Views concerning Nature and the Development of
Living Beings.
The
Doctrine of Metamorphosis.
We cannot understand Goethe's relation to the natural
sciences if we confine ourselves merely to the single
discoveries he made. I take as a guiding point of view for
the study of this relation the words which Goethe wrote to
Knebel from Italy, 18th August, 1787: “After what I
have seen of plants and fishes at Naples and in Sicily I
should be tempted, if I were ten years younger, to make a
journey to India, not in order to discover anything new, but
to observe, in my own way, what has already been
discovered.” It appears to. me to be a question of the
way in which Goethe coordinated the natural phenomena known
to him in a view of Nature in harmony with his mode of
thinking. Even if all his individual discoveries had already
been made, and he had given us nothing but his view of
Nature, this would not detract in the least from the
importance of his Nature studies. I am of the same opinion as
Du Bois-Reymond that “even without Goethe's
participation, science would still be as far advanced as it
is to-day” ... that “the steps attained by him
would have been attained by others sooner or later.”
(Goethe und kein Ende S.31.). I cannot, however, apply these
words, as Du Bois-Reymond does, to the sum-total of Goethe's
work in natural science. I limit them to the individual
discoveries made during the course of his work. In all
probability we should not be without a single one of them
to-day even if Goethe had never occupied himself with botany,
anatomy, and so forth. His view of Nature, however, emanated
from his personality; none other could have achieved it. The
single discoveries as such did not interest him. They
arose of themselves during his studies, because in regard to
the facts in question, views prevailed which were not
reconcilable with his mode of observation. If he could have
built up his views with what natural science had to offer he
would never have occupied himself with detailed studies. He
had to particularize because what was said to him by the
investigators of Nature about the particulars did not
correspond with his demands. The individual discoveries were
made only accidentally, as it were, during the course of
these detailed studies. For instance, the question whether
man, like other animals, has an intermaxillary bone in the
upper jaw-bone did not at first concern him. He was trying to
discover the plan by which Nature develops the series of
animals and, at its summit, Man. He wanted to find the
common archetype which lies at the basis of all animal
species and finally, in its highest perfection, at the basis
of the human species also. The Nature investigators said:
there is a difference between the structure of the animal
body and that of the human body. Animals have the
intermaxillary bone in the upper jaw, man has not. Goethe's
view was that the human physical structure could only be
distinguished from the animal by its degree of perfection,
not details. For, if the latter were the case, there could
not be a common archetype underlying the animal and the human
organisations. He could make nothing of the assertion of the
scientists, and so he sought for the intermaxillary bone in
man — and found it. Something similar to this can be
observed in the case of all his individual discoveries. For
him they are never the end in itself; they had to be made in
order to justify his ideas concerning natural phenomena.
In the realms of organic Nature the important thing in
Goethe's views is the conception he formed of the
nature of life. It is not a question of emphasising
the fact that leaf, calyx, corolla, etc., are plant-organs
identical with each other and unfolding out of a common basic
form. The essential point is Goethe's conception of the whole
plant-nature as a living thing, and how he thought of the
individual parts as proceeding from the whole. His idea of
the nature of the organism is his central, most individual
discovery in the realm of biology. Goethe's basic conviction
was that something can be perceived in the plant and
animal which is not accessible to mere sense observation.
What the bodily eye can observe in the organism appears to
Goethe to be merely the result of a living whole of formative
laws working through one another, laws which are perceptible
only to the ‘spiritual eye.’ He has described what his
spiritual eye perceived in the plant and in the animal. Only
those who are able to see as he did can recapture his idea of
the nature of the organism; those who remain stationary at
what the senses and experiments give, cannot understand him.
When we read his two poems
“The Metamorphosis of Plants,”
and
“The Metamorphosis of Animals,”
it appears at first as if the
words simply led us from one part of the organism to another,
as if the intention was merely to unite external facts
together. If, however, we permeate ourselves with what
hovered before Goethe as the idea of the living being
we feel ourselves transplanted into the sphere of organic
Nature and the conceptions concerning the various organs
develop from out of one central conception.
* * * * *
When Goethe began to make independent reflections upon the
phenomena of Nature it was the concept of life that claimed
his attention above all else. In a letter from the Strasburg
period, 14th July, 1770, he writes of a butterfly: “The
poor creature trembles in the net, and its fairest colours
are rubbed off; even if it is caught uninjured, in the end it
perishes there, stiff and lifeless; the corpse is not the
whole creature. Something else is required, indeed the
essential part, and in this case as in every other, the most
essential part: Life.” It was clear to Goethe from the
beginning that an organism cannot be considered as a dead
product of Nature; that something more exists within it over
and above the forces which also live in inorganic Nature.
When Du Bois-Reymond says that “the purely mechanical
world-construction which to-day constitutes science was no
less obnoxious to the princely poet of Weimar than, in
earlier days, the ‘Système de la Nature’ to Friederike's
friend,” he was undoubtedly right; he was no less right
when he said that “Goethe would have turned away with a
shudder from this world-construction which, with its primeval
generation, borders on the Kant-Laplace theory; from man's
emergence out of chaos as the result of the
mathematically-determined play of atoms from eternity to
eternity; from the icy world-end, from the pictures to which
our race adheres with all the insensibility by means of which
it has accustomed itself to the horrors of railway
travel.” (Goethe und kein Ende. S.35. f.). Naturally
Goethe would have turned away in disgust because he sought
and found a higher concept of the living than that of a
complicated, mathematically-determined mechanism. Only those
who are incapable of grasping a higher concept of this kind
and identify the living with the mechanical because they can
only see the mechanical in the organism, will enthuse over
the mechanical world-construction with its play of atoms, and
regard without feeling the pictures which Du Bois-Reymond
sketches. Those, however, who can assimilate the concept of
the organic in Goethe's sense will dispute its justification
as little as they dispute the existence of the mechanical. We
do not dispute with those who are colour-blind concerning the
world of colours. All views which represent the organic
mechanically incur the judgment which Goethe puts into the
mouth of Mephistopheles:
“Who
would describe and study aught alive.
Seeks first the living spirit thence to drive;
Then are the lifeless fragments in his hand,
There only fails, alas! the spirit band.”
* * * * *
The opportunity of concerning himself more intimately with
plant life came to Goethe when Duke Karl August presented him
with a garden (21st April, 1776). He was also stimulated by
excursions in the Thuringian forest, where he could observe
the living phenomena of lower organisms. Mosses and lichens
claimed his attention. On October 31st he begged Frau von
Stein to give him mosses of all kinds, if possible with the
roots and moist, so that he could use them for observing the
process of propagation. It is important to bear in mind that
at the beginning of his botanical studies Goethe occupied
himself with lower plant forms. He only studied the higher
plants when later he was forming his idea of the archetypal
plant. This was certainly not because the lower kingdom was
strange to him, but because he believed that the secrets of
plant-nature were more clearly manifested in the higher. His
aim was to seek the idea of Nature where it revealed itself
most distinctly and then to descend from the perfect to the
imperfect in order to understand the latter by means of the
former. He did not try to explain the complex by means of the
simple, but to survey it at one glance as a creative whole,
and then to explain the simple and imperfect as a one-sided
development of the complex and perfect. If Nature is
able, after countless plant forms, to create one more which
contains them all, on perceiving this perfect form, the
secret of plant formation must arise for the mind in direct
perception, and then man will easily be able to apply to the
imperfect what he has observed in the perfect. Nature
investigators go the opposite way to work, for they regard
the perfect merely as a mechanical sum-total of simple
processes. They proceed from the simple and derive the
perfect from it.
When Goethe looked around for a scientific guide in his
botanical studies he could find no other than Linnæus.
We first learn of his study of Linnæus from his letters
to Frau von Stein in the year 1782. The earnestness with
which Goethe pursued his studies in natural science is shown
by the interest he took in the writings of Linnæus. He
admits that after Shakespeare and Spinoza he was influenced
most strongly by Linnæus. But how little could
Linnæus satisfy him! Goethe wanted to observe the
different plant forms in order to know the common principle
that lived in them. He tried to discover what it is that
makes all these forms into plants. Linnæus was satisfied
with classifying the manifold plant forms in a definite order
and describing them. Here Goethe's naive, unbiased
observation of Nature, in one special instance, came into
contact with the scientific mode of thought that was
influenced by a one-sided conception of Platonism. This mode
of thought sees in the separate forms manifestations of
original, co-existing Platonic Ideas, or creative thoughts.
