The Metamorphosis of Phenomena
Goethe's world-conception reached its highest state of
maturity when there dawned within it the perception of
Nature's two great motive forces: the meaning of the concepts
of polarity and intensification (Steigerung)
(Compare the Essay,
Erläuterung zu dem Aufsatz
‘Die Natur’).
Polarity inheres in
the phenomena of Nature in so far as we think of them in a
material sense. It consists in this:( everything of a
material nature expresses itself in two opposites, like the
magnet, in a north and a south pole. These states of matter
are either apparent to the eye, or they lie latent within the
material and can be roused into activity by appropriate
means. Intensification presents itself when we think
of the phenomena in a spiritual sense. It can be observed in
Nature processes which fall within the scope of the idea of
development. At the different stages of development these
processes manifest the idea underlying them with greater or
less distinctness in their external appearance. In the fruit,
the idea of the plant, the vegetable law, is only
indistinctly expressed in outer appearance. The idea cognised
by the mind and the perception do not resemble each other.
“The vegetable law appears in its highest manifestation
in the blossom and the rose becomes once again the summit of
the phenomenon.” What Goethe calls
“intensification” consists in the emergence of
the spiritual from out of the material as a result of the
creative activity of Nature. Nature being engaged “in
an ever-striving ascent” means that her endeavour is to
create forms which, in ascending order, bring the ideas of
the objects ever more and more to manifestation in outer
appearance also. Goethe holds that “Nature has no
secret that is not somewhere revealed to the eye of the
attentive observer.” Nature can produce phenomena
wherein the ideas proper to a wide sphere of allied processes
may be discerned. They are the phenomena wherein the
“intensification” has reached its goal, wherein
the idea becomes immediate truth. The creative spirit of
Nature here appears on the surface of the objects; what can
only be apprehended by thought in the coarse material
phenomena — what can be perceived only by spiritual
vision — becomes visible to bodily eyes in
“intensified” phenomena. Here all that is
sensible is also spiritual, all that is spiritual, sensible.
Goethe thinks of the whole of Nature as permeated with
spirit. Her forms are different because the spirit becomes in
them outwardly visible to a lesser or greater degree. Goethe
knows no dead, spiritless matter. Those things appear as such
in which the spirit of Nature assumes an external form that
does not resemble her ideal essence. Because one and the same
spirit is working in Nature and in his own inner being man
can rise to a participation in the products of Nature.
“From the tile that falls from the roof, to the shining
flash of spirit that arises in thee and which thou
impartest” — everything in the universe is to
Goethe the activity, the manifestation of One Creative
Spirit. “All effects of which we are conscious in
experience, of whatever kind they be, are in continuous
interdependence; they merge into each other; they undulate
from the first to the last.” “A tile is loosed
from the roof and in the ordinary sense we call this chance;
it falls on the shoulders of a passer-by, in a mechanical
sense certainly; yet not only mechanically, for it follows
the laws of gravity and so works physically. The
ruptured life veins give up their functioning forthwith;
instantaneously the fluids work chemically, the rudimentary
qualities make their appearance. But the deranged organic
life offers opposition with equal rapidity and tries to
restore itself; the human being as a whole is, meanwhile,
more or less unconscious and psychically disturbed. The
person coming to himself again feels himself deeply wounded
in an ethical sense; he bewails his disturbed activity of
whatever kind it may be, but man does not willingly resign
himself in patience. In a religious sense, on the other hand,
it is easy to ascribe this accident to a higher destiny, to
view it as a preservation from a greater evil, as a
preliminary to a higher good. This is sufficient for the
sufferer; the convalescent, however, rises up with the
buoyancy of genius, with trust in God and himself, and feels
himself saved; he takes hold even of what is accidental and
turns it to his advantage in order to begin an eternally
fresh orbit of life.” All effects in the world appear
to Goethe modifications of the spirit, and the man who
penetrates into their depths, and studies them from the level
of the fortuitous to that of genius, experiences the
metamorphosis of the spirit from the form wherein it
expresses itself in an external manifestation unlike itself,
right up to the stage where it appears in its own most
appropriate form. In the sense of the Goethean
world-conception all creative forces operate uniformly. They
are one Whole manifesting itself in a gradation of related
multiplicities. Goethe, however, had no inclination to
present to himself the unity of the universe as
homogeneous. Adherents of the idea of unity often fall
into the error of extending the law that may be observed in
one region of phenomena to cover the whole of Nature. The
mechanistic view of the world, for example, has fallen into
this error. It has a special eye and understanding for
what can be explained mechanically. Therefore the mechanical
alone appears to it to be in accordance with Nature, and. it
tries to trace the phenomena of organic Nature as well back
to mechanical laws. Life is only a complicated form of the
co-operation of mechanical processes. Goethe found such a
world-conception expressed, in a singularly repulsive form,
in Holbach's “Système de la Nature” that
fell into his hands in Strasburg. Matter was supposed to have
existed and to have been in motion from all eternity, and to
this motion to right and left in every direction, were
attributed the infinite phenomena of existence. “We
might have allowed even so much to pass if the author, out of
his matter in motion, had built up the world before our eyes.
