The World Conception of the Greek Thinkers
With Pherekydes of Syros, who lived in the sixth century B.C., a
personality appears in the Greek intellectual-spiritual life in whom
one can observe the birth of what will be called in the following
presentation, a world and life conception. What he has to
say about the problems of the world is, on the one hand, still like
the mythical symbolic accounts of a time that lies before the striving
for a scientific world conception; on the other hand, his imagination
penetrates through the picture, through the myth, to a form of
reflection that wants to pierce the problems of man's existence and of
his position in the world by means of thoughts. He still
imagines the earth in the picture of a winged oak around which Zeus
wraps the surface land, oceans, rivers, etc., like a woven texture. He
thinks of the world as permeated by spiritual beings of which Greek
mythology speaks.
But Pherekydes also speaks of three principles of the world: Of
Chronos, of Zeus and of Chthon.
Throughout the history of philosophy there has been much discussion as
to what is to be understood by these three principles. As the
historical sources on the question of what Pherekydes meant to say in
his work, Heptamychos, are contradictory, it is quite
understandable that present-day opinions also do not agree. If we
reflect on the traditional accounts of Pherekydes, we get the
impression that we can really observe in him the beginning of
philosophical thought but that this observation is difficult because
his words have to be taken in a sense that is remote from the thought
habits of the present time; its real meaning is yet to be
determined.*
Pherekydes arrives at his world picture in a different way from that
of his predecessors. The significant fact is that he feels man to be a
living soul in a way different from earlier times. For the
earlier world view, the word, soul, did not yet have the
meaning that it acquired in later conceptions of life, nor did
Pherekydes have the idea of the soul in the sense of later thinkers.
He simply feels the soul-element of man, whereas the later
thinkers want to speak clearly about it (in the form of thought) and
they attempt to characterize it in intellectual terms. Men of earlier
times do not as yet separate their own soul experience from the life
of nature. They do not feel that they stand as a special entity beside
nature. They experience themselves in nature as they experience
lightning and thunder in it, the drifting of the clouds, the course of
the stars or the growth of plants. What moves man's hand on his own
body, what places his foot on the ground and makes him walk, for the
prehistoric man, belongs to the same sphere of world forces that also
causes lightning, cloud formations and all other external events. What
he at this stage feels, can be expressed by saying, Something
causes lightning, thunder, rain, moves my hand, makes my foot step,
moves the air of my breath within me, turns my head. If one
expresses what is in this way experienced, one has to use words that
at first hearing seem to be exaggerated. But only through these
exaggerations will it be possible to understand what is intended to be
conveyed.
A man who holds a world picture as it is meant here, experiences in
the rain that falls to the ground the action of a force that we at the
present time must call spiritual and that he feels to be
of the same kind as the force he experiences when he is about to exert
a personal activity of some kind or other. It should be of interest
that this view can be found again in Goethe in his younger years,
naturally in a shade of thought that it must assume in a personality
of the eighteenth century. We can read in Goethe's essay,
Nature:
She (nature) has placed me in life; she will also lead me out of it. I
trust myself into her care. She may hold sway over me. She will not
hate her work. It was not I who spoke about her. Nay, what is true and
what is false everything has been spoken by her. Everything is her
fault, everything her merit.
To speak as Goethe speaks here is only then possible if one feels
one's own being imbedded in nature as a whole and then expresses this
feeling in thoughtful reflection. As Goethe thought, so man of
an earlier time felt without transforming his soul experience into the
element of thought. He did not as yet experience thought; instead of
thought there unfolded within his soul a symbolic image. The
observation of the evolution of mankind leads back to a time in which
thought-like experiences had not yet come into being but in which the
symbolic picture rose in the soul of man when he contemplated the
events of the world. Thought life is born in man at a definite time.
It causes the extinction of the previous form of consciousness in
which the world is experienced in pictures.
For the thought habits of our time it seems acceptable to imagine that
man in archaic times had observed natural elements wind and weather,
the growth of seeds, the course of the stars and then poetically
invented spiritual beings as the active creators of these
events. It is, however, far from the contemporary mode of thinking to
recognize the possibility that man in older times experienced those
pictures as he later experienced thought, that is, as an inner reality
of his soul life.
One will gradually come to recognize that in the course of the
evolution of mankind a transformation of the human organization has
taken place. There was a time when the subtle organs of human nature,
which make possible the development of an independent thought life,
had not yet been formed. In this time man had, instead, organs, that
represented for him what he experienced in the world of pictures.
As this gradually comes to be understood, a new light will fall on the
significance of mythology on the one hand, and that of poetic
production and thought life on the other. When the independent inner
thought experience began, it brought the picture-consciousness to
extinction. Thought emerged as the tool of truth. This is only one
branch of what survived of the old picture-consciousness that had
found its expression in the ancient myth. In another branch the
extinguished picture-consciousness continued to live, if only as a
pale shadow of its former existence, in the creations of fantasy and
poetic imagination. Poetic fantasy and the intellectual view of the
world are the two children of the one mother, the old
picture-consciousness that must not be confused with the consciousness
of poetic imagination.
The essential process that is to be understood is the transformation
of the more delicate organization of man. It causes the beginning of
thought life. In art and poetry thought as such naturally does not
have an effect. Here the picture continues to exert its influence, but
it has now a different relation to the human soul from the one it had
when it also served in a cognitive function. As thought itself,
the new form of consciousness appears only in the newly emerging
philosophy. The other branches of human life are correspondingly
transformed in a different way when thought begins to rule in the
field of human knowledge.
The progress in human evolution that is characterized by this process
is connected with the fact that man from the beginning of thought
experience had to feel himself in a much more pronounced way
than before, as a separated entity, as a soul. In myth
the picture was experienced in such a way that one felt it to be
in the external world as a reality. One experienced this reality at
the same time, and one was united with it. With thought, as
well as with the poetic picture, man felt himself separated
from nature. Engaged in thought experience, man felt himself as an
entity that could not experience nature with the same intimacy as he
felt when at one with thought. More and more, the definite feeling of
the contrast of nature and soul came into being.
