Part 4
The Personality of Friedrich Nietzsche, A Memorial Address
A Memorial Address Given in Berlin
on September 13, 1900
T IS STRANGE
that with the infatuation for Nietzsche
in our day, someone must appear whose feelings, no less than those of
many others, are drawn to the particular personality, and yet who, in
spite of this, must constantly keep before him the deep contradictions
which exist between this type of spirit, and the ideas and feelings
of those who represent themselves as adherents of his world conception.
Such a one who stands apart must, above all, beware of the contrast
between the relationship of those contemporaries to Nietzsche a decade
ago as the night of madness broke over the “fighter against his
time” and what existed when death took him from us on the 25th
of August, 1900. It seems as if the complete opposite has happened from
what Nietzsche prophesied in regard to his effect on his contemporaries
in the last days of his creative work. The first part of his book, in
which he tried to recoin the values of thousands of years, his
Antichrist,
lay completed at the onset of his illness. He begins with the words,
“This book belongs to the very few; perhaps not even one of these
is yet living. There may be those who understand my
Zarathustra;
how could I confuse myself with those for whom ears are growing already
today? Only the day after tomorrow belongs to me. Some of my readers
will be born posthumously.” At his death it seemed as if the “day
after tomorrow” had already come. One must call into this apparent
“day after tomorrow” the words of
Zarathustra:
“You say you believe in Zarathustra? But of what importance is
Zarathustra? You are my believers, but of what importance are all believers?
Now I exhort you to lose me and to find yourselves; and only when you have
denied me will I return to you.” Who would dare to say whether
Nietzsche, were he to live today in fresh creativity, would look with
greater pleasure upon those who revere him with doubts, or upon others?
But it must be permitted, especially today, to look back, beyond these
present-day admirers, to the time when he felt himself alone and misunderstood
in the midst of the spiritual life surrounding him, when some people
lived who felt it blasphemous to be called his “believers,”
because he appeared to them to be a spirit whom one could not encounter
importunately with a “yes” or “no,” but like an
earthquake in the realm of the spirit, which stirs up questions for
which premature answers can only be like unripe fruits. But ten years
ago, more moving than the news of his death today, two pieces of news
which followed closely upon each other, came to the “ears”
which had “grown” for the Nietzsche admirers of that time.
The first concerned the cycle of lectures which Georg Brandes had held
about the world conception of Nietzsche at the University of Copenhagen
in the year 1888. Nietzsche felt this recognition to be one which had
come forth from “single ones” which were “born posthumously.”
He felt himself jerked out of his loneliness in a way which was in harmony
with his spirit. He did not want to be evaluated;
he wanted to be “described,” characterized. And soon upon
this news followed the report that his mind, tom from its loneliness,
had succumbed to the frightful destiny of spiritual darkness.
And, while he himself
could no longer contribute, his contemporaries had the leisure to sharpen
the outlines of his picture. Through the observation of his personality,
the picture of the time could imprint itself ever more clearly for them;
the picture of the time, from which his spirit rises like a Böcklin
figure. The worlds of his soul ideals could be illuminated by the light
which the spiritstars of the second half of the nineteenth century cast
upon them. In full clarity stood the points in which he was truly great.
But these also overshadowed the reason why he had to wander in loneliness.
The nature of his being led him over, heights of spirit life. He stepped
forth like one to whom only the essentials of mankind's development
are of concern. But this essential touched him as much as others are
touched in their soul by only the most intimate situations. Just as
the souls of others are burdened directly by only the most immediate
personal experiences, so the great questions of culture, the mighty
needs for knowledge of his age, decisively passed through his soul.
What permeated only the heads of many of his contemporaries, became
for him a personal affair of the heart.