Goethe sees in the individual formation only one special form
of an ideal archetypal being which lives in all forms. The
aim of the former mode of thought is to distinguish the
separate forms with the greatest possible exactitude in order
to discern the manifoldness of the ideal forms or of the plan
of creation; Goethe's aim is to explain the manifoldness of
the particular from out of the original unity. That many
things are present in manifold forms is clearly evident to
the former mode of thought, because for it the ideal
archetypes are already manifold. This is not evident to
Goethe, for according to his view the many only belong
together when a unity reveals itself in them. Goethe
therefore says that what Linnæus “sought to hold
forcibly asunder, had to strive for union, in order to
satisfy the innermost need of my being.” Linnæus
simply accepts the existing forms without asking how they
have arisen from a basic form. “We count as many
species as there are different forms that have been created
in principle.” This is a basic statement. Goethe sought
the active element in the plant kingdom that creates the
individual through the specific modifications of the
basic form.
In Rousseau Goethe found a more naïve relationship to
the plant world than was the case with Linnæus. He
writes to Karl August, 16th June, 1782: “In Rousseau's
Works one finds the most delightful letters on botany in
which he gives a very clear and charming exposition of this
science to a lady. It is a fine example of the way one ought
to give instruction, and is a supplement to Emil. It makes me
want to recommend the beautiful kingdom of flowers anew to my
friends of the fair sex.” In the
“History of my Botanical Studies”
Goethe tells us what attracted him to Rousseau's botanical ideas:
“His relation to plant lovers and connoisseurs, specially to
the Duchess of Portland, may have widened his penetrating sight,
and a spirit such as his, which felt called to prescribe law
and order to nations, was forced to suppose that in the
immeasurable kingdom of plants no such great diversity of
forms could appear without a basic law, be it ever so
concealed, which brings them back collectively to a
Unity.” Goethe was seeking for a fundamental law which
leads back the manifold to the unity from which it has
originally proceeded.
Two works of Freiherr von Gleichen, called
“Russwurm,” came at that time to Goethe's
knowledge. Both of them deal with the life of plants in a
manner which proved fruitful for him; they are
‘Das Neueste aus dem Reiche der Pflanzen’
(Nürnburg, 1764), and
‘Auserlesene Mikroscopische Entdeckungen
bet den Pflanzen’
(Nürnburg, 1777/1781.)
These books deal with the processes of fructification in
plants; pollen, stamens and pistils are minutely described
and the processes of fructification presented in
well-executed diagrams. Goethe himself now makes attempts to
observe with his own eyes the results described by
Gleichen-Russwurm. He writes to Frau von Stein, 12th Jan.,
1785: “Now that Spring is approaching my microscope is
set up in order to observe and check the experiments of
Gleichen-Russwurm.” At the same time Goethe studied the
nature of the seed, as may be gathered from an account which
he gives to Knebel, 2nd April, 1785: “I have reflected
on the seed substance as far as my experiences extend.”
These observations of Goethe only appear in the right light
when one considers that even at that time he did not stop at
them, but tried to acquire a general perception of
natural processes which should serve to support and
strengthen them. On April 8th of the same year he tells
Knebel that he is not merely observing facts, but that he has
also made “fine combinations” of these facts.
* * * * *
The share Goethe took in Lavater's great work,
“Physiognomic Fragments for the furtherance of Human
Knowledge and Human Love,”
which appeared in the years 1775 to 1778, had a considerable
influence on the development of his ideas concerning the workings
of organic Nature. He himself contributed to this work, and his
later mode of regarding organic Nature is already foreshadowed
in the way he expresses himself in these contributions. Lavater
goes no further than treating the form of the human organism
as the expression of the soul. He wanted to indicate the
character of soul from the forms of the body. Goethe began
even then to observe the external form in itself, to study
its own laws and formative force. He began at the same time
to study the writings of Aristotle on physiognomy and
endeavoured, on the basis of the study of the organic form,
to confirm the distinction between man and the animals. He
finds this in the prominence of the head which is determined
by the human structure as a whole, and in the perfect
development of the human brain to which all parts point
as to an organ by which they are determined. In the animal,
on the other hand, the head is merely appended to the spine;
the brain and spinal cord comprise no more than is absolutely
necessary for the execution of subordinate life-principles
and sense-activities pure and simple. Goethe was already then
seeking for the distinction between man and the animals, not
in any one detail, but in the different degrees of perfection
which the same basic form attains in one case or the other.
Already there hovers before him the picture of a type which
occurs both in the animal and in man, but which is developed
in the former in such a way that the entire structure
subserves animal functions, whereas in the latter the
structure furnishes the scaffolding for the development of
the spirit.
Goethe's specific studies in anatomy grew out of such
considerations. On Jan. 22nd, 1776, he writes to Lavater:
“The Duke has sent me six skulls, and I have made some
magnificent observations which are at your service if you
have not already found the same things without me.” In
Goethe's Diary, under the date, 15th Oct., 1781, we read that
he studied Anatomy in Jena with Einsiedel, and in the same
year began to enter more deeply into this science under the
guidance of Loder. He speaks of this in letters to Frau von
Stein, 29th Oct., and to the Duke, 4th Nov., 1781. He also
had the intention of “explaining the skeleton” to
the young people at the Drawing Academy, “and guiding
them to a knowledge of the human body.” “I do
it,” he says, “for my own sake as well as for
theirs; the method I have chosen will give them this winter a
real acquaintance with the basic structures of the
body.” The Diary shows that these lectures were, in
fact, given. During this time he also had many conversations
with Loder concerning the structure of the human body. Again
it is his general view of Nature which is the motive force
and the real aim of these studies. He treats “the bones
as a text to which all life and everything human may be
appended.” (Letters to Lavater and Marck, 14th Nov.,
1781.)
Goethe's mind was occupied at that time with conceptions
relating to the workings of organic Nature and the connection
between human and animal development. That the human form is
simply the highest stage of the animal, and that man produces
the moral world out of himself as a result of this more
perfect stage of animal life, is an idea which is already
expressed in the ode
“The Divine”
— written during the year 1782. “Let man
be noble, helpful and good; for that alone distinguishes him
from all the beings known unto us. According to laws mighty,
rigid, eternal, must all we mortals complete the orbit of our
existence.” The “eternal, rigid laws” work
in man just as they work in the rest of the world of
organisms; in him alone they reach a perfection which makes
it possible for him to be “noble, helpful and
good.”
While such ideas were establishing themselves in Goethe's
being more and more firmly Herder was working at his
“Ideas for a Philosophy of the History of
Mankind.” All the thoughts of this book were discussed
by the two men. Goethe was satisfied with Herder's
comprehension of Nature; it harmonised with his own
conceptions. Frau von Stein writes to Knebel, 1st May, 1784:
“Herder's work makes it probable that we were first
plants and animals. ... Goethe is now brooding profoundly
over these things and whatever has passed through his mind
becomes supremely interesting.” Goethe's words to
Knebel, 8th Dec., 1783, afford the justification for arriving
at his ideas from Herder's. “Herder is writing a
Philosophy of History, fundamentally new, as you may
well imagine. We read the first chapters together the day
before yesterday — and very excellent they are.”
Sentences such as the following entirely harmonise with
Goethe's mode of thought: “The human race is the great
coalescence of lower organic forces.” “And so we
assume that man is the central creation among animals,
i.e., the developed form wherein the features of all
species around him are summed up superbly.” The view of
anatomists at that time that the tiny bone which animals have
in the upper jaw, the intermaxillary bone which contains the
upper incisors, is lacking in man, was of course
irreconcilable with such conceptions. Sommering, one of the
most noted Anatomists of the time, writes to Merck, 8th Oct.,
1782: “I wish you had consulted Blumenbach on the
subject of the os intermaxillane which,
ceteris paribus, is the only bone which
all animals possess from the apes onward, including even the
orang-utan, but which is never to be found in man; with the
exception of this bone there is nothing in man which cannot
be attributed to the animals. I am sending you therefore the
head of a hind in order to convince you that this
os intermaxillane, as Blumenbach, or
os incis as Campa calls it, also exists in
animals which have no incisors.” That was the general
view of the time. Even the famous Camper, for whom Merck and
Goethe had the deepest respect, admitted it. The fact that
the intermaxillary bone in man coalesces left and right with
the upper jaw bone without any clear demarcation in the
normally developed individual, led to this view. If the
learned men were correct in this it would be impossible to
affirm the existence of a common archetype for the structure
of the animal and human organism; a boundary between the two
forms would have to be assumed. Man would not be created
according to the archetype which lies at the basis of the
animal. Goethe had to remove this obstacle to his
world-conception. This he succeeded in doing, in conjunction
with Loder, in the Spring of 1784. Goethe proceeded according
to his general principle that Nature has no secret which
“she does not somewhere place openly before the eye of
the attentive observer.” He found the demarcation
between upper jaw and intermaxillary bone actually existing
in some abnormally developed skulls. He joyfully announced
his discovery to Herder and Frau von Stein (27th March). To
Herder he wrote: “It should heartily please you also,
for it is like the keystone to man; it is not lacking;
it is there! But how?” “I have thought of it in
connection with your ‘Whole’ and it will indeed be a fair
link in the chain.” When Goethe sent the treatise he
had written on the subject to Knebel in Nov., 1784, he
indicated the significance which he attributed to this
discovery in his whole world of ideas by the words: “I
have refrained from pointing to the logical outcome which
Herder already indicates in his ideas, that the distinction
between man and the animal is not to be looked for in any
single detail.” Goethe could gain confidence in his
view of Nature only when the erroneous view about this fatal
little bone had been rejected. He gradually found the courage
to extend to all kingdoms of Nature, to her whole realm, his
ideas concerning the manner in which, playing as it were with
one basic form, she produces life in all its diversity. In
this sense he writes to Frau von Stein in the year 1786.