In the civilizations of the different peoples this transition from the
old picture-consciousness to the consciousness of thought experience
took place at different times. In Greece we can intimately observe
this transition if we focus our attention on the personality of
Pherekydes of Syros. He lived in a world in which
picture-consciousness and thought experience still had an equal share.
His three principal ideas Zeus, Chronos and Chthon can only be
understood in such a way that the soul, in experiencing them, feels
itself as belonging to the events of the external world. We are
dealing here with three inwardly experienced pictures and we find
access to them only when we do not allow ourselves to be distracted by
anything that the thought habits of our time are likely to imagine as
their meaning.
Chronos is not time as we think of it today. Chronos is a being that
in contemporary language can be called spiritual if one
keeps in mind that one does not thereby exhaust its meaning. Chronos
is alive and its activity is the devouring, the consumption of the
life of another being, Chthon. Chronos rules in nature; Chronos rules
in man; in nature and man Chronos consumes Chthon. It is of no
importance whether one considers the consumption of Chthon through
Chronos as inwardly experienced or as external events, for in both
realms the same process goes on. Zeus is connected with these two
beings. In the meaning of Pherekydes one must no more think of Zeus as
a deity in the sense of our present day conception of mythology, than
as of mere space in its present sense, although he is the
being through whom the events that go on between Chronos and Chthon
are transformed into spatial, extended form.
The cooperation of Chronos, Chthon and Zeus is felt directly as a
picture content in the sense of Pherekydes, just as much as one is
aware of the idea that one is eating, but it is also experienced as
something in the external world, like the conception of the colors
blue or red. This experience can be imagined in the following way. We
turn our attention to fire as it consumes its fuel. Chronos lives in
the activity of fire, of warmth. Whoever regards fire in its
activity and keeps himself under the effect, not of independent
thought but of image content, looks at Chronos. In the activity of
fire, not in the sensually perceived fire, he experiences time
simultaneously. Another conception of time does not exist before
the birth of thought. What is called time in our present
age is an idea that has been developed only in the age of intellectual
world conception.
If we turn our attention to water, not as it is as water but as it
changes into air or vapor, or to clouds that are in the process of
dissolving, we experience as an image content the force of Zeus, the
spatially active spreader. One could also say, the force
of centrifugal extension. If we look on water as it becomes solid, or
on the solid as it changes into fluid, we are watching Chthon. Chthon
is something that later in the age of thought-ruled world conception
becomes matter, the stuff things are made of;
Zeus has become ether or space, Chronos
changes into time.
In the view of Pherekydes the world is constituted through the
cooperation of these three principles. Through the combination of
their action the material world of sense perception fire, air, water
and earth come into being on the one hand, and on the other, a
certain number of invisible supersensible spirit beings who animate
the four material worlds. Zeus, Chronos and Chthon could be referred
to as spirit, soul and matter, but their significance is
only approximated by these terms. It is only through the fusion of
these three original beings that the more material realms of the world
of fire, air, water and earth, and the more soul-like and spirit-like
(supersensible) beings come into existence. Using expressions of later
world conceptions, one can call Zeus, space-ether; Chronos,
time-creator; Chthon, matter-producer the three mothers of the
world's origin. We can still catch a glimpse of them in Goethe's
Faust, in the scene of the second part where Faust sets out on
his journey to the mothers.
As these three primordial entities appear in Pherekydes, they remind
us of conceptions of predecessors of this personality, the so-called
Orphics. They represent a mode of conception that still lives
completely in the old form of picture consciousness. In them we also
find three original beings: Zeus, Chronos and Chaos. Compared to these
primeval mothers, those of Pherekydes are somewhat less
picture-like. This is so because Pherekydes attempts to seize, through
the exertion of thought, what his Orphic predecessors still held
completely as image-experience. For this reason we can say that he
appears as a personality in whom the birth of thought life
takes place. This is expressed not so much in the more thought-like
conception of the Orphic ideas of Pherekydes, as in a certain
dominating mood of his soul, which we later find again in several of
his philosophizing successors in Greece. For Pherekydes feels that he
is forced to see the origin of things in the good
(Arizon). He could not combine this concept with the world of
mythological deities of ancient times. The beings of this world
had soul qualities that were not in agreement with this concept. Into
his three original causes Pherekydes could only think the
concept of the good, the perfect.
Connected with this circumstance is the fact that the birth of thought
life brought with it a shattering of the foundations of the inner
feelings of the soul. This inner experience should not be overlooked
in a consideration of the time when the intellectual world conception
began. One could not have felt this beginning as progress if one had
not believed that with thought one took possession of something that
was more perfect than the old form of image experience. Of course, at
this stage of thought development, this feeling was not clearly
expressed. But what one now, in retrospect, can clearly state with
regard to the ancient Greek thinkers was then merely felt. They felt
that the pictures that were experienced by our immediate ancestors did
not lead to the highest, most perfect, original causes. In these
pictures only the less perfect causes were revealed; we must raise our
thoughts to still higher causes from which the content of those
pictures is merely derived.
Through progress into thought life, the world was now conceived as
divided into a more natural and a more spiritual sphere. In this more
spiritual sphere, which was only now felt as such, one had to conceive
what was formerly experienced in the form of pictures. To this was
added the conception of a higher principle, something thought of as
superior to the older, spiritual world and to nature. It was to this
sublime element that thought wanted to penetrate, and it is in this
region that Pherekydes meant to find his three Primordial
Mothers. A look at the world as it appears illustrates what kind
of conceptions took hold of a personality like Pherekydes. Man finds a
harmony in his surroundings that lies at the bottom of all phenomena
and is manifested in the motions of the stars, in the course of the
seasons with their blessings of thriving plant-life, etc. In this
beneficial course of things, harmful, destructive powers intervene, as
expressed in the pernicious effects of the weather, earthquakes, etc.
In observing all this one can be lead to a realization of a dualism in
the ruling powers, but the human soul must assume an underlying unity.