Greek culture, Schopenhauer's
world conception, Wagner's music dramas, the knowledge of the more recent
natural science, aroused in him such personal, deep feelings as would
have been aroused in others only by the experiences of a strong, passionate
love. What the entire age lived through in hopes and doubts, in temptations
and joys of knowledge, Nietzsche experienced in his special way on his
lonesome heights. He found no new ideas; but he suffered and rejoiced
in the ideas of his time in a way different from that of his contemporaries.
It was their task to give birth to the ideas; before him arose the difficult
question, How can one live with these ideas?
His educational path had
made Nietzsche a philologist. He had penetrated so deeply into the world
of Greek spiritual culture that his teacher, Ritschl, could recommend
him with these words to the University of Basel, which engaged the young
scholar before he had taken his doctorate: Friedrich Nietzsche is a
genius and is able to do whatever he puts his mind to. He may well have
achieved excellent results in the sense of the requirements made of
philologists. But his relationship to Greek culture was not only that
of a philologist. He did not live in ancient Greece in thought alone;
with his whole heart he was deeply engrossed in Greek thinking and feeling.
The bearers of Greek culture did not remain the object of his studies;
they became his personal friends. During the first period of his teaching
activity in Basel, he worked out a book about the philosophers of the
tragic age before Socrates. It was published among his posthumus works.
He does not write like a scholar about Thales, Heraclitus and Parmenides;
he converses with these figures of antiquity as with personalities with
whom his heart is closely connected. The passion which he feels for
them makes him a stranger to the Western culture, which according to
his feelings, since Socrates has taken paths other than those of ancient
times. Socrates was Nietzsche's enemy because he had dulled the great
tragic fundamental moods of his predecessors. The instructive mind of
Socrates strove toward an understanding of reality. He desired reconciliation
with life through virtue. But there is nothing, according to Nietzsche,
which can degrade mankind more than the acceptance of life as it is.
Life cannot reconcile itself with itself; man can only bear this life
if he creates over and above it. Before Socrates, the Greeks
understood this. Nietzsche believed that he found their fundamental
mood expressed in these words which, according to legend, the wise Silenus,
the companion of Dionysus, gave as answer to the question, What is best
for mankind: “Miserable creation of a moment, children of accident
and travail, why do you force me to tell you what is not the most profitable
for you to hear? What is the very best for you is not attainable by
you; that is, not to be born, not to exist, to be nothing. But the second
best for you is to die soon.” Ancient Greek art and wisdom sought
consolation in the face of life. The servants of Dionysus did not wish
to belong to this community of life, but rather to a higher one. For
Nietzsche this was expressed in their culture. “In song and dance,
the human being expresses himself as a member of a higher community;
he has forgotten how to walk and how to speak, and he is about to fly,
to dance into the air.” There are two paths for man which lead
him over and above existence; in a blessed enchantment, as if in an
opium dream, he can forget existence and, “singing and dancing,”
feel himself at one with a universal soul; or he can look for his satisfaction
in an ideal picture of reality as if in a dream which flutters gently
above existence. Nietzsche characterizes these two paths as the Dionysian
and the Apollonian soul conditions. But the more recent culture since
Socrates has looked for reconciliation with existence, and thereby has
lowered the value of mankind. It is no wonder that with such feelings,
Nietzsche felt lonely in this more recent culture.
Two personalities seemed
to pull him out of this state of loneliness. On his life path he encountered
Schopenhauer's conception of the worthlessness of existence, and Richard
Wagner. The position he took in relation to these two clearly illuminated
the being of his spirit. Toward Schopenhauer he felt a devotion more
intimate than can be imagined. And yet Schopenhauer's teachings remained
almost without importance for him. The wise one from Frankfurt had innumerable
disciples who accepted faithfully what he had to say. But Nietzsche
never was one of these believers. At the same time that he sent his
pean of praise,
Schopenhauer als Erzieher,
Schopenhauer as Educator,
into the world, he wrote secretly for himself his serious
doubts about the philosopher's ideas. He did not look up to him as to
a teacher; he loved him like a father. He felt the heroic quality of
his thoughts even when he did not agree with them. His relationship
to Schopenhauer was too intimate to necessitate an external faith in
him or an outer confession. He loved his “educator” so much
that he attributed his own thoughts to him in order to be able to revere
them in another. He did not want to agree with a personality in his
thoughts; he wanted to live in friendship with another. This
desire also attracted him to Richard Wagner. What then were all those
figures of pre-Socratic Greek culture with whom he had wished to live
in friendship? Indeed, they were mere shadows from a far distant past.