* * * * *
The book of Nature becomes more and more legible to Goethe
after he has deciphered the one letter. “My long
‘spelling out’ has helped me; now at last it works, and my
silent joy is inexpressible.” He writes thus to Frau
von Stein, 15th May, 1785. He now regards himself capable of
writing a small botanical treatise for Knebel. Their journey
together to Karlsbad, in 1785, becomes a formal journey of
botanical study. After their return the kingdom of fungi,
mosses, lichens and algae were studied with the help of
Linnæus. He informs Frau von Stein, 9th November:
“I continue to read Linnæus, indeed I must, for I
have no other book with me: it is the best way of reading a
book conscientiously and I must cultivate the practice, for
it is not easy for me to read a book to the end. This book is
not compiled for reading but for repeated study, and is of
the very greatest service to me because I have thought for
myself on most of the points.” During these studies the
basic form out of which Nature fashions all the manifold
plant forms assumes separate contours in his mind, even if
they are not yet quite definite. In a letter to Frau von
Stein, 9th July, 1786, we find these words: “It is a
perception of the form with which Nature is, as it were,
always playing, and in her play producing life in its
diversity.”
* * * * *
In April and May, 1786, Goethe made microscopical
observations of lower organisms which develop in infusions of
different substances — plantain pulp, cactus, truffles,
peppercorn, tea, beer, and so on. He carefully noted the
processes which he perceived in these organisms and prepared
drawings of them. It is apparent also from these notes that
Goethe did not try to approach the knowledge of life through
such observation of the lower and simpler organisms. It is
quite apparent that he thought he could grasp the essential
features of life-processes in the higher organisms just as
well as in the lower. He is of the opinion that in the
infusoria the same kind of law repeats itself as the eye of
the mind perceives, for instance, in the dog. Observation
through the microscope only yields information of
processes which are, in miniature, what the unaided eye sees
on a larger scale. It merely affords an enrichment of
sense-experiences. The essential nature of life reveals
itself to a higher kind of perception, and not to observation
that merely traces to their minutest details, processes that
are accessible to the senses. Goethe seeks to cognise this
essential nature of life through the observation of higher
plants and animals. He would undoubtedly have sought this
knowledge in the same way, even if in his age the anatomy of
plants and animals had advanced as far as it has to-day. If
Goethe had been able to observe the cells out of which the
bodies of plants and animals are built he would have asserted
that these elementary organic forms reveal the same
conformity to law as is to be perceived in the most complex.
He would have explained the phenomena in these minute
entities by means of the same ideas by which he interpreted
the life-processes of higher organisms. It is in Italy that
Goethe first finds the thought which solves the riddle facing
him in organic development and metamorphosis. On September
3rd he leaves Karlsbad for the South. In a few but
significant sentences he describes in the
History of my Botanical Studies
the thoughts stimulated in him by the
observation of the plant world up to the moment when, in
Sicily, a clear conception comes to him of how it is that
“a fortunate mobility and plasticity is bestowed on
plant forms, together with a strong generic and specific
tenacity, so that they can adapt themselves to the many
conditions working upon them over the face of the earth and
develop and transform themselves accordingly.” The
“variability of plant forms” was revealed to him
as he was crossing the Alps, in the Botanic Gardens of Padua,
and in other places. “Whereas in the lower regions
branches and stalks were stronger and more bounteous in sap,
the buds in closer juxtaposition, and the leaves broader, the
higher one got on the mountains the stalks and branches
became more fragile, the buds were at greater intervals, and
the leaves more lancelate. I noticed this in the case of a
willow and of a gentian, and convinced myself that it was not
a case of different species. So also near the Walchensee I
noticed longer and thinner rushes than in the lowlands”
(Italian Journey, 8th September).
On October 8th, by the seashore in Venice, he finds different plants
wherein the relation between the organic and its environment becomes
specially clear to him. “These plants are all both
robust and virile, succulent and hardy, and it is apparent
that the old salt of the sandy soil, and still more the
saline air, gives them this characteristic; they are swollen
with juices like water-plants; they are fleshy and hardy like
mountain-plants; if their edges have the tendency to form
prickles, like thistles, they are exceedingly strong and
highly pointed. I found such leaves on bushes; they appeared
to me to resemble our harmless coltsfoot, but here they were
armed with sharp weapons, the leaves like leather, as also
the seed capsules and the stalk, everything very thick and
succulent.” (Italian Journey). In the Botanical
Gardens at Padua the thought of how all plant-forms could be
developed out of one, assumes more definite shape in Goethe's
mind. In November he writes to Knebel: “The little
botany I know has for the first time become a pleasure to me
in this land with its brighter, less sporadic vegetation. I
have already made fine general observations which will
subsequently be acceptable to you also.” On 25th March,
1787, there comes to him “considerable illumination
regarding botanical phenomena.” He begs that
“Herder may be told that he is very near to finding the
archetypal plant.” Only he fears “no one will be
willing to recognise the rest of the plant world
therein.” On April 17th he goes to the Public Gardens
“with a firm, calm determination to continue his
poetical dreams.” But all of a sudden the plant-nature
catches him up like a ghost. “The many plants which I
was formerly only accustomed to see in pots and tubs, indeed
only behind glass windows for most of the year, stand here
fresh and gay under the open sky, and thus fulfilling their
destiny, they become clearer to us. Amongst so many
formations, some new, some familiar, the old fancy again
occurred to me as to whether I could not discover among the
multitude the archetypal plant. There must be such a thing:
how otherwise should I recognise this or that form to be a
plant if they were not all fashioned after one type?”
He tries hard to distinguish the divergent forms, but his
thoughts are guided ever and again to an archetype that lies
at the basis of them all. Goethe starts a Botanical Diary in
which he notes all his experiences and reflections on the
subject of the plant world during the journey. (Goethe's
Werke. Weimar Edition Bd. 17. S.273). These diary leaves show
how untiringly he is occupied in seeking out specimens of
plants fitted to lead him to the laws of growth and
reproduction. When he thinks he is on the track of any law he
first puts it into hypothetical form, in order to confirm it
in the course of his further experiences. He makes careful
notes of the processes of generation, of fructification, of
growth. More and more it dawns upon him that the leaf is the
basic organ of plants, and that the forms of all other plant
organs are best understood if they are considered as
transformed leaves. He writes in his Diary:
“Hypothesis: all is leaf, and through this simplicity
the greatest diversity becomes possible.” And on May
17th he writes to Herder: “I must further confide to
you that I am very near to the secret of plant generation and
organisation, and that it is the simplest thing conceivable.
Under this sky the finest observations are possible. I have
found clearly and indubitably the cardinal point where the
germ is concealed: already I see everything else in its
entirety, and only a few details have yet to become more
definite. The archetypal plant is the most wonderful
creation in the world, for which Nature herself should envy
me. With this model, and its key, one can invent plants ad
infinitum, and consequently, that is to say, plants which
could exist, even if they do not exist, and are not as it
were artistic or poetic shadows and fancies but have an inner
truth and necessity. The same law may be applied to all else
that lives. ... Forwards and backwards the plant is ever only
leaf, so indissolubly united with the future germ that one
cannot think of the one without the other. To grasp such a
concept, to sustain it, to discover it in Nature, is a task
which places us in a condition that is almost painful,
despite its joy.” (Italian Journey).
* * * * *
For an explanation of the phenomena of life Goethe takes a
path entirely different from those which scientists usually
travel. Investigators of Nature may be divided into two
classes. There are those who advocate the existence of a
life-force working in organic Nature, and this life-force
represents a special, higher form of force compared with
other Natural causes. Just as the forces of gravity, chemical
attraction and repulsion, magnetism, and so on, exist, so
there must also exist a life-force which brings about such an
interaction in the substances of the organism, that it can
maintain itself, grow, nourish and propagate itself. These
investigators of Nature say: In the organism work the
same forces as in the rest of Nature, but they do not work as
in a lifeless machine. They are taken up, as it were, by the
life-force and raised to a higher stage of activity. Other
investigators oppose this view, believing that no special
force works in the organism. They regard the phenomena of
life as more highly complicated chemical and physical
processes and hope that some time it will be possible to
explain an organism just as it is possible to explain a
machine, by reducing it to the workings of inorganic forces.