It naturally feels that, in the last analysis, the ravaging hail, the
destructive earthquake, must spring from the same source as the
beneficial cycle of the seasons. In this fashion man looks through
good and evil and sees behind it an original good. The same good force
rules in the earthquake as in the blessed rain of spring. In the
scorching, devastating heat of the sun the same element is at work
that ripens the seed. The good Mothers of all origin are,
then, in the pernicious events also. When man experiences this
feeling, a powerful world riddle emerges before his soul. To find the
solution, Pherekydes turns toward his Ophioneus. As Pherekydes leans
on the old picture conception, Ophioneus appears to him as a kind of
world serpent. It is in reality a spirit being, which,
like all other beings of the world, belongs to the children of
Chronos, Zeus and Chthon, but that has later so changed that its
effects are directed against those of the good mother of
origin. Thus, the world is divided into three parts. The first
part consists of the Mothers, which are presented as good,
as perfect; the second part contains the beneficial world events; the
third part, the destructive or the only imperfect world processes
that, as Ophioneus, are intertwined in the beneficial effects.
For Pherekydes, Ophioneus is not merely a symbolic idea for the
detrimental destructive world forces. Pherekydes stands with his
conceptive imagination at the borderline between picture and thought.
He does not think that there are devastating powers that he conceives
in the pictures of Ophioneus, nor does such a thought process develop
in him as an activity of fantasy. Rather, he looks on the detrimental
forces, and immediately Ophioneus stands before his soul as the red
color stands before our souls when we look at a rose.
Whoever sees the world only as it presents itself to image perception
does not, at first, distinguish in his thought between the events of
the good mothers and those of Ophioneus. At the borderline
of a thought-formed world conception, the necessity of this
distinction is felt, for only at this stage of progress does the soul
feel itself to be a separate, independent entity. It feels the
necessity to ask what its origin is. It must find its origin in the
depths of the world where Chronos, Zeus and Chthon had not as yet
found their antagonists. But the soul also feels that it cannot know
anything of its own origin at first, because it sees itself in the
midst of a world in which the Mothers work in conjunction
with Ophioneus. It feels itself in a world in which the perfect and
the imperfect are joined together. Ophioneus is twisted into the
soul's own being.
We can feel what went on in the souls of individual personalities of
the sixth century B.C. if we allow the feelings described here to make
a sufficient impression on us. With the ancient mythical deities such
souls felt themselves woven into the imperfect world. The deities
belonged to the same imperfect world as they did themselves.
The spiritual brotherhood, which was founded by Pythagoras of Samos
between the years 549 and 500 B.C. in Kroton in Magna Graecia, grew
out of such a mood. Pythagoras intended to lead his followers back to
the experience of the Primordial Mothers in which the
origin of their souls was to be seen. It can be said in this respect
that he and his disciples meant to serve other gods than
those of the people. With this fact something was given that must
appear as a break between spirits like Pythagoras and the people, who
were satisfied with their gods. Pythagoras considered these gods as
belonging to the realm of the imperfect. In this difference we also
find the reason for the secret that is often referred to
in connection with Pythagoras and that was not to be betrayed to the
uninitiated. It consisted in the fact that Pythagoras had to attribute
to the human soul an origin different from that of the gods of the
popular religion. In the last analysis, the numerous attacks that
Pythagoras experienced must be traced to this secret. How
was he to explain to others than those who carefully prepared
themselves for such a knowledge that, in a certain sense, they,
as souls, could consider themselves as standing even
higher than the gods of the popular religion? In what other form than
in a brotherhood with a strictly regulated mode of life could the
souls become aware of their lofty origin and still find themselves
deeply bound up with imperfection? It was just through this feeling of
deficiency that the effort was to be made to arrange life in such a
way that through the process of self-perfection it would be led back
to its origin. That legends and myths were likely to be formed about
such aspirations of Pythagoras is comprehensible. It is also
understandable that scarcely anything has come down to us historically
about the true significance of this personality. Whoever observes the
legends and mythical traditions of antiquity about Pythagoras in an
all-encompassing picture will nevertheless recognize in it the
characterization that was just given.
In the picture of Pythagoras, present-day thinking also feels the idea
of the so-called transmigration of souls as a disturbing
factor. It is even felt to be naive that Pythagoras is reported to
have said that he knew that he had already been on earth in an earlier
time as another human being. It may be recalled that that great
representative of modern enlightenment, Lessing, in his Education
of the Human Race, renewed this idea of man's repeated lives on
earth out of a mode of thinking that was entirely different from that
of Pythagoras. Lessing could conceive of the progress of the human
race only in such a way that the human souls participated repeatedly
in the life of the successive great phases of history. A soul brought
into its life in a later time as a potential ability what it had
gained from experience in an earlier era. Lessing found it natural
that the soul had often been on earth in an earthly body, and that it
would often return in the future. In this way, it struggles from life
to life toward the perfection that it finds possible to obtain. He
pointed out that the idea of repeated lives on earth ought not to be
considered incredible because it existed in ancient times, and
because it occurred to the human mind before academic sophistry
had distracted and weakened it.
The idea of reincarnation is present in Pythagoras, but it would be
erroneous to believe that he along with Pherekydes, who is mentioned
as his teacher in antiquity had yielded to this idea because he had
by means of a logical conclusion arrived at the thought that the path
of development indicated above could only be reached in repeated
earthly lives. To attribute such an intellectual mode of thinking to
Pythagoras would be to misjudge him. We are told of his extensive
journeys. We hear that he met together with wise men who had preserved
traditions of oldest human insight. When we observe the oldest human
conceptions that have come down to us through posterity, we arrive at
the view that the idea of repeated lives on earth was widespread in
remote antiquity. Pythagoras took up the thread from the oldest
teachings of humanity. The mythical teachings in picture form appeared
to him as deteriorated conceptions that had their origin in older and
superior insights. These picture doctrines were to change in his time
into a thought-formed world conception, but this intellectual world
conception appeared to him as only a part of the soul's life. This
part had to be developed to greater depths. It could then lead the
soul to its origins. By penetrating in this direction, however, the
soul discovers in its inner experience the repeated lives on earth as
a soul perception. It does not reach its origins unless it
finds its way through the repeated terrestrial lives. As a wanderer
walking to a distant place naturally passes through other places on
his path, so the soul on its path to the mothers passes
the preceding lives through which it has gone during its descent from
its former existence in perfection, to its present life in
imperfection. If one considers everything that is pertinent in this
problem, the inference is inescapable that the view of repeated earth
lives is to be attributed to Pythagoras in this sense as his inner
perception, not as something that was arrived at through a process of
conceptual conclusion.