But he seemed to know as little of Nature as we did, for,
after simply propounding some general ideas, he forthwith
disregards them in order to change what seems above Nature,
or a higher Nature within Nature, into matter with weight and
motion but without aim or shape, — and by this he
fancies he has gained much.”
(Poetry and Truth, Book II.).
Goethe would have expressed himself in similar
words if he could have heard Du-Bois Reymond's phrase
(Grenzen des Naturerkennens, S.13.):
“Natural knowledge is a tracing back of the variations
in the corporeal world to movements of atoms generated by
their central forces which are independent of time, or it is
the conversion of natural processes into the mechanics of
atoms.” Goethe thought that the modes of natural
operations were interrelated, the one passing over into the
other; but he never wanted to trace them back to one single
mode. He did not aspire after one abstract principle to which
all natural phenomena should be traced back, but for
observation of the characteristic mode in which creative
Nature, in each single one of her regions of phenomena,
manifests her universal laws through specific forms. He did
not want to force one particular form of thought on all
natural phenomena, but by living experience in different
forms of thought, his aim was to keep the spirit within him
as vital and pliable as Nature herself. When the feeling of
the mighty unity of all Nature's activity was strong within
him he was a Pantheist. “With the many and varied
tendencies of my being, I for myself can never be satisfied
with one mode of thinking; as poet and artist I am a
Polytheist, as Nature investigator, a Pantheist, and such as
decisively as the other. If I need a God for my personality
as a moral being, that also is provided for” (To
Jacobi, 6th January, 1813.). As Artist, Goethe turned to
those natural phenomena where the idea is present in direct
perception. Here the particular seemed immediately divine,
the world a multiplicity of divine entities. As Nature
investigator Goethe had perforce also to follow up the forces
of Nature in those phenomena where the idea in its individual
existence was not visible. As Poet, he could rest content
with the multiplicity of the Divine; as Nature investigator
he had to seek for the uniformly active ideas of Nature.
“The law that manifests in the most absolute freedom,
according to its own conditions, produces the objectively
beautiful, and this must indeed find worthy subjects by whom
it can be understood.” As Artist, Goethe's aim is to
perceive this element of objective beauty in the single
creation, but as Nature investigator his aim is “to
cognise the laws according to which universal Nature wills to
act.” Polytheism is the mode of thought that sees and
venerates a spiritual element in the particular;
Pantheism is the mode that apprehends the Spirit of the
Whole. The two modes of thought can exist side by side; the
one or the other asserts itself according to whether the gaze
is directed to Nature as one Whole, that is, life and
progression from one central point; or to those entities
wherein Nature unites in one form all that she usually
extends over a whole kingdom. Such forms arise when, for
instance, the creative powers of Nature “after
producing manifold plant forms, produce one wherein all the
rest are contained;” or “after manifold animal
forms, a being who contains them all: Man.”