The first view is described as the theory of vitalism, the
second as mechanistic theory. Goethe's mode of conception
differs essentially from both. It appears to him self-evident
that in the organism something is active as well as the
forces of inorganic Nature. He cannot admit a mechanical
explanation of living phenomena. Just as little does he seek
a special life-force in order to explain the activities in an
organism. He is convinced that for the understanding of
living processes there must be a perception of a kind other
than that through which the phenomena of inorganic Nature are
perceived. Those who decide in favour of the assumption of a
life-force realise, it is true, that organic activities are
not mechanical, but at the same time they are not able to
develop in themselves that other kind of perception by means
of which the organic could be understood. The conception of
the life-force remains obscure and indefinite. A more recent
adherent of the theory of vitalism, Gustav Bunge, thinks that
“All the riddles of life are contained in the tiniest
cell, and with the existing means at our disposal we have
already reached the boundary line.” (Vitalismus und
Mechanismus, Leipsig. 1886, S.17). One may answer,
entirely in the sense of Goethe's mode of thinking:
“That power of perception which only cognises the
nature of inorganic phenomena has arrived at the boundary
which must be crossed in order to grasp what is
living.” This power of perception, however, will never
find within its sphere the means adequate to explain the life
of even the tiniest cell. Just as the eye is necessary for
the perception of colour phenomena, so the understanding of
life is dependent on the power of perceiving directly in the
sensible a supersensible element. This supersensible element
will always escape one who only directs his senses to organic
forms. Goethe seeks to animate the sensible perception of the
plant forms in a higher sense and to represent to himself the
sensible form of a supersensible archetypal plant.
(Geschichte meines botanischen Studiums.
Kürschner Nat. Lit. Bd. 33. S.80).
The Vitalist takes refuge in the empty concept of the
“life-force” because he simply does not see
anything that his senses cannot perceive in the organism;
Goethe sees the sensible permeated by a supersensible
element, in the same sense as a coloured surface is permeated
by colour.
The followers of the mechanistic theory hold the view that
some day it will be possible to produce living substances
artificially from inorganic matter. They say that not many
years ago it was maintained that substances existed in the
organism which could only arise through the activity of the
life-force and not artificially. To-day it is already
possible to produce some of the substances artificially in
the laboratory. Similarly, it may one day be possible to
produce a living albumen, which is the basic substance of the
simplest organism, out of carbonic acid, ammonia, water and
salts. The mechanists think that this will provide the
irrefutable proof that life is nothing more than a
combination of inorganic processes — the organism just
a machine that has arisen in a natural way.
From the standpoint of Goethe's world-conception it may be
said that the mechanists speak of substances and forces in a
way that has no justification in experience. And people have
grown so accustomed to speak in this way that it becomes very
difficult to maintain the clear pronouncements of experience
in the face of such concepts. Let us, however, consider,
without bias, a process of the external world. I/it us take a
quantity of water at a definite temperature. How do we know
anything about this water? We observe it, notice that it
takes up space and is enclosed within definite boundaries. We
put a finger or a thermometer into it and find that it has a
definite degree of warmth. We press against the surface and
find that it is fluid. This is what the senses tell us
concerning the condition of the water. Now let us heat the
water. It will boil and finally change into steam. Again one
can acquire knowledge through sense-perception of the
constitution of the substance, of the steam into which the
water has changed. Instead of heating the water, it can be
subjected to an electric current, under certain conditions.
It changes into two substances, hydrogen and oxygen. We can
learn about the nature of these two substances also through
the senses. Thus in the corporeal world we perceive states,
and observe at the same time that these states can, under
certain conditions, pass over into others. The senses inform
us of these states. When we speak of something else besides
states which change we no longer keep to pure facts, but we
add concepts to these. When it is said that the oxygen and
the hydrogen which have developed out of the water as a
result of the electric current were already contained in the
water, but so closely united that they could not be perceived
individually, a concept has been added to the perception
— a concept by means of which the development of the
two bodies out of the one is explained. When it is further
maintained that oxygen and hydrogen are substances, as is
shown by the fact that names have been given to them, again a
concept has been added to what has been perceived. For, in
reality, in the space occupied by the oxygen, all we can
perceive is a sum of states. To these states we add, in
thought, the substance to which they are supposed to belong.
The substantiality of the oxygen and hydrogen that is
conceived of as already existing in water is something that
is added in thought to the content of perception. If we
combine hydrogen and oxygen into water by a chemical process
we can observe that one collection of states passes over into
another. When we say: “the two simple substances have
united to form a compound,” we have there attempted to
give a conceptual exposition of the content of observation.
The idea “substance” receives its content, not
from perception but from thought. The same thing holds good
with “force” as with “substance.” We
see a stone fall to the earth. What is the content of
perception? A sum-total of sense impressions, states, which
appear at successive places. We try to explain this change in
the sense-world and say: “the earth attracts the stone;
it has a ‘force’ by which it draws the stone to
itself.” Again our mind has added a conception to the
actuality and given it a content which does not arise out of
perception. We do not perceive substances and forces, but
states and their transitions into each other. These changes
of states are explained by adding concepts to perceptions.
Let us conceive of a being who could perceive oxygen and
hydrogen but not water. If we combined oxygen and hydrogen
into water before the eyes of such a being the states it
perceived in the two substances would disappear into
nothingness. If we now described the states which we perceive
in water, such a being could form no idea of them. This
proves that in the perceptual contents of hydrogen and oxygen
there is nothing from which the perceptual content
water can be derived. When one substance arises out of
two or more different ones that means: Two or more perceptual
contents have transformed themselves into a content which is
connected with them but is absolutely new. What would have
been achieved if it were found possible to combine carbonic
acid, ammonia, water and salt into a living albumenous
substance in the laboratory? We should know that the
perceptual content of many substances could combine into one
perceptual content. But this latter perceptual content cannot
in any sense be derived out of the former. The state of
living albumen can only be observed in itself; it cannot be
developed out of the states of carbonic acid, ammonia, water
and salt. In the organism we have something wholly different
from the inorganic constituents out of which it can be
formed. The sensible contents of perception change into
sensible-supersensible when the living being arises. And
those who have not the power to form sensible-supersensible
conceptions can as little know anything of the nature of an
organism as they could experience water if the sensible
perception of it were inaccessible to them.
* * * * *
In his studies of the plant and animal world Goethe tried to
conceive of germination, growth, transformations of organs,
nutrition and reproduction of the organism, as
sensible-supersensible processes. He perceived that this
sensible-supersensible process is the same, ideally,
in all plants and that it only assumes different forms in its
outer manifestation. He was able to establish the same thing
concerning the animal world. When man has formed in himself
the idea of the sensible-supersensible archetypal plant he
will find this again in all single plant-forms. Diversity
arises because things, the same ideally, can exist in
the perceptual world in different forms. The single organism
consists of organs which can be traced back to one basic
organ. The basic organ of the plant is the leaf with the
nodes from which it develops. This organ assumes different
forms in external appearance: cotyledon, foliage, leaf,
sepal, petal, etc. “The plant may sprout, blossom, or
bear fruit, but it is always the same organs which in
manifold conditions and under frequently changed forms fulfil
Nature's prescription.”
* * * * *
In order to get a complete picture of the archetypal plant
Goethe had to follow, in general, the forms which the basic
organ passes through in the progress of the growth of the
plant from germination to the ripening of the seed. In the
beginning of its development the whole plant-form rests
in the seed. In this the archetypal plant has assumed a form,
through which it conceals, as it were, its ideal content in
outward appearance.
“Simply
slumbered the force in the seed; a germ of the future
Peacefully locked in itself, 'neath the integument lay,
Leaf and root and bud, still void of colour and shapeless;
Thus does the kernel, while dry, cover that motionless life.
Upward then strives it to swell, in gentle moisture confiding,
And from the night where it dwelt, straightway ascendeth
to light.”
(Translation
by A. E. Bowring).
Out of the seed the plant develops its primary organs, the
cotyledons, after it “has left behind its
coverings more or less in the earth” and has
established “the root in the soil.” And now, in
the further course of growth, impulse follows impulse, nodes
upon nodes are piled one above the other, and at each node we
have a leaf.