Now the view that is spoken of as especially characteristic of the
followers of Pythagoras is that all things are based on numbers. When
this statement is made, one must consider that the school of
Pythagoras was continued into later times after his death. Philolaus,
Archytas and others are mentioned as later Pythagoreans. It was about
them especially that one in antiquity knew they considered
things as numbers. We can assume that this view goes back to
Pythagoras even if historical documentation does not appear possible.
We shall, however, have to suppose that this view was deeply and
organically rooted in his whole mode of conception, and that it took
on a more superficial form with his successors.
Let us think of Pythagoras as standing before the beginning of
intellectual world conception. He saw how thought took its origin in
the soul that had, starting from the mothers, descended
through its successive lives to its state of imperfection; Because he
felt this he could not mean to ascend to the origins through mere
thought. He had to seek the highest knowledge in a sphere in which
thought was not yet at home. There he found a life of the soul that
was beyond thought life. As the soul experiences proportional numbers
in the sound of music, so Pythagoras developed a soul life in which he
knew himself as living in a connection with the world that can be
intellectually expressed in terms of numbers. But for what is thus
experienced, these numbers have no other significance than the
physicist's proportional tone numbers have for the experience of
music.
For Pythagoras the mythical gods must be replaced by thought. At the
same time, he develops an appropriate deepening of the soul life; the
soul, which through thought has separated itself from the world, finds
itself at one with the world again. It experiences itself as
not separated from the world. This does not take place in a
region in which the world-participating experience turns into a
mythical picture, but in a region in which the soul reverberates with
the invisible, sensually imperceptible cosmic harmonies. It brings
into awareness, not its own thought intentions, but what cosmic powers
exert as their will, thus allowing it to become conception in the soul
of man.
In Pherekydes and Pythagoras the process of how thought-experienced
world conception originates in the human soul is revealed. Working
themselves free from the older forms of conception, these men arrive
at an inwardly independent conception of the soul distinct
from external nature. What is clearly apparent in these
two personalities the process in which the soul wrests its way out
of the old picture conceptions takes place more in the
undercurrents of the souls of the other thinkers with whom it
is customary to begin the account of the development of Greek
philosophy. The thinkers who are ordinarily mentioned first are
Thales of Miletos (640 550 B.C.), Anaximander (born
610 B.C.), Anaximenes (flourished 600 B.C.) and Heraclitus
(born 500 B.C. at Ephesus).
Whoever acknowledges the preceding arguments to be justified will also
find a presentation of these men admissible that must differ from the
usual historical accounts of philosophy. Such accounts are, after all,
always based on the unexpressed presupposition that these men had
arrived at their traditionally reported statements through an
imperfect observation of nature. Thus the statement is made that the
fundamental and original being of all things was to be found in
water, according to Thales; in the infinite,
according to Anaximander; in air, according to Anaximenes;
in fire, in the opinion of Heraclitus.
What is not considered in this treatment is the fact that these men
are still really living in the process of the genesis of intellectual
world conception. To be sure, they feel the independence of the human
soul in a higher degree than Pherekydes, but they have not yet
completed the strict separation of the life of the soul from the
process of nature. One will, for instance, most certainly construct an
erroneous picture of Thales's way of thinking if it is imagined that
he, as a merchant, mathematician and astronomer, thought about natural
events and then, in an imperfect yet similar way to that of a modern
scientist, had summed up his results in the sentence, Everything
originates from water. To be a mathematician or an astronomer,
etc., in those ancient times meant to deal in a practical way with the
things of these professions, much in the way a craftsman makes use of
technical skills rather than intellectual and scientific knowledge.
What must be presumed for a man like Thales is that he still
experienced the external processes of nature as similar to inner soul
processes. What presented itself to him like a natural event, as did
the process and nature of water (the fluid, mudlike,
earth-formative element), he experienced in a way that was similar to
what he felt within himself in soul and body. He then experienced in
himself and outside in nature the effect of water, although to a
lesser degree than man of earlier times did. Both effects were for him
the manifestation of one power. It may be pointed out that at a
still later age the external effects in nature were thought of as
being akin to the inner processes in a way that did not provide for a
soul in the present sense as distinct from the body. Even
in the time of intellectual world conception, the idea of the
temperaments still preserves this point of view as a reminiscence of
earlier times.
One called the melancholic temperament, the earthy; the phlegmatic,
the watery; the sanguinic, the airy; the choleric, the fiery. These
are not merely allegorical expressions. One did not feel a completely
separated soul element, but experienced in oneself a soul-body entity
as a unity. In this unity was felt the stream of forces that go, for
instance, through a phlegmatic soul, to be like the forces in external
nature that are experienced in the effects of water. One saw these
external water effects to be the same as what the soul experienced in
a phlegmatic mood. The thought habits of today must attempt an empathy
with the old modes of conception if they want to penetrate into the
soul life of earlier times.
In this way one will find in the world conception of Thales an
expression of what his soul life, which was akin to the phlegmatic
temperament, caused him to experience inwardly. He experienced in
himself what appeared to him to be the world mystery of water. The
allusion to the phlegmatic temperament of a person is likely to be
associated with a derogatory meaning of the term. Justified as this
may be in many cases, it is nevertheless also true that the phlegmatic
temperament, when it is combined with an energetic, objective
imagination, makes a sage out of a man because of its calmness,
collectedness and freedom from passion. Such a disposition in Thales
probably caused him to be celebrated by the Greeks as one of their
wise men.