* * * * *
Goethe has made this remark: “Whoever has learnt to
understand my writings and my real nature will have to admit
that he has attained a certain inner freedom”
(Conversations with Chancellor F. von Müller, January
5th, 1813.). Goethe was referring here to the active force
which asserts itself in all man's striving for knowledge. So
long as man remains stationary at the point where he
perceives all the antitheses around him, regarding their laws
as principles which have been implanted in them and by which
they are governed, he has the feeling that they confront him
as unknown powers working upon him, forcing upon him the
thoughts of their laws. He feels no freedom in face of the
objects; he experiences the Law of Nature as inflexible
necessity to which he has to submit. Only when man becomes
aware that the forces of Nature are only forms of the same
spirit that works also in himself does the intuition dawn in
him that he partakes of freedom. Nature's Law is perceived as
compulsion only so long as man looks upon it as an alien
power. If he penetrates its true being it is experienced as a
force which he himself uses in his inner being; he feels
himself to be an element co-operating productively in the
“being and becoming” of things. He is on intimate
terms with all power of “becoming;” he has
absorbed into his own action what he otherwise only
experiences as external instigation. This is the liberating
process brought about by the cognitional act in the sense of
the Goethean world-conception. Clearly did Goethe perceive
the ideas of Nature's activity as they faced him in the
Italian works of Art. He also realised clearly the liberating
effect which the mastery of these ideas has on man. A
consequence of this is his description of the mode of
cognition which he speaks of as that of comprehensive minds.
“Comprehensive minds, which we can proudly speak
of as creative, are productive in the highest degree; in that
they take their start from ideas, they already express the
unity of the Whole, and it is really thereafter the
concern of Nature to submit herself to these
ideas.” Goethe, however, never attained to direct
perception of the act of liberation. This perception can only
be attained by one who observes himself in the act of
cognition. Goethe did indeed practise the highest mode of
cognition, but he did not observe this mode of cognition in
himself. Does he not himself admit: “I have been
clever, for I have never thought about thought.”
But just as the creative powers of Nature after manifold
plant forms bring forth one wherein “all the others are
contained,” so, after manifold ideas, do these creative
powers of Nature produce one wherein is contained the whole
of ideas. And man apprehends this idea when to the perception
(Anschauung) of other objects and processes, he adds the
perception (Anschauung) of thinking. For the very reason that
Goethe's thinking was entirely filled with the objects
perceived, because his thinking was a perception, his
perception a thinking, he could not come to the point of
making thought itself into an object of thought. But the idea
of freedom is only attained through the perception of
thought. Goethe did not make the distinction between thinking
about thought and the perception of thought. Otherwise he
would have attained the insight that although in the sense of
his world-conception one may indeed refrain from thinking
about thought, it is nevertheless possible to attain to
perception of the world of thought. Man has no participation
in the coming-into-existence of all other perceptions. The
ideas of these perceptions come to life within him. The
ideas, however, would not be there if the productive power to
bring them to manifestation did not exist within him.
The ideas may be in truth the content of what is working in
the objects, but they come to evident existence as a result
of the activity of man. Therefore man can only cognise the
essential nature of the world of ideas when he
perceives his own activity. In every other perception
he does nothing more than penetrate the idea in operation;
the object in which it is operating remains, as perception,
outside his mind. In the perception of the idea the operative
activity and what it has brought about are contained within
his inner being. He has the whole process completely present
within him. The perception no longer seems to have been
generated by the idea; for the perception is now itself idea.
This perception of what brings forth its self, is,
however, the perception of freedom (free spiritual activity).
When he observes thought, man penetrates the world-process.