The leaves appear in different forms, the lower still simple,
the upper much indented, notched, and composed of many tiny
leaves. The archetypal plant at this stage of development
spreads out its sensible-supersensible content in space
as external sense appearance. Goethe imagines that the leaves
owe their progressive development and improvement to the
light and the air. “When we find these cotyledons
produced in the enclosing seed-walls, filled as it were with
a crude sap, almost entirely unorganised, or at any rate only
crudely organised and unformed, so do we find the leaves of
those plants which grow under water more crudely organised
than others that are exposed to the free air; indeed even the
same plant species develops smoother and less perfect leaves
if it grows in deep, moist places; whereas, on the contrary,
in higher regions it produces fibrous and more finely
developed leaves, provided with tiny hairs” (Goethe's
Werke, Kürschner Nat. Lit. Bd. 33. S25.).
In the second epoch of growth the plant again contracts into
a narrower space what was previously spread out.
“Less
abundantly yielding the sap, contracting the vessels,
So that the figure 'ere long gentler effects doth disclose.
Soon and in silence is checked the growth of the vigorous branches
And the rib of the stalk fuller becometh in form.
Leafless however and quick the tenderer stem then upspringeth,
And a miraculous sight doth the observer enchant.
Ranged in a circle, in numbers that now are small, and now countless,
Gather the smaller-sized leaves, close by the side of their like,
And as the perfectest type, brilliant-hued coronals form.”
(Translation
by A. E. Bowring).
In the calyx the plant form draws itself together, and in the
corolla again spreads itself out. The next contraction
follows in the pistils and stamens, the organs of generation.
In the previous periods of growth the formative force of the
plant developed uniformly as the impulse to repeat the basic
form. At this stage of contraction the same force distributes
itself into two organs. What is separated seeks to re-unite.
This happens in the process of fructification. The male
pollen existing in the stamens unites with the female
substance in the pistils, and the germ of a new plant arises.
Goethe calls this fructification, a spiritual
anastomosis, and sees in it only another form of the
process which occurs in the development from one node to
another. “In all bodies which we call living we observe
the force to produce its like. When we perceive this force
divided, we speak of the two sexes.”
The plant produces its like from node to node, for nodes and
leaf are the simple form of the archetypal plant. In this
form production means growth. If this reproductive force is
divided among two organs we speak of two sexes. In this sense
Goethe believes he has brought the concepts of growth and
generation nearer to each other. At the stage of
fruit-formation the plant attains its final expansion; in the
seed it appears again contracted. In these six steps Nature
accomplishes a cycle of plant development, and begins the
whole process over again. Goethe sees in the seed only
another form of the nodule which develops on the leaves. The
shoots developing out of the node are complete plants which
rest on a mother-plant instead of in the earth. The
conception of the basic organ transforming itself
stage by stage, as on a “spiritual
ladder” from seed to fruit is the idea of the
archetypal plant. In order to prove to sense perception,
as it were, the transforming power of the basic organ,
Nature, under certain conditions, at one stage allows another
organ to develop instead of the one that should arise in
conformity with the regular course of growth. In the double
poppy, for example, petals appear in the lilace where the
stamens should arise. The organ destined ideally to
become a stamen has become a petal. In the organ that has a
definite form in the regular course of plant development
there is the possibility to assume another.
As an illustration of his idea of the archetypal plant Goethe
considers the bryophyllum calycinum, a
plant species which was brought to Calcutta from the Molucca
Islands, and thence came to Europe. Out of the notches in the
fleshy leaves these plants develop fresh plantlets, which
grow to complete plants after their detachment. In this
process, sensibly and visibly presented, Goethe sees that
ideally a whole plant slumbers in the leaf. (Goethe's
Notes on Bryophyllum Calycinum. Weimar
Edition, Part 2. Vol. VII.).
One who develops the idea of the archetypal plant in himself,
and keeps it so plastic that he can think of it in all
possible forms which its content permits, can explain all
formations in the plant kingdom by its help. He will
understand the development of the individual plant, but he
will also find that all sexes, species, and varieties are
fashioned according to this archetype. Goethe developed these
views in Italy and recorded them in his work entitled
Versuch, die Metamorphose der Pflanzen zu erklären
which appeared in 1790.
* * * * *
In Italy Goethe also makes progress in the development
of his ideas concerning the human organism. On January 20th
he writes to Knebel: “As regards anatomy, I have only a
very indifferent preparation, and it is not without some
labour that I have succeeded in acquiring a certain knowledge
of the human frame. Constant examination of the stages here
leads one to a higher understanding. In our Academy of
Medicine and Surgery it is merely a question of knowing the
part, and for this a wretched muscle serves just as well. But
in Rome the parts mean nothing unless at the same time they
present a noble form. In the great hospital San Spirito they
have prepared, for the sake of artists, a very beautiful body
displaying the muscles, so that one marvels at its beauty. It
could really pass for some flayed demi-god, for a Marsyas.
Thus one does not study the skeleton as an artificially
arranged mask of bones, but rather after the example of the
ancients, with the ligaments by which it receives life and
movement.”
After his return from Italy Goethe applied himself
industriously to the pursuit of anatomical studies. He feels
compelled to discover the formative laws of the animal form
just as he had succeeded in doing in the case of the plant.
He is convinced that the uniformity of the animal
organisation is also based on a fundamental organ which can
assume different forms in its external manifestation. When
the idea of the basic organ is concealed the organ itself has
an undeveloped appearance. Here we have the simpler organs of
animals: when the idea is master of the substance, forming
the substance into a perfect likeness of itself, the higher,
nobler organs arise. That which is present ideally in
the simpler organs manifests itself externally in the higher.
Goethe did not succeed in apprehending in a single idea the
law of the whole animal form as he did for the plant form. He
found the formative law for one part only of this animal form
— for the spinal cord and brain, with the bones
enclosing these organs. He sees in the brain a higher
development of the spinal cord. He regards each nerve centre
of the ganglia as a brain which has remained at a lower stage
(Weimar Edition, Part 2, Vol. 8.).
He explains the skull-bones enclosing the brain as
transformations of the vertebrae surrounding the spinal cord.
It had occurred to him previously that he must regard the
posterior cranial bones (occipital, posterior and anterior
sphenoid bones) as three transformed vertebrae; he maintains
the same thing in regard to the anterior cranial bones, when
in the year 1790 he finds in the sands of the Lido a sheep's
skull, which is, by great good fortune, cracked in such a way
that three vertebrae are made visible to immediate sense
perception in a transformed shape in the hard palate —
the upper jaw-bone, and the intermaxillary bone.
In Goethe's time the anatomy of animals had not yet advanced
so far that he was able to cite a living being which really
has vertebrae in place of developed cranial bones, and which
thus presents in sensible form that which only exists
ideally in developed animals. The investigations of
Karl Gegenbauer, published in the year 1872, made it possible
to instance such an animal form. Primitive fish, or
selachians, have cranial bones and a brain which are
obviously terminal members of the vertebral column and spinal
cord. According to this discovery a greater number of
vertebrae than Goethe supposed, at least nine, appear to have
entered into the head formation. This error in the number of
vertebrae, and, in addition, the fact that in the embryonic
condition the skull of higher animals shows no trace of being
composed of vertebral parts but develops out of a single
cartilaginous vesicle, has been adduced as evidence against
the value of Goethe's idea concerning the transformation of
the spinal cord and vertebrae. It is indeed admitted that the
skull has originated from vertebrae, but it is denied that
the cranial bones, in the form in which they appear in the
higher animals, are transformed vertebrae. It is said that a
complete amalgamation of vertebrae into a cartilaginous
vesicle has taken place, and that in this amalgamation the
original vertebral structure has entirely disappeared. The
bony forms which are to be perceived in the higher animals
have developed out of this cartilaginous capsule. These forms
have not developed in accordance with the archetype of the
vertebra, but in accordance with the tasks they have to
fulfil in the developed head. So that in seeking an
explanation of the forms of any cranial bone the question is
not, “How has a vertebra been transformed in order to
become the bones of the head?” — but “What
conditions have led to this or that bony form
separating out of the simple cartilaginous capsule?” It
is believed that there is a development of new forms, in
conformity with new formative laws, after the original
vertebral form has passed over into an unorganised capsule. A
contradiction between this view and Goethe's can only be
found from the standpoint of “fact-fanaticism.”
The vertebral structure that is no longer sensibly
perceptible in the cartilaginous capsule of the skull does
nevertheless exist in it ideally and re-appears as
soon as the conditions for this appearance are there.
In the cartilaginous skull-capsule the idea of the vertebral
basic organ is concealed within matter; in the developed
cranial bones it re-appears in outer manifestation.