For Anaximenes, the world picture formed itself in another way. He
experienced in himself the sanguine temperament. A word of his has
been handed down to us that immediately shows how he felt the air
element as an expression of the world mystery. As our soul,
which is a breath, holds us together, so air and breath envelop the
universe.
The world conception of Heraclitus will, in an unbiased contemplation,
be felt directly as a manifestation of his choleric inner life. A
member of one of the most noble families of Ephesus, he became a
violent antagonist of the democratic party because he had arrived at
certain views, the truth of which was apparent to him in his immediate
inner experience. The views of those around him, compared with his
own, seemed to him to prove directly in a most natural way, the
foolishness of his environment. Thus, he got into such conflicts that
he left his native city and led a solitary life at the Temple of
Artemis. Consider these few of his sayings that have come down to us.
It would be good if the Ephesians hanged themselves as soon as
they grew up and surrendered their city to those under age. Or
the one about men, Fools in their lack of understanding, even if
they hear the truth, are like the deaf: of them does the saying bear
witness that they are absent when present.
The feeling that is expressed in such a choleric temperament finds
itself akin to the consuming activity of fire. It does not live in the
restful calm of being. It feels itself as one with eternal
becoming. Such a soul feels stationary existence to be an
absurdity. Everything flows, is, therefore, a famous
saying of Heraclitus. It is only apparently so if somewhere an
unchanging being seems to be given. We are lending expression to a
feeling of Heraclitus if we say, The rock seems to represent an
absolute unchanging state of being, but this is only appearance; it is
inwardly in the wildest commotion; all its parts act upon one
another. The mode of thinking of Heraclitus is usually
characterized by his saying, One cannot twice enter the same
stream, for the second time the water is not the same. A
disciple of Heraclitus, Cratylus, goes still further by saying that
one could not even enter the same stream once. Thus it is with all
things. While we look at what is apparently unchanging, it has already
turned into something else in the general stream of existence.
We do not consider a world conception in its full significance if we
accept only its thought content. Its essential element lies in the
mood it communicates to the soul, that is, in the vital force that
grows out of it. One must realize how Heraclitus feels himself with
his own soul in the stream of becoming. The world soul pulsates in his
own human soul and communicates to it of its own life as long as the
human soul knows itself as living in it. Out of such a feeling of
union with the world soul, the thought originates in Heraclitus,
Whatever lives has death in itself through the stream of
becoming that is running through everything, but death again has life
in itself. Life and death are in our living and dying. Everything has
everything else in itself; only thus can eternal becoming flow through
everything. The ocean is the purest and impurest water,
drinkable and wholesome to fishes, to men undrinkable and
pernicious. Life and death are the same, waking and
sleeping, young and old; the first changes into the second and again
into the first. Good and evil are one. The
straight path and the crooked . . . are one.
Anaximander is freer from the inner life, more surrendered to the
element of thought itself. He sees the origin of things in a kind of
world ether, an indefinite formless basic entity that has no limits.
Take the Zeus of Pherekydes, deprive him of every image content that
he still possesses and you have the original principle of Anaximander:
Zeus turned into thought. A personality appears in Anaximander in whom
thought life is borne out of the mood of soul that still has, in the
preceding thinkers, the color of temperament. Such a personality feels
united as a soul with the life of thought, and thereby is not so
intimately interwoven with nature as the soul that does not yet
experience thought as an independent element. It feels itself
connected with a world order that lies above the events of
nature. When Anaximander says that men lived first as fishes in the
moist element and then developed through land animal forms, he means
that the spirit germ, which man recognizes through thinking as his
true being, has gone through the other forms only as through
preliminary stages, with the aim of giving itself eventually the shape
that has been appropriate for him from the beginning.
The thinkers mentioned so far are succeeded historically by
Xenophanes of Kolophon (born 570 B.C.); Parmenides (460
B.C., living as a teacher in Athens), younger and inwardly related to
Xenophanes; Zenon of Elea (who reached his peak around 500
B.C.); Melissos of Samos (about 450 B.C.).
The thought element is already alive to such a degree in these
thinkers that they demand a world conception in which the life of
thought is fully satisfied; they recognize truth only in this form.
How must the world ground be constituted so that it can be fully
absorbed within thinking? This is their question.
Xenophanes finds that the popular gods cannot stand the test of
thought; therefore, he rejects them. His god must be capable of being
thought. What the senses perceive is changeable, is burdened
with qualities not appropriate to thought, whose function it is to
seek what is permanent. Therefore, God is the unchangeable, eternal
unity of all things to be seized in thought.
Parmenides sees the Untrue, the Deceiving, in sense-perceived,
external nature. He sees what alone is true in the Unity, the
Imperishable that is seized by thought. Zeno tries to come to terms
with, and do justice to, the thought experience by pointing out the
contradictions that result from a world view that sees truth in the
change of things, in the process of becoming, in the multiplicity that
is shown by the external world. One of the contradictions pointed out
by Zeno is that the fastest runner (Achilles) could not catch up with
a turtle, for no matter how slowly it moved, the moment Achilles
arrived at the point it had just occupied, it would have moved on a
little. Through such contradictions Zeno intimates how a conceptual
imagination that leans on the external world is caught in
self-contradiction. He points to the difficulty such thought meets
when it attempts to find the truth.
One will recognize the significance of this world conception, which is
called the eleatic view (Parmenides and Zeno are from
Elea), if one considers that those who hold this view have advanced
with the development of thought experience to the point of having
transformed it into a special art, the so-called dialectic. In the
art of thought the soul learns to feel itself in its
self-dependence and its inward self-sufficiency. With this step, the
reality of the soul is felt to be what it is through its own being. It
experiences itself through the fact that it no longer, as in earlier
times, follows the general world experience with its life, but unfolds
independent thought experience within itself. This experience is
rooted in itself and through it, it can feel itself planted into a
pure spiritual ground of the world. At first, this feeling is not
expressed as a distinctly formulated thought but, in the esteem it
enjoyed, it can be sensed vividly as a feeling in this age. According
to a Dialogue of Plato, the young Socrates is told by Parmenides that
he should learn the art of thought from Zeno; otherwise,
truth would be unattainable for him. This art of thought
was felt to be a necessity for the human soul intending to approach
the spiritual fundamental grounds of existence.
