The Position of Goethe in the Evolution of Western
Thought.
Goethe
and Schiller.
Goethe narrates a conversation that once ensued between
Schiller and himself after they had both attended a meeting
of the Society for Nature Research in Jena. Schiller was
dissatisfied with the results of the meeting. He had found
there a most disintegrating method for the study of Nature
and he remarked that such a method could never appeal to a
layman. Goethe replied that “possibly this method was
cumbersome for the initiated also and that there might well
exist yet another way of portraying Nature active and living,
struggling from the whole into the parts, and not severed and
isolated.” And then Goethe evolved the great ideas
which had arisen within him concerning the nature of plants.
He drew “with many characteristic strokes, a symbolic
plant” before Schiller's eyes. This symbolic plant was
intended to give expression to the essential being lying in
every single plant, whatever particular form it assumes. It
was intended to demonstrate the successive development of the
single portions of the plant, their emergence from each other
and their mutual relationship. In Palermo, 17th April, 1787,
Goethe wrote these words in reference to this symbolic plant
form: “There must be such a thing; if not, how could I
recognise this or that structure to be a plant if all were
not moulded after one pattern?” Goethe had evolved in
himself the conception of a plastic, ideal form that was
revealed to his spirit when he surveyed the diversity of the
plant forms and observed the element common to them all.
Schiller contemplated this form that was said to live, not in
the single plant but in all plants, and said, dubiously:
“That is not an experience, that is an idea.” To
Goethe these words seemed to proceed from an alien world. He
was conscious of the fact that he had arrived at his symbolic
form by the same mode of naive perception by which he arrived
at the conception of anything visible to the eye and tangible
to the hand. To him the symbolic or archetypal plant was an
objective being just as the single plant. He believed that
this archetypal plant was the result, not of arbitrary
speculation, but of unbiased observation. He could only
rejoin: “It may be very pleasing to me if without
knowing it, I have ideas and can actually perceive them with
my eyes.” And he was very unhappy when Schiller added:
“How can there ever be an experience that is
commensurate with an idea? For the inherent characteristic of
the latter is that an experience can never be equivalent to
it.”
Two opposing world-conceptions were confronting each other in
this conversation. Goethe sees in the idea of an object an
element that is immediately present, working and creating
within it. In his view, any given object assumes definite
forms for the reason that the idea has to express itself
within this object in a particular way. For Goethe it has no
meaning to say that an object is not in conformity with the
idea, for the object can only exist as the idea has made it.
Schiller thinks otherwise. To him the world of ideas and the
world of experience are two separate regions. To experience
belong the diverse objects and occurrences filling Space and
Time. The realm of ideas stands over against this as a
different kind of reality that is laid hold of by the reason.
Schiller distinguishes two sources of knowledge, because
man's knowledge flows to him from two directions — from
without through observation, and from within through thought.
For Goethe there is one source of knowledge only, the world
of experience, and this includes the world of ideas. Goethe
finds it impossible to speak of experience and idea,
because for him the idea is there before the eye of the
spirit as the result of spiritual experience, in the same way
as the sense-world lies before the physical eyes.
Schiller's conception has grown out of the philosophy of his
time. We must go back to Greek Antiquity to discover the
basic conceptions which are the hall-mark of this philosophy
and which have become the motive forces of the whole of
Western spiritual culture. We can form a picture of the
particular nature of the Goethean world-conception if we
endeavour to build up this picture entirely from elements
inherent in the world-conception itself, with the help of
ideas gleaned from it. Such an attempt will be made in the
later chapters of this book. A delineation of this kind can,
however, be assisted by a preliminary consideration of the
fact that Goethe expressed himself in this or that way about
certain matters because he agreed or disagreed, as the case
might be, with what others thought about some particular
region of natural and spiritual life. Many an utterance of
Goethe becomes intelligible only when we study the modes of
conception which confronted him and which he analysed in
order to arrive at his own personal point of view. How he
thought and felt about one thing or another throws light on
the nature of his own world-conception. When it is a question
of considering this sphere of Goethe's being a great deal of
what with him remained unconscious feeling only must be given
expression. In the conversation with Schiller referred to
above there stood before Goethe's spiritual eye a
world-conception contrary to his own. And this element of
opposition shows how he felt in regard to the mode of
conception proceeding from one aspect of Greek culture, which
perceives a gulf between material and spiritual experience;
it shows how, to him, sense experience and spiritual
experience were united without any such gulf, in a
world-picture communicated to him by reality. If we want to
experience in conscious living thoughts what was in Goethe a
more or less unconscious perception of the constitution of
Western world-conceptions we must consider the following. At
a certain crucial moment a mistrust in man's organs of sense
took possession of a Greek thinker. He began to think that
these organs of sense do not impart the Truth to man but that
they deceive him. He lost faith in the results of naive,
direct observation. He discovered that thought about
the true being of phenomena has not the same thing to say as
experience. It is difficult to indicate the particular
mind where this mistrust first gained a hold. We meet with it
in the Eleatic School of philosophy, of which Xenophanes,
born at Kolophon, 570 B.C., is the first representative. The
personality of greatest significance in this School appears
in Parmenides. Parmenides has asserted more emphatically than
any of his predecessors that there are two sources of human
knowledge. He has declared that sense impressions are
illusory and deceptive and that man can only attain to
knowledge of the True through pure thinking that takes no
account of experience. As a result of this conception of
thought and sense experience that arose with Parmenides many
later philosophies came to be inoculated with an evolutionary
disease, from which scientific culture still suffers to-day.
To discuss what origin this mode of conception has in
oriental thought does not fall within the scope of the
Goethean world-conception.
|