* * * * *
Goethe hopes that the formative laws of the other parts of
the animal organism will be revealed to him in the same way
as was the case with those of brain, spinal cord, and their
enveloping organs. With regard to the Lido discovery he
informs Herder, through Frau von Kalb, April 30th, that he
“has come much closer to the animal form and its many
transformations and indeed through a most curious
accident.” He believes himself to be so near his goal
that he wants to complete, in the very year of his discovery,
a work on animal development which may be placed side by side
with the “Metamorphosis of Plants”
(Correspondence with Knebel, pp 98.).
During his travels in Silesia, July, 1790, Goethe pursues
studies in Comparative Anatomy and begins to write an Essay
On the Form of Animals
(Weimar Edition, Part 2, Vol. 8, p. 261.).
He did not succeed in advancing from this happy
starting point to the formative laws of the whole animal
form. He made many an attempt to find the Type of the animal
form, but nothing analogous to the idea of the
archetypal plant resulted. He compares the animals with
each other, and with man, and seeks to obtain a general
picture of the animal structure, according to which, as a
model, Nature fashions the individual forms. This general
picture of the animal type is not a living conception that is
filled with a content in accordance with the basic laws of
animal formation, and thus recreates, as it were, the
archetypal animal of Nature. It is only a general concept
that has been abstracted from the special appearances.
It confirms the existence of the common element in the
manifold animal forms, but it does not contain the law of
animal nature.
“All
the members develop according to Laws Eternal.
And the rarest of forms secretly preserves the Archetype.”
(The Metamorphosis of Animals.)
Goethe could not evolve a uniform conception of how the
archetype, through the transformation according to law of a
basic member, develops as the many-membered archetypal form
of the animal organism. The Essays on
The Form of Animals
and the
Sketch of Comparative Anatomy proceeding from Osteology,
which were written in Jena in
1795, as well as the later and more detailed work,
Lectures on the first three Chapters of an Outline of a
General Introduction to Comparative Anatomy,
only contain indications as to how the animals are to be compared
suitably in order to obtain a general scheme according to which
the creative power “produces and develops organic
beings,” in accordance with which these
descriptions are worked out and to which the most
diverse forms are to be traced back, since such a norm may be
abstracted from the forms of different animals. In the case
of plants, however, Goethe has shown how through successive
modifications an archetype develops, according to law, to the
perfect organic form.
* * * * *
Even if Goethe could not follow the creative power of Nature
in its formative and transforming impulse through the
different members of the animal organism, yet he did succeed
in finding single laws to which Nature adheres in the
building of animal forms, laws which do indeed conform to the
general norm but vary in their manifestation. He imagines
that Nature has no power to change the general picture at
will. If in some creature one member is developed to a high
degree of perfection, this can only happen at the expense of
another. The archetypal organism contains all the members
that can appear in any one animal. In the single animal form
one member may be developed, another only indicated; one may
develop completely, another may be imperceptible to the
senses. In the latter case Goethe is convinced that the
elements pertaining to the general type that are not visible
in an animal exist, nevertheless, in the idea.
“If we behold in a creature some special excellence we
have merely to question and find where something is lacking.
The searching spirit will find somewhere the existence of a
defect and at the same time the key to the whole of creation.
Thus we can find no beast who carries a horn on its head and
has perfect teeth in the upper bone of the jaw; the Eternal
Mother, therefore, could never have created a lion with horns
even by the exercise of all her power. For she has not enough
substance to implant the full series of teeth and at the same
time bring forth horns and antlers.”
(Metamorphosis of the Animals.)
All members are developed in the archetypal organism and
maintained in equilibrium; the diversity arises because the
formative force expends itself on one member and, as a
result, another remains in an absolutely undeveloped
state or is merely indicated in external manifestation.
This law of the animal organism is called to-day the law of
the correlation or compensation of organs.
* * * * *
Goethe's conception is that the whole plant world is
contained in the archetypal plant and the whole animal world
in the archetypal animal, as idea. Out of this thought
arises the question: How is it that in one case these
definite plant or animal forms arise, and in another, others?
Under what conditions does a fish develop out of the
archetypal animal? under what conditions a bird? In the
scientific explanation of the structure of organisms Goethe
finds a mode of presentation that is distasteful to him. The
adherents of this mode of conception ask in regard to each
organ: What purpose does it serve in the living being in whom
it occurs? — Such a question is based on the general
thought that a divine Creator, or Nature, has predetermined a
definite purpose in life for each being and has then bestowed
upon it a structure which enables it to fulfil this purpose.
In Goethe's view this is just as absurd as the question: To
what end does an elastic sphere move when it is pushed by
another? An explanation of the motion can only be given by
discovering the law by which the sphere is set in motion
through a blow or other cause. One does not ask: “What
purpose is served by the motion of the sphere?” but,
“Whence is the motion derived?” In Goethe's
opinion one should not ask: “Why has the bull
horns?” but rather: “How can he have
horns?” Through what law does the archetypal animal
appear in the bull as a horn-carrying form? Goethe sought for
the idea of the archetypal plant and animal in order to find
in them the reasons for the diversity of organic forms. The
archetypal plant is the creative element in the plant world.
If one wants to explain a single plant species then one must
show how this creative element works in this special case.
The thought that an organic being owes its form, not to the
forces formatively acting in it, but to the fact that the
form is imposed upon it from without for certain ends, was
repulsive to Goethe. He writes: “In a pitiful,
apostolically monkish declamation of the Zurich prophet I
recently found this stupid sentence: ‘Everything that
has life, lives through something outside of itself’ —
or words to that effect. Only a proselytiser of the heathen
could write such a thing, and on revising it, his genius does
not pluck him by the sleeve”
(Italian Journey, 5th Oct., 1781).
Goethe thinks of the organic being as a
“little” world, a microcosm which has arisen
through itself, and fashions itself according to its own
laws. “The conception that a living being is produced
from outside for certain extraneous ends, and that its form
is determined by a purposive primeval force, has already
delayed us many centuries in the philosophical consideration
of Nature, and still holds us back, although individual men
have vigorously attacked this mode of thought, and have shown
the obstacles which it creates. It is, if one may so express
it, a paltry way of thinking, which like all paltry things is
trivial just because it is convenient and sufficient for
human nature in general” (Weimar Edition, Part 2, Vol.
7, p.217). It is, of course, convenient to say that a
Creator, when forming an organic species, has based it on a
certain purposive thought, and has therefore given it a
definite form. Goethe's aim, however, is not to explain
Nature by the intentions of some supernatural being, but out
of her inherent formative laws. An individual organic form
arises because the archetypal plant or animal assumes a
definite form in a special case. This form must be of such a
kind that it is able to live in the conditions surrounding
it. “The existence of a creature which we call fish is
only possible under the condition of an element that we call
water.” (Weimar Edition, Part 2, Vol. 7. p. 221). When
Goethe is seeking to comprehend the formative laws which
produce a definite organic form he goes back to his
archetypal organism. This archetypal organism has the power
to realise itself in the most manifold external forms. In
order to explain a fish Goethe would investigate what
formative forces the archetypal animal employs in order to
produce this particular fish form from among all the forms
which exist in it ideally. If the archetypal animal
were to realise itself in certain conditions in a form in
which it could not live it would not survive. An organic form
can only maintain itself within certain conditions of life if
it is adapted to them.
“Thus
by the animal's form is its manner of living determined,
Likewise the manner of life worketh back
on every creature, And so the organised form firmly makes its appearance,
Yet with the power to change, through outer conditions of Nature.”
(The Metamorphosis of Animals.)
The organic forces surviving in a given life-element are
conditioned by the nature of the element. If an organic form
were to leave one life-element for another it must transform
itself accordingly. This can happen in definite cases because
the archetypal organism which lies at its base has the power
of realising itself in countless forms. The transformation of
one form into another is, however, according to Goethe's
view, not to be conceived of in such a way that the external
conditions immediately remould the form in accordance with
their own nature, but that they become the cause through
which the inner being transforms itself. Changed
life-conditions provoke the organic form to transform itself
in a certain way according to inner laws. The external
influences work indirectly, not directly, on the living
being. Countless forms of life are contained in the
archetypal plant and animal ideally: those on which
external influences work as stimuli come to actual
existence.
* * * * *
The conception that a plant or animal species can in the
course of ages, as a result of certain conditions, be
transformed into another, has its full justification in
Goethe's view of Nature. Goethe's view is that the force
which produces a new being through the process of procreation
is simply a transformation of that force which brings about
the progressive metamorphosis of organs in the course of
growth. Reproduction is a “growing-beyond” the
individual.
As the basic organ during growth undergoes a sequence of
changes which are ideally the same, similarly, a
transformation of the external form can also occur in
reproduction, while the ideal archetype remains the
same. If an original organic form existed, then its
descendants in the course of great epochs of time could pass
over through gradual transformations into the manifold forms
peopling the earth at present. The thought of an actual
blood-relationship uniting all organic forms flows out of
Goethe's basic conceptions. He might have expressed it in its
completed form immediately after he had formed his idea of
the archetypal animal and plant. But he expresses
himself with reserve, even indefinitely, when he alludes to
this thought.