Whoever does not see how, in the progress of human development toward
the stage of thought experience, real experiences the picture
experiences came to an end with the beginning of this thought life,
will not see the special quality of the Greek thinkers from the sixth
to the fourth pre-Christian centuries in the light in which they must
appear in this presentation. Thought formed a wall around the human
soul, so to speak. The soul had formerly felt as if it were within the
phenomena of nature. What it experienced in these natural phenomena,
like the activities of its own body, presents itself to the soul in
the form of images that appeared in vivid reality. Through the power
of thought this entire panorama was now extinguished. Where previously
images saturated in content prevailed, thought now expanded through
the external world. The soul could experience itself in the
surroundings of space and time only if it united itself with thought.
One senses such a mood of soul in Anaxagoras of Clazomenae in
Asia Minor (born 500 B.C.). He found himself deeply bound up in his
soul with thought life. His thought life encompassed what is extended
in space and time. Expanded like this, it appears as the nous,
the world reason. It penetrates the whole of nature as an entity.
Nature, however, presents itself as composed only of little basic
entities. The events of nature that result from the combined actions
of these fundamental entities are what the senses perceive after the
texture of imagery has vanished from nature. These fundamental
entities are called homoiomeries. The soul experiences in
thought the connection with the world reason (the nous) inside its
wall. Through the windows of the senses it watches what the world
reason causes to come into being through the action of the
homoiomeries on each other.
Empedocles (born 490 B.C. in Agrigent) was a personality in whose
soul the old and the new modes of conception clash as in a violent
antagonism. He still feels something of the old mode of being in which
the soul was more closely interwoven with external existence. Hatred
and love, antipathy and sympathy live in the human soul. They also live
outside the wall that encloses it. The life of the soul is thus
homogeneously extended beyond its boundaries and it appears in forces
that separate and connect the elements of external nature air,
fire, water and earth thereby causing what the senses perceive
in the outer world.
Empedocles is, as it were, confronted with nature, which appears to
the senses to be deprived of life and soul, and he develops a soul
mood that revolts against this extirpation of nature's animation. His
soul cannot believe that nature really is what thought wants to make
of it. Least of all can it admit that it should stand in such a
relation to nature as it appears according to the intellectual world
conception. We must imagine what goes on in a soul that senses such a
discord in all its harshness, suffering from it. We shall then be
capable of entering into the experience of how, in this soul of
Empedocles, the old mode of conception is resurrected as the power of
intimate feeling but is unwilling to raise this fact into full
consciousness. It thus seeks a form of existence in a shade of
experience hovering between thought and picture that is reechoed in
the sayings of Empedocles. These lose their strangeness if they are
understood in this way. The following aphorism is attributed to him.
Farewell. A mortal no longer, but an immortal god I wander about
. . . and as soon as I come into the flourishing cities I am
worshipped by men and women. They follow me by the thousands, seeking
the path of their salvation with me, some expecting prophecies,
others, curative charms for many diseases.
In such a way, a soul that is haunted by an old form of consciousness
through which it feels its own existence as that of a banished god who
is cast out of another form of existence into the soul-deprived world
of the senses, is dazed. He therefore feels the earth to be an
unaccustomed place into which he is cast as in punishment.
There are certainly other sentiments also to be found in the soul of
Empedocles because significant flashes of wisdom shine in his
aphorisms. His feeling with respect to the birth of the
intellectual world conception is characterized, however, by the
thought mood mentioned above.
The thinkers who are called the atomists regarded what nature had
become for the soul of man through the birth of thought in a different
way. The most important among them is Democritus (born 460 B.C.
in Abdera). Leucippus is a kind of forerunner to him.
With Democritus, the homoiomeries of Anaxagoras have become, to a
considerable degree, more material. In Anaxagoras, one can still
compare the entities of the basic parts with living germs. With
Democritus, they become dead indivisible particles of matter, which in
their different combinations make up the things of the outer world.
They mix freely as they move to and fro; thus, the events of nature
come to pass. The world reason (nous) of Anaxagoras, which has the
world processes grow out of the combined action of the homoiomeries
like a spiritual (incorporeal) consciousness, with Democritus, turns
into the unconscious law of nature (ananke). The soul is ready
to recognize only what it can grasp as the result of simple thought
combinations. Nature is now completely deprived of life and soul;
thought has paled as a soul experience into the inner shadow of
inanimate nature. In this way, with Democritus, the intellectual
prototype of all more or less materialistically colored world
conceptions of later times has made its appearance.
The atom world of Democritus represents an external world, a nature in
which no trace of soul life can be found. The thought experiences in
the soul, through which the soul has become aware of itself, are mere
shadow experiences in Democritus. Thus, a part of the fate of thought
experiences is characterized. They bring the human soul to the
consciousness of its own being, but they fill it at the same time with
uncertainty about itself. The soul experiences itself in itself
through thought, but it can at the same time feel that it lost its
anchorage in the independent spiritual world power that used to lend
it security and inner stability. This emancipation of the soul was
felt by the group of men in Greek intellectual life known as
Sophists. The most important among them is Protagoras
of Abdera (480 410 B.C.). Also to be noted besides him are
Gorgias, Critias, Hippias, Thrasymachus and Prodicus.
The sophists are often presented as men who superficially played with
their thinking. Much has been contributed to this opinion by the
manner in which Aristophanes, the playwright of comedies, treated
them, but there are many things that can lead to a better appreciation
of the sophists. It is noteworthy that even Socrates, who to a certain
limited extent thought of himself as a pupil of Prodicus, is said to
have described him as a man who had done much for the refinement of
the speech and thinking of his disciples.
