wilight of Idols, 1888
(Nietzsche's Works, Volume VIII, page 167),
after his description of what he wishes to owe to the Romans, we read,
“To the Greeks I owe absolutely no strong kindred impressions; and,
to say it straight out, they can not be for us what the Romans are.
One does not learn from the Greeks; their way is foreign, it is also
too liquid to work imperatively, ‘classically.’ Whoever would
have learned writing from
a Greek? Who would have learned it without the Romans! ...
The splendid, pliant corporality, and bold realism and immorality,
which is part of the Hellenic, was a necessity, not something
natural. It came only later; it was not there from the beginning. And
from, festivals and arts one wanted nothing more than to feel and act
in a buoyant spirit; they are a means to glorify one's self,
under certain circumstances, to create fear for one's self. ... To
judge the Greeks in the German manner, according to their philosophers,
is to use, for example, the honorable gentlemen of the Socratic school
for solving solutions which fundamentally are Hellenic! ... The philosophers
indeed are the decadents of Greece. ...”
One will only gain full
clarity concerning Nietzsche's arguments when one combines the fact
that his philosophical thoughts rest upon self-observation,
with the idea that this self is not an harmonious self, but is rather
a self split apart. This splitting apart he also brought into his explanation
of the world. In looking back upon himself he could say, “Do not
we artists have to confess to ourselves that a weird difference exists
in us, that our taste, and, on the other hand, our creative power, stand
alone in a mysterious way, remain standing alone, and have a force of
growth in themselves: I want to say, quite different degrees of tempos,
old, young, ripe, dry, rotten? So that, for example, a musician is able
to create things for life which contradict what his spoiled
listener-ear, listener-heart, values, tastes, prefers; he doesn't even
need to know about this contradiction!” (Nietzsche's Works, Volume
V, page 323) This is an explanation of the nature of an artist, formed
according to Nietzsche's own being. We encounter something similar in
him in all his writings.
There is no doubt that
in many cases one goes too far when one connects manifestations of the
soul-life with pathological concepts; in a personality like Nietzsche's
the world-conception finds full clarification only through such a connection.
Useful as it might be in many ways to cling to the sentence of Dilthey's
Einbildungskraft und Wahnsinn,
Powers of Conceit and Illusion,
(Leipzig, 1886),
“The genius is no pathological manifestation, but the sound perfect
human being,” just as wrong might it be to reject dogmatically such
observations about Nietzsche as have been presented here.
|