The Platonic Conception of the World.
Plato expresses this distrust in experience with his own
admirable courage. “The things of this world which our
senses perceive have no real existence: they are always
becoming, they never are. Theirs is only a relative
existence; taken together, they exist only in and by virtue
of their relation to each other; hence we can with equal
truth say of their whole existence that it is Non-Existence.
Hence they are not objects of a real knowledge. There can
only be real knowledge of something that exists in and for
itself, and ever the same way, whereas these sense-phenomena
are only the objects of conjecture evoked by sensation. So
long as we are restricted to the perception of these things
we are like men in a dark cave, bound so rigidly that they
cannot even turn the head, seeing nothing except when the
light of a fire burning behind them throws on the wall in
front the shadows of real objects which pass between them and
the fire; each man sees only the shadows of the other, only
the shadow of himself on that wall. But the wisdom of such
men would consist in predicting the sequence of those shadows
as taught them by experience.”
Platonism tears the perception (Vorstellung) of the universe
into two parts: the perception of the world of appearance and
that of the world of ideas, and true, eternal reality is
supposed to correspond only to the latter. “That which
alone may be said to have true existence, because it always
is, neither becoming nor passing away, is the ideal Archetype
of each shadow picture, the eternal idea, the archetypal form
of each object. These eternal ideas undergo no multiplicity,
for each in its true nature is one and one alone; it
is the archetype whose reflections or shadows picture are all
homonymous, single, transitory things of the same nature.
These eternal ideas do not arise, neither do they pass away;
they truly are, they do not become nor pass away like
their transitory reflections. Hence of them alone can there
be a real knowledge, for the object of a real knowledge can
only be that which is eternally and in every respect,
not that which is and again is not, according to how it is
perceived.”
It is only justifiable to make a distinction between ideas
and perception when we are speaking of the way in which human
cognition arises. Man must allow the objects to speak to him
in a twofold sense. They communicate one part of their being
to him voluntarily, and he need only pay attention. This is
the part of reality that is free of ideas. The other part,
however, he must himself extract from the objects. He must
set thought in action and then his inner being is flooded
with the ideas of the objects. The stage whereon objects
reveal their inner, ideal content, is within the personality.
They there make manifest that which is forever concealed from
external perception. The true being of Nature here becomes
articulate. It is due to the constitution of the human
organisation that objects can only be cognised through the
consonance of two tones. In Nature we have one exitant
producing both tones. The open-minded man listens for the
consonance. In the ideal speech of his inmost being he
recognises the utterances which the objects make to him. Only
those who are no longer open-minded interpret the matter
otherwise. They believe that the speech of their inmost being
proceeds from a sphere other than that of the speech of
external perception. Plato realised how important it is for
man's world-conception that the universe is revealed to him
from two sides. His understanding appreciation of this fact
made him recognise that reality may not be ascribed to the
sense-world per se. Only when the world of ideas
lights up from out of the life of soul and in his
contemplation of the world man is able to set before his
spirit, idea and sense perception as a uniform, cognitional
experience, has he true reality before him. That which
confronts sense-perception without being irradiated by the
light of the world of ideas, is a world of appearance. In
this sense Plato's insight also sheds light on Parmenides'
view concerning the illusory nature of sense objects. It may
well be said that Plato's philosophy is one of the most
sublime thought-structures that have ever emanated from
the mind of man. Platonism represents the conviction that the
goal of all striving after knowledge must be the assimilation
of the ideas that support the world and constitute its
foundations. A man who cannot awaken this conviction in
himself has no understanding of the Platonic view of
the world. So far as Platonism has entered into the evolution
of Western thought, however, it reveals yet another aspect.