Here he has not to search for an idea of this process, for
the process is the idea itself. The previously experienced
unity of perception and idea is here experience of the
spirituality of the world of ideas which has become
perceptible. The man who perceives this self-grounded
activity has the feeling of freedom. Goethe indeed
experienced this feeling but did not express it in its
highest form. He practised a free activity in his observation
of Nature, but this activity was never objective to him. He
never gazed behind the veils of human cognition and therefore
never assimilated into his consciousness the idea of the
world-process in its essential form, in its highest
metamorphosis. As soon as man attains to the perception of
this highest metamorphosis he moves with certainty within the
realm of things. At the central point of his personality he
has attained the true point of departure for all observation
of the world. He will no longer search for unknown
principles, for causes that he outside himself; he knows that
the highest experience of which he is capable consists in the
self-contemplation of his own being. Those who are wholly
permeated by the feelings which this experience evokes will
attain the truest relationship to things. Where this is not
the case men will seek for the highest form of existence
elsewhere and since it is not to be discovered in
experience, they will conjecture that it lies in an
unknown region of reality. An element of uncertainty will
make its appearance in their observation; in answering the
questions which Nature puts to them they will perpetually
plead the unfathomable. Because of his life in the world of
ideas Goethe had a feeling of the firm central point within
the personality, and so he succeeded within certain limits in
acquiring sure concepts in his observation of Nature.
Because, however, the direct perception of the most inward
experience eluded him, he groped around insecurely outside
these limits. For this reason he says that man is not born
“to solve the problems of the universe but to seek
where the problem commences, and then to keep within the
boundary of the comprehensible.” He says:
“Unquestionably the greatest service rendered by
Kant is that he sets up limits to which the human mind is
capable of advancing, and that he leaves the insoluble
problems alone.” If the perception of the highest
experience had yielded him certainty in the observation of
things Goethe would have attained more along his path than
“a kind of qualified reliability by means of ordered
experience.” Instead of penetrating right through
experience in the consciousness that the true has only
meaning to the extent to which it is demanded by the nature
of man, he came to the conviction that “a higher
influence favours the constant, the active, the rational, the
ordered and the ordering, the human and the pious” and
that “the moral World Order” manifests in the
greatest beauty where it “comes indirectly to the
assistance of the good, of the valiant sufferer.”
* * * * *
Because Goethe did not know the most inward human experience
it was impossible for him to attain to the ultimate thoughts
concerning the moral World Order which essentially belong to
his conception of Nature. The ideas of things are the content
of the active creative elements within them. Man experiences
moral ideas directly in the form of ideas. A man who is able
to experience how in perception of the world of ideas, the
ideal itself becomes self-contained, filled with itself, is
also able to experience how the moral element is produced
within the nature of man. A man who knows the ideas of Nature
only in their relationship to the world of perception will
want to relate moral concepts also to something external to
them. He will seek a reality for these concepts similar to
the reality that exists for concepts that have been acquired
from experience. A man, however, who is able to perceive
ideas in their own proper essence will be aware that in the
case of moral ideas nothing external corresponds to them,
that they are produced directly in spiritual experience as
ideas. It is clear to him that neither an externally working
Divine Will nor an externally working moral World Order is
active in producing these ideas. For no trace of relationship
to such powers can be observed in them. All that they express
is also included in their pure, ideal form which is
experienced spiritually. They work upon man as moral powers
by virtue of their own content only. No categorical
imperative stands behind them with a whip and forces man to
follow them. Man feels that he himself has brought them
forth and he loves them as he loves his child. Love is the
motive power of action. Spiritual delight in one's own
production is the source of the moral.
There are men who are incapable of giving birth to any moral
ideas. They assimilate those of other men through tradition.