In the Essay,
Versuch einer allgemeinen Vergleich-ungslehre,
which was probably written shortly after the
Metamorphosis of Plants,
we read: “And how worthy it is of Nature
that she must always employ the same means in order to
produce and nourish a creature. Thus one will progress along
just these paths, and just as one at first only regarded the
inorganic, undetermined elements as vehicles of
organised beings, so will one now progress in
observation, and again regard the organised world as a union
of many elements. The whole kingdom of plants, for example,
will again appear to us like a great ocean, which is just as
necessary to the limited existence of the insects, as the
waters and rivers are to the limited existence of fishes, and
we shall see that a vast number of living creatures are born
and nourished in this ocean of plants; we shall, finally,
again regard the whole animal world as a great element where
one race maintains itself out of and through the other
if not arising from it.” There is less reserve in the
following sentence from
Lectures on the first three Chapters of an Outline of
Comparative Anatomy (1796):
“We should also have come to the point where we could
fearlessly maintain that all the more perfect organic beings,
among which we reckon fishes, amphibia, birds, mammals, and
at the summit of the last, Man, are formed according to one
archetype, which only in its constituent parts inclines
hither and thither and daily develops and transforms itself
through procreation.” Goethe's caution regarding the
thought of transformation is comprehensible. The epoch
in which he elaborated his ideas was not unfamiliar with this
thought. It had, however, been developed in the most confused
sense. “That epoch,” writes Goethe, “was
darker than one can conceive of now.” It was stated,
for example, that man, if he liked, could go about
comfortably on all fours, and that bears, if they remained
upright for a period of time, could become human beings. The
audacious Diderot ventured to make certain proposals as to
how goat-footed fauns could be produced and then put into
livery, to sit in pomp and distinction on the coaches of the
mighty and the rich! Goethe would have nothing to do with
such undue ideas. His aim was to obtain an idea of the
basic laws of the living. It became clear to him here
that the forms of the living are not rigid and unchangeable,
but are subject to continual transformation. He had,
however, no opportunity of making observations which would
have enabled him to see how this transformation was
accomplished in the single phenomenon. It was the
investigations of Darwin and the reflections of Haeckel that
first threw light on the actual relationship between the
single organic forms. From the standpoint of Goethe's
world-conception one can only give assent to the assertions
of Darwinism in so far as they concern the actual
emergence of one organic species from another. Goethe's
ideas, however, penetrate more deeply into the nature of the
organic world than modern Darwinism. Modern Darwinism
believes that it can do without the inner impelling forces in
the organism which Goethe conceives of in the
sensible-supersensible image. Indeed it would even deny that
Goethe was justified in arguing, from his postulates, an
actual transformation of organs and organisms. Jul. Sachs
rejects Goethe's thoughts by saying that he transfers
“the abstraction evolved by the intellect to the object
itself when he ascribes to this object a metamorphosis which,
fundamentally speaking, is only accomplished in our
concept.” According to this view Goethe has presumably
gone no further than to reduce leaves, sepals, petals, etc.,
to one general concept, designating them by the name ‘leaf.’
“Of course the matter would be quite different if we
could assume that the stamens were ordinary leaves in the
ancestors of the plant-forms lying before us, etc.”
(Sachs,
History of Botany.
1875, p. 169).
This view springs from that “fact-fanaticism”
which cannot see that the ideas belong just as objectively to
the phenomena as the elements that are perceptible to the
senses. Goethe's view is that the transformation of one organ
into another can only be spoken of if both contain something
in common over and above their external appearance. This is
the sensible-supersensible form. The stamens of a plant-form
before us can only be described as the transformed leaf of
the predecessors if the same sensible-supersensible form
lives in both. If that is not the case, if the stamen has
developed in the particular plant-form simply in the same
place in which a leaf developed in its predecessors,
then no transformation has occurred, but one organ has merely
appeared in the place of another. The Zoologist Oscar Schmidt
asks: “What is it that is supposed to be transformed
according to Goethe's views? Certainly not the
archetype!”
(War Goethe Darwinianer?
Graz. 1871, p. 22.).
Certainly the archetype is not
transformed, for this is the same in all forms. But it is
just because this remains the same that the external
forms can be different, and yet represent, a uniform Whole.
If one could not recognise the same ideal archetype in two
forms developing out of each other, no relation could be
assumed to exist between them. Only the conception of the
ideal archetypal form can impart real meaning to the
assertion that the organic forms arise by a process of
transformation out of each other. Those who cannot rise
to this conception remain chained within the mere facts. The
laws of organic development lie in this conception. Just as
Kepler's three fundamental laws make the processes in the
solar system comprehensible, so can the forms of organic
Nature be understood through Goethe's ideal archetypes.
Kant, who denies to the human spirit the power of
understanding, in the ideal sense, a Whole by which a
multiplicity is determined in its appearance, calls it
“a risky adventure of reason” to seek to explain
the various forms of the organic world by an archetypal
organism. For him man is only in a position to gather the
manifold, individual phenomena into one general concept by
which the intellect forms for itself a picture of the unity.
This picture, however, exists only in the human mind and has
nothing to do with the creative power by which the unity
really causes the multiplicity to proceed out of itself. The
“risky adventure of reason” consists in assuming
that the Earth first allows the more simple organisms to
proceed out of her womb and that these then produce from
themselves forms with more deliberate purpose; that from
these again, still higher forms develop, up to the most
perfect living being. Kant holds that even if such a
supposition is made, it can only be based on a purposive
creative force, which has given evolution such an impulse
that all its various members develop in accordance with some
goal. Man perceives a multitude of different organisms; and
since he cannot penetrate them in order to see how they
themselves assume a form adapted to the life-element in which
they develop, he must conceive that they are so adapted from
without that they can live within these conditions. Goethe,
however, claims the faculty of being able to recognise how
Nature creates the particular from the whole, the outer from
the inner. He is willing to undertake courageously what Kant
calls the “adventure of reason”
(cp. the Essay:
Anschauende Urteilskraft
Kürschner. Bd. 34.).
If we had no other proof that Goethe regarded as
justifiable the thought of a blood-relationship among all
organic forms within the limits here specified, we should
have to conclude it from this judgment of Kant's
“adventure of reason.”
* * * * *
A sketch,
Entwurf einer Morphologie,
which still exists, suggests that Goethe intended to present, in
their sequence, the special forms which his archetypal plant
and archetypal animal assume in the main forms of living
beings. He wanted first to describe the nature of the organic
as it appeared to him through his contemplation of animals
and plants. Then he wanted to show how the organic archetypal
being, “proceeding from a centre,” develops on
the one side to the manifold plant world, on the other to the
multiplicity of animal forms, and how particular forms of
worms, of insects, of higher animals and the form of man can
be derived from the general archetype. He intended even to
shed light on physiognomy and phrenology. He made it his task
to present the external form in its connection with the inner
spiritual faculties. He was impelled to follow the organic
formative impulse, which in the lower organisms is portrayed
in a simple external appearance, in its striving to fulfil
itself stage by stage in ever more perfect forms until it
produces in man a form which makes him able to be the creator
of spiritual production.
This plan of Goethe's was never completed, any more than was
another, the commencement of which is to be found in the
fragment,
Vorarbeiten zu einer Physiologie der Pflanzen
(cp. Weimar Edition, Part 2, Vol. 6, pp. 286 ff.).
Goethe tried to show how the various branches of
material knowledge, — Natural History, Physics,
Anatomy, Chemistry, Zöonomy and Physiology — must
work together, in order to be applied in a higher mode of
perception to explain the forms and processes of living
beings. He wanted to bring forward a new science, a general
morphology of organisms, new indeed “not in reference
to its subject-matter, for this is known, but in its outlook
and method, which must give an individual form to the
doctrine as well as establish a place for it among other
sciences.” What Anatomy, Natural History, Physics,
Chemistry, Zöonomy, Physiology have to offer as the
various laws of Nature, would be taken up by the living idea
of the organic and placed on a higher level, just as the
living being itself takes up the different processes of
Nature in the cycle of its development and places them on a
higher level of activity.
* * * * *
Goethe reached the ideas which guided him through the
labyrinth of living forms along paths of his own. The
prevailing conceptions in regard to important regions of
Nature's activity contradicted his own general
world-conception. Therefore with regard to these regions he
had to form for himself conceptions in accordance with his
own being. He was convinced, however, that there was
“nothing new under the sun,” and that one
“could certainly find one's own perceptions already
indicated in traditions.” For this reason he sent his
work on the Metamorphosis of the Plants to learned friends,
and begged them to tell him whether anything had already been
written or handed down concerning the theme in question. He
was glad to be told, by Friedrich August Wolf, of an
“admirable precursor,” one Caspar Friedrich Wolf.