Plato did not only stress the knowledge that so far as human
perception is concerned the sense world becomes mere
appearance when the light of the world of ideas is not shed
upon it, but his presentation of this fact has furthered the
notion that the sense world in itself, apart altogether from
man, is a world of appearance, and that true reality is to be
found only in the ideas. Out of this notion the question
arises: How do ideas and the world of sense (Nature) outside
man coincide? Those who cannot admit the existence of a sense
world, free of ideas, outside man, must seek for and solve
the problem of the relationship of idea and sense world
within the being of man. And this is how the matter stands
before the Goethean world-conception. The question,
“What is the relationship outside man between idea and
sense world?” is, so far as this world-conception is
concerned, unsound, because for it there exists outside man
no sense world (Nature) apart from idea. Man alone can for
himself separate ideas from the world of sense and so
conceive Nature void of ideas. It may therefore be said that
in the Goethean world-conception the question which has
occupied the evolution of Western thought for centuries
as to how idea and sense-object come together, is utterly
superfluous. And the outcome of this current of Platonism in
the evolution of Western thought which Goethe encountered in
the above-mentioned conversations with Schiller, for example,
and also elsewhere, seemed to him an unhealthy element in
human thought. The view that he did not definitely put into
words but which lived in his perception and was a formative
impulse in his own world-conception was this: healthy human
feeling teaches us at every moment how the languages of
perception and of thought unite in order to reveal the full
reality, and this has been ignored by the speculative
thinkers. Instead of paying attention to the way in which
Nature speaks to man, they have built up artificial
concepts of the relationship of the world of ideas and
experience. In order to realise fully what deep significance
this trend of thought, considered by Goethe to be unsound,
had in the world-conception which confronted him and from
which he would have liked to take his bearings, we must bear
in mind how this current of Platonism which dissipates the
sense world into appearance and so brings the world of ideas
into a distorted relationship to it, has been strengthened as
the result of a one-sided philosophical interpretation of
Christian truth in the course of the evolution of Western
thought. It was because of the fact that Goethe encountered
Christian conceptions bound up with this, to him, unhealthy
current of Platonism, that he could only with difficulty
build up his relationship to Christianity. Goethe has
not followed up in detail the further influence of this
current of Platonism (which he discarded) in the evolution of
Christian thought, but he perceived its influence in the
modes of thought which he encountered. As a result of this,
light is thrown on the development of Goethe's mode of
conception by observation that is able to trace the growth of
this influence in the directions taken by thought through the
centuries prior to Goethe. The evolution of Christian
thought as shown in many of its exponents, endeavoured to
come to terms with the belief in the world Beyond and with
the value that sense existence has in relation to the
spiritual world. Those who adhered to the conception that the
relation of the sense world to the world of ideas has a
significance apart altogether from man, arrived, together
with the problems arising out of this, at the conception of a
Divine World Order. And Church Fathers, faced with this
problem, had to cogitate on the role played by the Platonic
world of ideas within this Divine World Order. Here there
arose the danger of conceiving idea and sense world (which
are united in human cognition through direct perception) not
only as being separated off from man in themselves, but
separated from each other, so that the ideas, apart from what
is given to man in Nature, lead an independent existence of
their own in a spirituality separated from Nature. When this
conception, which is based on a false view of the world of
ideas and the sense world, was added to the justifiable
opinion that the Divine can never live in full
consciousness in the human soul, the result was a
complete severance of the world of ideas and Nature from each
other. That which ought always to be sought within the spirit
of man is then sought outside it in creation. The Archetypes
of all objects are thought to be contained within the Divine
Spirit. The world becomes the imperfect reflection of the
perfect world of ideas resting in God. As a result, then, of
a one-sided understanding of Platonism, the human soul is
separated from the relationship existing between idea and
“reality.” The soul extends its rightly conceived
relationship to the Divine World Order to the relationship
existing within itself between the world of ideas and the
world of sense appearance. This mode of conception leads
Augustine to the following view: “We can believe
without hesitation that although the thinking soul is not of
like nature to God, since He permits of no communion, the
soul may indeed be illuminated as the result of participation
in the Divine Nature.” And so when this particular mode
of conception is carried to extremes, it is no longer
possible for the human soul in its contemplation of Nature to
experience the world of ideas as the essence of reality. Such
experience is designated unchristian. The one-sided
conception of Platonism is extended to Christianity itself.
Platonism, as a philosophical view of the world remains more
within the element of thought; religious experience plunges
thought into the life of feeling and establishes it thus in
man's nature. Grappled in this way to the soul life of man,
the unsound element of a one-sided Platonism was able to
assume a deeper significance in the Western evolution of
thought than would have been the case if it had remained pure
philosophy. For centuries this thought-evolution confronted
questions such as: What relation is there between that which
man builds up as idea and objects of reality? Are the living
concepts existing in the human soul through the world of
ideas only notions, names, that have nothing to do with
reality? Have these concepts within them something real that
enters into man when he becomes aware of reality and
comprehends it through his intelligence? So far as the
Goethean world-conception is concerned such questions are not
reasonable in reference to anything that lies outside
the scope of man's being. In man's perception of reality
these problems are resolved through true human cognition in
eternal, living essence. And the Goethean world-conception
has not only to come to the conclusion that an element of a
one-sided Platonism lives in Christian thought but it has a
feeling of estrangement even from true Christianity itself
when this appears before it saturated with such Platonism. In
many of the thoughts that Goethe developed, in order to make
the world intelligible to himself, there lived this element
of aversion from the current of Platonism that he felt to be
unsound. That he had, also, an open mind for the way in which
Platonism raises the soul of man to the world of ideas is
proved by many an utterance of his in this connection. He
felt in himself the activity of the real world of ideas while
observing and investigating Nature in his own way; he felt
that Nature herself speaks in the language of ideas when the
soul opens itself to such language. But he could not admit
that the world of ideas may be considered as something
separate and apart, and that it is possible, as a result of
this, to say of an idea of the plant-being, that this is not
an experience but an idea. For Goethe felt that his spiritual
eye perceived the idea as reality, just as the eye of sense
sees the physical part of the plant-being. In this sense the
orientation of Platonism towards the world of ideas entered
into the Goethean world-conception in its purity and
the current of Platonism that leads away from reality was
there overcome. As the result of this configuration of his
world-conception Goethe had also to reject so-called
“Christian” conceptions which had assumed a form
that could only appear to him as transformed and one-sided
Platonism. And he was, moreover, bound to feel that many of
the world-conceptions confronting him and with which he would
have liked to come to terms, had not been able in Western
culture to overcome this Christian-Platonic view of reality
that is not in conformity with Nature and Ideal.
|