And if they have no perceptual faculty for ideas per
se they do not recognise the source of the Moral that can
be experienced in the mind. They seek this source in a
superhuman Will that lies outside them. Or they believe that
outside that spiritual world which is experienced by man
there exists an objective, moral World Order whence the moral
ideas are derived. The speech organ of this World Order is
frequently thought to lie in the human conscience. Goethe is
uncertain in his thoughts about the source of the Moral, just
as he is about certain matters pertaining to the rest of his
world-conception. Here too, his feeling for what is in
conformity with ideas drives him to principles that accord
with the demands of his nature: “Duty — where man
loves the commands he gives to himself.” Only a man who
perceives the basis of the Moral wholly in the content of
moral ideas could have said: “Lessing, who reluctantly
was aware of various limitations, puts these words into the
mouth of one of his characters: Nobody is compelled to be
compelled (Niemand muss müssen). A spiritually-minded,
happily disposed man said: He who wants to — must. A
third, a man of culture to be sure, added: He who has
insight, he also wants to. And so it was believed that the
whole range of knowledge, will and necessity had been
defined. But on the average, man's knowledge of whatever kind
it be, determines his actions and missions; therefore nothing
is more terrible to see than ignorance in action.” The
following utterance proves that a sense of the true nature of
the moral held sway in Goethe but never became a clear
perception: “In order to become perfect the will must
submit itself in the moral sphere, to the conscience that
does not err. ... The conscience needs no ancestry,
everything exists within it, it is concerned with the inner
world alone.” “Conscience needs no
ancestry” can only mean that originally there exists no
moral content in man; he supplies it himself. In
contradistinction to these sayings we find others where the
origin of conscience is relegated to a region outside man:
“However strongly the earth with its thousands upon
thousands of phenomena attracts man, he still raises his gaze
with longing to the heavens, because he feels deeply and
vividly within himself that he is a citizen of that spiritual
realm the belief in which we can neither reject nor
surrender.” “That which defies solution we leave
with God as the All-determinant, All-liberating
Being.”
* * * * *
Goethe has no faculty for observation of the innermost
nature of man, for self-contemplation. “I acknowledge
in this connection that the mighty command which sounds
so significant — ‘Know thyself!’ — has always
roused the suspicion in me that it was a ruse of a secret
confederacy of the priesthood whose aim it was to confuse men
by unattainable demands and to lead them away from activity
in the external world to a false inward contemplation. Man
knows himself only to the extent to which he knows the world.
He becomes aware of the world only in himself, and of
himself, only in the world. Every fresh object, contemplated
with deliberation, opens up a new faculty within us.”
The truth is exactly the reverse: man knows the world
only to the extent to which he knows himself. For what is
present as perception in external objects in reflection,
example, symbol, only reveals itself in his inner being in
its own essential form. That which man can otherwise only
speak of as unfathomable, impenetrable, divine, appears
before him in its true form in self-perception. Because in
self-perception he sees the ideal in direct form he acquires
the power and faculty to seek for and recognise this ideal
element in all outer phenomena also, in the whole of Nature.
A man who has experienced the flash of self-perception does
not any longer set out in quest of a “hidden” God
behind the phenomena; he apprehends the Divine in its
different metamorphoses within Nature. Goethe remarked
in reference to Schelling: “I would see him more
frequently if I were not still living in the hope of poetic
moments; philosophy ruins poetry so far as I am concerned,
probably because it forces me into the object, and
since I can never remain purely speculative but am compelled
to seek a perception for every principle I take flight at
once out into Nature.” The highest perception, the
perception of the world of ideas, however, was just what he
could not discover. That perception cannot ruin poetry, for
it alone frees the spirit from all conjectures as to the
existence in Nature of an unknown, an unfathomable element.
It makes the spirit able to surrender itself wholly and
freely to the objects, for it imparts the conviction that all
that the spirit may desire from Nature may be gleaned from
her.