Protagoras's view is expressed in the famous statement, Man is
the measure of all things, of those that are, that they are; of those
that are not, that they are not. In the sentiment underlying
this statement the thought experience feels itself sovereign. It does
not sense any connection with an objective world power. If Parmenides
is of the opinion that the senses supply man with a world of
deception, one could go further and add, Why should not
thinking, although one experiences it, also deceive? Protagoras,
however, would reply to this, Why should it be man's concern if
the world outside him is not as he perceives and thinks it? Does he
imagine it for anyone else but himself? No matter how it may be for
another being, this should be of no concern to man. The contents of
his mind are only to serve him; with their aid he is to find his way
through the world. Once he achieves complete clarity about himself, he
cannot wish for any thought contents about the world except those that
serve him. Protagoras means to be able to build on thinking. For
this purpose he intends to have it rest exclusively on its own
sovereign power.
With this step, however, Protagoras places himself in contradiction to
the spirit that lives in the depths of Greek life. This spirit is
distinctly perceptible in the Greek character. It manifests itself in
the inscription, Know Thyself, at the temple of Delphi.
This ancient oracle wisdom speaks as if it contained the challenge for
the progress of world conceptions that advances from the conception in
images to the form of consciousness in which the secrets of the world
are seized through thought. Through this challenge man is directed to
his own soul. He is told that he can hear the language in his soul
through which the world expresses its essence. He is thereby also
directed toward something that produces uncertainties and insecurities
for itself in its experience. The leading spirits of Greek
civilization were to conquer the dangers of this self-supporting soul
life. Thus, they were to develop thought in the soul into a world
conception.
In the course of this development the sophists navigated in dangerous
straits. In them the Greek spirit places itself at an abyss; it means
to produce the strength of equilibrium through its own power. One
should, as has been pointed out, consider the gravity and boldness of
this attempt, rather than lightly condemn it even though condemnation
is certainly justified for many of the sophists.
This attempt of the sophists takes place at a natural turning point of
Greek life. Protagoras lived from 480 to 410 B.C. The Peloponnesian
War, which occurred at this turning point of Greek civilization,
lasted from 431 to 404 B.C. Before this war the individual member of
Greek society had been firmly enclosed by his social connections.
Commonwealth and tradition provided the measuring stick for his
actions and thinking. The individual person had value and significance
only as a member of the total structure. Under such circumstances the
question, What is the value of the individual human being?
could not be asked. The sophists, however, do ask this question, and
in so doing introduce the era of Greek Enlightenment. Fundamentally,
it is the question of how man arranges his life after he has become
aware of his awakened thought life.
From Pherekydes (or Thales) to the sophists, one can observe how
emaciated thought in Greece, which had already been born before these
men, gradually finds its place in the stream of philosophical
development. The effect thought has when it is placed in the service
of world conception becomes apparent in them. The birth of thought,
however, is to be observed in the entire Greek life. One could show
much the same kind of development in the fields of art, poetry, public
life, the various crafts and trades, and one would see everywhere how
human activity changes under the influence of the form of human
organization that introduces thought into the world conception. It is
not correct to say that philosophy discovers thought. It
comes into existence through the fact that the newly born thought life
is used for the construction of a world picture that formerly had been
formed out of experiences of a different kind.
While the sophists led the spirit of Greece, expressed in the motto,
Know Thyself, to the edge of a dangerous cliff, Socrates,
who was born in Athens about 470 and was condemned to death through
poison in 399 B.C., expressed this spirit with a high degree of
perfection.
Historically, the picture of Socrates has come down to us through two
channels of tradition. In one, we have the figure that his great
disciple, Plato (427 347 B.C.), has drawn of him. Plato presents his
philosophy in dialogue form, and Socrates appears in these dialogues
as a teacher. He is shown as the sage who leads the
persons around him through intellectual guidance to high stages of
insight. A second picture has been drawn by Xenophon in his
Memorabilia of Socrates. At first sight it seems as if Plato
had idealized the character of Socrates and as if Xenophon had
portrayed him more directly as he had been. But a more intimate
inspection would likely show that both Plato and Xenophon each drew a
picture of Socrates as they saw him from a special point of view. One
is justified, therefore, in considering the question as to how these
pictures supplement and illuminate each other.
The first thing that must appear significant here is that Socrates'
philosophy has come down to posterity entirely as an expression of his
personality, of the fundamental character of his soul life. Both Plato
and Xenophon present Socrates in such a way that in him his personal
opinion speaks everywhere. This personality carries in itself the
awareness that, whoever expresses his personal opinion out of the true
ground of the soul, expresses something that is more than just human
opinion, something that is a manifestation of the purposes of the
world order through human thinking. By those who think they know him,
Socrates is taken as the living proof for the conviction that truth is
revealed in the human soul through thinking if, as was the case with
Socrates, this soul is grounded in its own substance. Looking on
Socrates, Plato does not teach a doctrine that is asserted by
contemplative thought, but the thought has a rightly developed human
being speak, who then observes what he produces as truth. Thus, the
manner in which Plato behaves toward Socrates becomes an expression
for what man is in his relation to the world. What Plato has advanced
about Socrates is significant and also the way in which he, in his
activity as a writer, has placed Socrates in the world of Greek
spiritual life.
With the birth of thought man was directed toward his
soul. The question now arises as to what this soul says
when it begins to speak, expressing what the world forces have laid
into it. Through the attitude Plato takes with respect to Socrates,
the resulting answer is that in the human soul the reason of the world
speaks what it intends to reveal to man. The foundation is laid with
this step for the confidence expressed in the revelations of
the human soul insofar as it develops thought in itself. The
figure of Socrates appears in the sign of this confidence.
In ancient times the Greek consulted the oracles in the most important
questions of life. He asked for prophecy, the revelation of the will
and the opinion of the spiritual powers. Such an arrangement is in
accord with the soul experience in images. Through the image man feels
himself bound to the powers holding sway over the world. The oracle,
then, is the institution by means of which somebody who is especially
gifted in that direction finds his way to the spiritual powers better
than other people. As long as one did not experience one's soul as
separated from the outer world, the feeling was natural that this
external world was able to express more through a special institution
than through everyday experience. The picture spoke from without. Why
should the outer world not be capable of speaking distinctly at a
special place? Thought speaks to the inner soul. With thought,
therefore, the soul is left to its own resources; it cannot
feel united with another soul as with the revelations of a priestly
oracle. To thought, one had to lend one's own soul. One felt of
thought that it was a common possession of all men.