Goethe became acquainted with his
Theoria Generationis
which had appeared in 1759. But this very
work shows that it is possible to hold a correct view of the
facts and yet that a man cannot come to the full idea of
organic development unless he is capable of arriving at the
sensible-supersensible form of life through a power of
perception higher than that of the senses. Wolf was an
excellent observer. He sought to discover the beginnings of
life by means of microscopical investigations. He
recognised transformed leaves in the calyx, corolla, pistils,
stamens and seed. But he ascribed the process of
transformation to a gradual decrease of the life-force, which
diminishes in proportion to the length of time the plant
exists, until it finally disappears. Calyx, corolla, etc.,
are, therefore, for him an imperfect development of the leaf.
Wolf came forward as the opponent of Haller, who advanced the
theory of Pre-formation or “Encasement.”
According to this theory, all the members of a fully-grown
organism are already represented on a small scale in the
germ, and, indeed, in the same shape and mutual arrangement
as in the developed living being. The development of an
organism is thus simply an unfolding of what already exists.
Wolf would only accept validity in what he saw with his eyes.
And since the encased condition of a living being could not
be discovered even by the most careful observations, he
regarded development as an actually new formation. According
to his view, the shape of an organic being is not yet present
in the germ. Goethe is of the same opinion in reference to
the external manifestation. He, too, rejects the
“Encasement Theory” of Haller. For Goethe the
organism is indeed pre-figured in the germ, not according to
its external appearance but according to the idea. He
regards the external appearance as a new formation, but
reproaches Wolf with the fact that where he sees nothing with
the eyes of the body, he also sees nothing with the eyes of
the spirit. Wolf had no conception of the fact that something
may still exist in the idea even if it does not pass into
external manifestation. “Therefore he is always
concerned with penetrating to the beginnings of the
development of life by means of microscopical
investigations and so following the organic embryos
from their earliest appearance up to their development.
However admirable this method may be, yet the excellent man
did not think that there is a distinction between ‘seeing’
and ‘seeing,’ that the eyes of the spirit have to work in
constant, living union with the eyes of the body because
otherwise one may fall into the danger of seeing and yet
overlooking. ... In the plant-transformation he saw the same
organ continually contracting, continually diminishing, but
he did not see that this contraction alternated with an
expansion. He saw that it diminished in volume, but did not
observe that at the same time it became more perfect, and he
therefore absurdly attributed the path towards perfection to
a process of impoverishment.” (Kürschner Nat. Lit.
Bd. 33.).
* * * * *
Until the very end of his life Goethe was in touch with
innumerable scientific investigators, both in personal and
written intercourse. He followed the progress of the science
of living beings with the keenest interest; he saw with joy
how modes of thought resembling his own gained entrance into
this department of knowledge, and how his doctrine of
metamorphosis was also recognised and made fruitful by
individual investigators. In the year 1817 he began to gather
his works together and to publish them in a periodical which
he founded under the title,
Zur Morphologie.
In spite of all this, however, he
made no further progress, through personal observation or
reflection, in the growth of his ideas concerning organic
development. On two other occasions only did he feel
compelled to occupy himself more deeply with such ideas. In
both cases he was attracted by scientific phenomena in which
he found the confirmation of his own thoughts. The one case
was the Course of Lectures held by K. F. Martius on
“The Vertical and Spiral Tendency of Vegetation”
at the Conference of Natural Scientists in the years 1828 and
1829, of which the periodical “Isis” published
extracts; the other was a scientific dispute in the French
Academy which broke out in the year 1830 between Geoffrey de
Saint-Hilaire and Cuvier.
Martius conceived of the growth of plants as being dominated
by two tendencies by a striving in the vertical direction
which governs the root and stem, and by another which causes
the leaves, the organs of the blossoms and so on, to
incorporate themselves into the vertical organs of the form
of a spiral line. Goethe took these thoughts and brought them
into connection with his idea of metamorphosis. He wrote a
long essay (Kürschner Bd. 33), into which he collected
all his experiences of the plant-world which appeared to him
to point to the existence of these two tendencies. He
believed that he had to merge these tendencies into his idea
of metamorphosis. “This much we must assume: there
prevails in vegetation a general spiral tendency, whereby, in
union with the vertical striving of the whole structure, each
formation in the plant is brought about in accordance with
the laws of metamorphosis.” Goethe regarded the
existence of spiral vessels in the various plant organs as a
proof that the spiral tendency dominates the life of plants
throughout. “Nothing is more in accordance with Nature
than the fact that what she intends in the Whole she
activates through the minutest detail.” “Let us
in summer look at a stake planted in the soil up which a
bindweed (convolvulus) climbs from below, winding its way to
the heights and — clinging closely — maintains
its living growth. Let us think now of the bindweed and stake
as both equally living and ascending upwards from one root,
producing each other alternately and so progressing
unchecked. Those who can transform this picture into an inner
perception will find the idea considerably easier. The
twining plant seeks outside itself that which it should
itself produce, but cannot.” Goethe uses the same
comparison in a letter to Count Sternberg, 15th March, 1832,
and adds these words: “Of course the comparison does
not entirely fit, for in the beginning the creeper must wind
itself round the stem in barely perceptible circles. The
nearer it approaches the summit, however, the quicker must
the spiral line turn in order finally (in the blossom) to
collect itself in a circle on the disc. This process
resembles the dances of one's youth, where half reluctantly
one was often pressed in the close embrace of affectionate
children. Pardon these anthropomorphisms!”
Ferdinand Cohn remarks in reference to this passage:
“If only Goethe had known Darwin! How pleased he would
have been with this man, who through his strictly inductive
methods knew how to find clear and convincing proofs for his
ideas.” Darwin thinks that in nearly all plant organs
he can show that in the period of their growth they have the
tendency to spiral movements which he calls
circummutation.
In September, 1830, Goethe refers in an essay to the dispute
between the two investigators, Cuvier and Geoffrey de
Saint-Hilaire; in March, 1832, he continues this essay. In
February and March, 1830, Cuvier, the
“fact-fanatic” came forward in the French Academy
in opposition to the work of Geoffrey de Saint-Hilaire, who,
in Goethe's opinion, had attained to a “lofty mode of
thought in conformity with the idea.” Cuvier was a
master of the distinctions existing between the various
organic forms. Saint-Hilaire tried to discover the analogies
in these forms and to prove that the organisation of animals
is “subject to a general plant only modified here and
there, whence the differences can be derived.” He
tried to acquire knowledge of the relationship between the
laws and was convinced that the particular could develop
stage by stage from the whole. Goethe regards Saint-Hilaire
as a man of like mind with himself and he expresses this to
Eckermann, 2nd August, 1830, in the words: “Geoffrey de
Saint-Hilaire is now our ally, and with him all important
followers and adherents in France. This occurrence is of
inconceivable value to me and I justly rejoice at this final
victory of a matter to which I have devoted my life and which
is my own special concern.” Saint-Hilaire practises a
mode of thought which is also that of Goethe, for he seeks to
lay hold in experience of the idea of unity
simultaneously with the sensible manifold. Cuvier clings to
the manifold, to the particular, because in his observation
of the particular the idea does not immediately arise.
Saint-Hilaire had a right perception of the relation of the
sensible to the idea; Cuvier had not. Therefore he describes
Saint-Hilaire's all-inclusive principle as presumptive
— nay even inferior. One can often experience,
especially in the case of investigators of Nature, that they
speak in a derogatory sense of something merely ideal, of
something merely “thought.” They have no organ
for the ideal, and therefore do not know its mode of working.
It was because Goethe possessed this organ in a highly
perfect state of development that he was led from his general
world-conception to his deep insight into the nature of the
living. His power of allowing the spiritual eye to work in
constant living union with the eye of the body made it
possible for him to behold the uniform sensible-supersensible
essence which permeates organic evolution. He was also able
to recognise this essence where one organ develops out of the
other, and where, by its transformation, it conceals its
relationship and similarity to its predecessor, even belying
it, and changing, both in its function and in its form, to
such a degree that no parallel, according to external
characteristics, can be found with its earlier stages
(cp. the essay on Joachim Jungius, Kürschner, Nat. Lit.
Bd. 33.). Perception with the eye of the body imparts
knowledge of the sensible and material; perception with the
eye of the spirit leads to the perception of processes in
human consciousness, to the observation of the world of
thinking, feeling and willing; the living union of the
spiritual and bodily eye makes possible the knowledge of the
organic which, as a sensible-supersensible element, lies
between the purely sensible and the purely spiritual.
|