The highest perception, however, also frees the human spirit
from any one-sided sense of dependence. In possessing it the
spirit of man feels itself master in the realm of the moral
World Order. The spirit of man knows that in its inner being
there works, as in its own will, the motive power that brings
forth all things, and that the highest moral decisions lie
within itself. For these highest decisions flow from the
world of moral ideas, and the soul of man has been present at
the production of this world. Man may be conscious of
limitation in regard to a particular thing, may be dependent
on a thousand others, but on the whole he himself sets his
own moral goal and moral direction. The operative element of
all other things is manifested in man as idea; the operative
element in man is the idea which he himself brings forth. The
process that takes place in Nature as a Whole is accomplished
in each single human individuality: it is the creation of an
actuality from out of the idea, man himself being the
creator. For at the basis of his personality there lives the
idea which imparts content to itself. Going beyond Goethe, we
must expand his phrase that Nature “in her creation is
so bounteous that after multifarious plant forms she makes
one wherein all the others are contained, and after
multifarious animals one being who contains them all —
Man.” Nature is so mighty in her creation that she
repeats in each individual human being the process by means
of which she brings forth all creatures directly out of the
idea, inasmuch as moral acts spring from the ideal basis of
the personality. That which man feels to be the objective
basis of his acts is only the result of
“paraphrasing” and misunderstanding of his
own being. Man realises himself in his moral acts. In concise
phrases Max Stirner has described this knowledge in his work:
“The Individual and his Rights.” “I
am the owner of my power; I am this when I know myself as a
unique individual. In the individual the owner returns to his
creative void out of which he was born. Every higher being
above me, be he God, be he Man, weakens the sense of my
individuality and pales before the sunlight of this
consciousness. If I cast my lot upon myself, the individual,
it rests on its own perishable, mortal creator who consumes
himself, and I am able to say: ‘I have cast my lot on
Nothingness.’” But one may reply to Stirner in the
words of Faust to Mephistopheles: “In thy Nothingness I
hope to find the All,” for in my inner being dwells, in
its individual form, the active power whereby Nature creates
the All. So long as man has not perceived this active power
in himself he will appear, in face of it, as Faust appeared
to the Earth Spirit. It will always cry to him in the words:
“Thou'rt like the Spirit whom thou comprehendest, not
me!” Only the perception of the deepest inner life can
conjure forth this Spirit which says of itself:
“In
the tides of Life, in Action's storm,
A fluctuant wave,
A shuttle free,
Birth and the Grave,
An eternal sea,
A weaving, flowing
Life, all-glowing,
Thus at Time's humming loom 'tis my hand prepares
The garment of Life which the Deity weaves.”
In my
Philosophy of Spiritual Activity
[The Philosophy of Spiritual Activity,
Anthroposophical Publishing Company, 46 Gloucester Place, London, W.1.
Price 12/-]
I have tried to show how the knowledge
that in his actions man is dependent upon himself is derived
from the most inward of all experiences, from the perception
of his own being. In 1844 Stirner advocated the view that if
man truly understands himself he can only see the basis of
his activity in himself. In the case of Stirner, however,
this knowledge did not proceed from perception of the most
inward experience but from the feeling of being free and
untrammelled by all-constraining world powers. Stirner does
not go further than to demand freedom; in this region he is
led to lay the sharpest possible emphasis on the fact that
human nature is based upon itself. I have tried to describe
life in freedom on a broader basis by showing what man
discovers when he beholds the foundation of his soul. Goethe
did not attain to the perception of freedom because he had an
aversion to self-knowledge. If this had not been the case the
knowledge of man as a free personality based on itself must
have constituted the summit of his world-conception. We find
the germs of this knowledge everywhere in Goethe, and they
are at the same time the germs of his view of Nature.
* * * * *
In his real studies of Nature Goethe never speaks of
impenetrable courses or of hidden motive forces of phenomena.