And Nietzsche aspired to life, to the direct friendship of tragic human
beings. Greek culture remained dead and abstract for him, despite all
the life his fantasy tried to breathe into it. The Greek intellectual
heroes remained for him a yearning; for him Richard Wagner
was a fulfillment which tried to re-awaken the old world of
Greece within his personality, his art, his world conception. Nietzsche
spent most glorious days when from Basel he was allowed to visit the
Wagner couple on their Triebschen estate. What the philologist had looked
for in spirit, to breathe Greek air, he believed he found here in reality.
He could find a personal relationship to a world which previously
he had sought in ideas. He could experience intimately what he could
otherwise only have conjured before himself in thought. To him the Triebschen
idyll was like home. How descriptive are the words with which he describes
his feelings in regard to Wagner: “A fruitful, rich, stirring life,
quite different and unheard of in more mediocre mortals! For this reason
he stands there rooted deeply in his own strength, with his gaze over
and above all that is ephemeral; eternal in the most beautiful sense.”
In Richard Wagner's personality
Nietzsche believed he had the higher worlds, which could make life as
bearable for him as he imagined it to be in the sense of the ancient Greek
world conception. But precisely here did he not commit the greatest error
in his sense? Indeed he sought in life for what, according
to his assumptions life could not offer. He wanted to be above
life; and with all his strength he threw himself into the life that
Wagner lived. For this reason it is understandable that his greatest
experience had to be his deepest disappointment at the same time. To
be able to find in Wagner what he was searching for, he had first to
magnify the true personality of Wagner to an ideal picture. What Wagner
could never be, Nietzsche had made out of him. He did not see and revere
the true Wagner; he revered his image, which towered far above reality.
Then when Wagner had achieved what he aspired, when he had reached his
goal, Nietzsche felt the disharmony between his impression
and the true Wagner. And he separated from Wagner. But only he interprets
this separation psychologically correctly who recognizes that Nietzsche
did not separate from the true Wagner, because he never was his follower;
he only saw his deception clearly. What he had looked for in Wagner,
he could never find in him because that had nothing to do with Wagner;
it had to be freed from all reality as a higher world. Then Nietzsche
later characterized the necessity of his apparent separation from Wagner.
He says that what in his younger years he had heard in Wagner's music
had absolutely nothing to do with Wagner. “When I described the
Dionysian music, I described what I had heard; instinctively I had to
translate and transfigure everything into the new spirit which I bore
within me. The proof of this, as strong as proof as can be, is my book,
Wagner in Bayreuth;
in all psychologically decisive places
one can place my name, or the name
Zarathustra
wherever the text uses the name Wagner. The complete picture of the
dithyrambic artist is the picture of the pre-existentialist poet of
Zarathustra, drawn with profound depth, and without really
touching the reality of Wagner for a single moment. Wagner himself
had an idea of this; he did not recognize himself in the book.”
In
Zarathustra
Nietzsche sketches the world for which he had searched in vain in Wagner,
separated from alt reality. He placed his
Zarathustra
ideal in a different relationship to reality than his own earlier ideals.
He had had bad experiences in his direct turning away from existence.
He must have done injustice to this existence, and for this reason it
had avenged itself so bitterly against him; this idea gained the upper
hand within him more and more. The disappointment which his idealism
had caused him, drove him into a hostile mood toward all idealism. During
the time following his separation from Wagner, his works become accusations
against ideals. “One error after another is placed upon ice; the
ideal is not refuted — it freezes to death.” Thus in
1888 he expresses himself about the goal of his book which had appeared
in 1878,
Menschliches, Allzumenschliches,
Human, All Too Human.