He is content with observing the phenomena in their sequence
and explaining them by the help of those elements which in
the act of observation are revealed to the senses and
the mind. On May 5th, 1786, he writes in this sense to
Jacobi; he says that he had the courage “to devote his
whole life to the observation of objects accessible to
him” and of whose essential being he “can hope to
form an adequate idea,” without worrying in the least
about how far he will advance or about what is suitable for
him. A man who believes that he draws near to Divinity in the
single object of Nature does not any longer need to build up
for himself a separate conception of a God existing exterior
to and alongside of the objects. It is only when Goethe
leaves the realm of Nature that his sense for the essential
being of objects no longer asserts itself. His lack of human
self-knowledge leads him then to make statements that cannot
be reconciled either with his innate mode of thought or with
the trend of his Nature studies. Those who are prone to refer
to statements of this kind may assume that Goethe believed in
an anthropomorphous God and in an individual continuation of
that form of the soul's life that is bound up with the
conditions of the physical, bodily organisation. Such a
belief is contradictory to Goethe's Nature studies. The trend
of these studies could never have become what it is if Goethe
had allowed himself to be guided by this belief. In
accordance with the whole character of his Nature studies is
the conception that the true being of the human soul lives in
a supersensible form of existence after the body has been
laid aside. This form of existence necessitates that by
reason of the changed life conditions it will also assume a
mode of consciousness different from that which it possessed
through the physical body. And so the Goethean teaching of
metamorphoses leads also to the perception of metamorphoses
of soul life. But we shall only be able to apprehend this
Goethean idea of Immortality aright if we realise that
Goethe's view of the world could not lead him to conceive of
an unmetamorphosed continuation of that form of spiritual
life that is conditioned by the physical body. Because Goethe
did not attempt a perception of the life of thought in the
sense indicated here he was not induced in the course of his
life to develop in any special degree that idea of
Immortality which would have been the continuation of his
thoughts on Metamorphosis. This is, however, the idea that
would really in truth have followed from his world-conception
in reference to this sphere of knowledge. What Goethe gave as
the expression of a personal feeling in reference to the view
of life of one or another of his contemporaries, or from some
other motive, without thinking of its connection with the
view of the world won from its Nature studies must not be
quoted as characteristic of his idea of Immortality.
When it is a question of a true estimation of some particular
utterance of Goethe within the collective picture of his
world-conception, we must also take into consideration the
fact that the attitude of his soul in the different periods
of his life gives special colouring to such utterances. He
was fully conscious of this variation in the forms in which
his ideas were expressed. When Forster gave it as his view
that the solution of the Faust problem is given in the
words:
“A
good man through obscurest aspirations
Has still an instinct of the one, true way,”
Goethe's reply was: “That would be an explanation.
Faust ends as an old man, and in old age we become
Mystics.” And in the Prose Aphorisms we read:
“There is a specific philosophy answering to every
period of life. The child is a Realist, for it finds itself
as convinced about the existence of the pears and apples as
it is about its own. The youth, assailed by inner passions,
must reckon with himself, must feel his way, and he is
transformed into an idealist. On the other hand, the grown
man has every cause to become a sceptic; he does well to
doubt as to whether the means which he has chosen for his
ends are the right ones. Before acting and in action he has
every cause to keep his intellect mobile in order that he may
not later have to regret a wrong choice. The old man,
however, will always embrace Mysticism; he realises that so
much seems to be dependent on chance; the unreasonable
succeeds, the reasonable strikes amiss, fortune and
misfortune alike balance unexpectedly; thus it is, thus it
was, and old age rests in Him Who is, Who was and Who will
be.”
In this book I have been concerned with Goethe's
world-conception out of which his insight into the life of
Nature has developed, and was the driving force in him, from
the discovery of the intermaxillary bone in man up to the
completion of his Doctrine of Colours. And I think I have
shown that this world-conception corresponds more fully to
his personality as a whole than any compilation of utterances
where it is necessary above all to take into consideration
the colouring given to the thoughts by the mood of youth or
mature age. It is my belief that in his Nature studies Goethe
was guided by a true feeling, although not by a clear
self-knowledge in conformity with ideas, and that he
maintained a free and independent mode of procedure, derived
from the true relationship of human nature to the external
world. Goethe himself realises that there is something
unfinished in his mode of thought. “I was conscious of
great and noble aims, yet I could never understand the
conditions under which I worked; I noted what was lacking in
me, and equally what was exaggerated; therefore I did not
abstain from developing myself from without and from
within. And yet it remained as before. I pursued each aim
with earnestness, intensity and fidelity. I often succeeded
in a complete mastery of refractory conditions, but I was
often frustrated by them because I could not learn how to
yield and to evade. And so my life passed amid action and
enjoyment, suffering and opposition, amid love, contentment,
enmity and displeasure of others. Let those who share the
same destiny behold themselves mirrored here!”
|