After this Nietzsche looks for refuge in reality; he deepens himself
in the more recent natural science, in order that through it he can
gain a true guide to reality. All worlds beyond this world, which lead
human beings away from reality, now become abominable, remote worlds
for him, conceived out of the fantasy of weak human beings, who do not
have sufficient strength to find their satisfaction in immediate, fresh
existence. Natural science has placed the human being at the end of
a purely natural evolution. Through the fact that the latter has conceived
the human being out of itself, all that is below him has taken on a
higher meaning. Therefore, man should not deny its significance and
wish to make himself an image of something beyond this world. He should
understand that he is not the meaning of a super-earthly power, but
the “meaning of this earth.” What he wishes to attain above
what exists, he should not strive for in enmity against what exists.
Nietzsche looks within reality itself for the germ of the higher, which
is to make reality bearable. Man should not strive toward a divine being;
out of his reality he should bring forth a higher way of existence. This
reality extends over and above itself. Humanity has the possibility to
become superhumanity. Evolution has always been. The human being should
also work at evolution. The laws of evolution are greater, more comprehensive
than all that has already been developed. One should not only look upon that
which exists, but one must go back to primeval forces which have engendered
the real. An ancient world conception questioned how “good and
evil” came into the world. It believed that it had to go behind
existence in order to discover “in the eternal” the reasons for
“good and evil.” But with the “eternal,” with the
“beyond,” Nietzsche had also to reject the “eternal”
evaluation of “good and evil.” Man has come into existence
through the natural; and “good and evil” have come into existence
with him. The creation of mankind is “good and evil.” And
deeper than the created is the creator. The “human being”
stands “beyond good and evil.” He has made the one thing to
be good, the other to be evil. He may not let himself be chained through
his former “good and evil.” He can follow further the path
of evolution which he has taken till now. From the worm he has become
a human being; from man he can develop to the superman. He can create
a new good and evil. He may “reevaluate” present day values.
Nietzsche was torn from his work on
Umwertung aller Werte,
Transvaluation of All Values,
through his spiritual darkness. The evolution
of the worm to the human being was the idea which he had gained from
the more recent natural science. He himself did not become a scientist;
he had adopted the idea of evolution from others. For them it was a
matter of the intellect; for him it became a matter of the heart. The
others waged a spiritual battle against all old prejudices. Nietzsche
asked himself how he could live with the new idea. His battle
took place entirely within his own soul. He needed the further development
to the superman in order to be able to bear mankind. Thus, by itself,
in lonely heights, his sensitive spirit had to overcome the natural
science which he had taken into himself. During his last creative period,
Nietzsche tried to attain from reality itself what earlier he thought
he could gain in illusion, in an ideal realm. Life is assigned a task
which is firmly rooted in life, and yet leads over and above this life.
In this immediate existence one cannot remain standing in real life, or in
the life illuminated by natural science. In this life there also must be
suffering. This remained Nietzsche's opinion. The “superman”
is also a means to make life bearable. All this points to the fact
that Nietzsche was born to “suffer from existence.” His
genius consisted in the searching for bases for consolation. The struggle
for world conceptions has often engendered martyrs. Nietzsche has produced
no new ideas for a world conception. One will always recognize that
his genius does not lie in the production of new ideas. But he suffered
deeply because of the thoughts surrounding him. In compensation for
this suffering he found the enraptured tones of his
Zarathustra.
He became the poet of the new world conception; the hymns in
praise of the “superman” are the personal, the poetic
reply to the problems and results of the more recent natural science.
All that the nineteenth century produced in ideas, would also have been
produced without Nietzsche. In the eyes of the future he will not be
considered an original philosopher, a founder of religions, or a prophet;
for the future he will be a martyr of knowledge, who in poetry found
words with which to express his suffering.
|