World reason shines into thought life without especially established
institutions. Socrates felt that the force lives in the thinking soul
that used to be sought in the oracles. He experienced the
daimonion in himself, the spiritual force that leads the
soul. Thought has brought the soul to the consciousness of itself.
With his conception of the daimonion speaking in him that, always
leading him, told him what to do, Socrates meant to say, The
soul that has found its way to the thought life is justified to feel
as if it communicated in itself with the world reason. It is an
expression of the high valuation of what the soul possesses in its
thought experience.
Virtue, under the influence of this view, is placed in a
special light. Because Socrates values thought, he must presuppose
that true virtue in human life reveals itself in the life of thought.
True virtue must be found in thought life because it is from thought
life that man derives his value. Virtue is teachable. In
this way is Socrates' conception most frequently expressed. It is
teachable because whoever really seizes thought life must be in its
possession. What Xenophon says about Socrates is significant in this
respect. Socrates teaches a disciple about virtue and the following
dialogue develops.
Do you believe there is a doctrine and science of justice, just as
there is a doctrine of grammar?
Whom do you consider now as better versed in grammar, the one who
intentionally writes and reads incorrectly, or the one who does so
without intention?
I should think the one who does it intentionally, for if he meant to,
he could also do it correctly.
Does it not seem to you that the one who intentionally writes
incorrectly knows how to write, but the other one does not?
Who now understands more of justice, he who intentionally lies or
cheats, or he who does so inadvertently?
Socrates attempts to make clear to the disciple that what matters is
to have the right thoughts about virtue. So also what Socrates says
about virtue aims at the establishment of confidence in a soul
that knows itself through thought experience. The right thoughts about
virtue are to be trusted more than all other motivations. Virtue makes
man more valuable when he experiences it in thought.
Thus, what the pre-Socratic age strove for becomes manifest in
Socrates, that is, the appreciation of what humanity has been given
through the awakened thought life. Socrates' method of teaching is
under the influence of this conception. He approaches man with the
presupposition that thought in life is in him; it only needs to be
awakened. It is for this reason that he arranges his questions in such
a way that the questioned person is stimulated to awaken his own
thought life. This is the substance of the Socratic method.
Plato, who was born in Athens in 427 B.C., felt, as a disciple
of Socrates, that his master had helped him to consolidate his confidence
in the life of thought. What the entire previous development tended to
bring into appearance reaches a climax in Plato. This is the conception
that in thought life the world spirit reveals itself. The awareness of
this conception sheds, to begin with, its light over all of Plato's soul
life. Nothing that man knows through the senses or otherwise has any
value as long as the soul has not exposed it to the light of thought.
Philosophy becomes for Plato the science of ideas as the world
of true being, and the idea is the manifestation of the world
spirit through the revelation of thought. The light of the world spirit
shines into the soul of man and reveals itself there in the form of
ideas; the human soul, in seizing the idea, unites itself with
the force of the world spirit. The world that is spread in space and
time is like the mass of the ocean water in which the stars are reflected,
but what is real is only reflected as idea. Thus, for Plato, the whole
world changes into ideas that act upon each other. Their effect in the
world is produced through the fact that the ideas are reflected in
hyle, the original matter. What we see as the many individual
things and events comes to pass through this reflection. We need not
extend knowledge to hyle, the original matter, however, for in it is no
truth. We reach truth only if we strip the world picture of everything
that is not idea. For Plato, the human soul is living in the idea, but
this life is so constituted that the soul is not a manifestation of its
life in the ideas in all its utterances. Insofar as it is submerged in
the life of ideas, it appears as the "rational soul
(thought-bearing soul), and as such, the soul appears to itself when
it becomes aware of itself in thought perception. It must also manifest
itself in such a way that it appears as the "non-rational soul
(not-thought-bearing soul), As such, it again appears in a twofold way
as courage-developing, and as appetitive soul. Thus, Plato seems to
distinguish three members or parts in the human soul: The rational soul,
the courage-like (or will-exertive) soul and the appetitive soul. We
shall, however, describe the spirit of his conceptional approach better
if we express it in a different way. According to its nature, the soul
is a member of the world of ideas, but it acts in such a way that it
adds an activity to its life in reason through its courage life and
its appetitive life. In this threefold mode of utterance it appears as
earthbound soul. It descends as a rational soul through physical birth
into a terrestrial existence, and with death again enters the world of
ideas. Insofar as it is rational soul, it is immortal, for as
such it shares with its life the eternal existence of the world of ideas.
Plato's doctrine of the soul emerges as a significant fact in the age
of thought perception. The awakened thought directed man's attention
toward the soul. A perception of the soul develops in Plato that is
entirely the result of thought perception. Thought in Plato has become
bold enough not only to point toward the soul but to express what the
soul is, as it were, to describe it. What thought has to say about the
soul gives it the force to know itself in the eternal. Indeed,
thought in the soul even sheds light on the nature of the temporal by
expanding its own being beyond this temporal existence. The soul
perceives thought. As the soul appears in its terrestrial life, it
could not produce in itself the pure form of thought. Where does the
thought experience come from if it cannot be developed in the life on
earth? It represents a reminiscence of a pre-terrestrial,
purely spiritual state of being. Thought has seized the soul in such a
way that it is not satisfied by the soul's terrestrial form of
existence. It has been revealed to the soul in an earlier state of
being (preexistence) in the spirit world (world of ideas) and the soul
recalls it during its terrestrial existence through the reminiscence
of the life it has spent in the spirit.
What Plato has to say about the moral life follows from this soul
conception. The soul is moral if it so arranges life that it exerts
itself to the largest possible measure as rational soul. Wisdom
is the virtue that stems from the rational soul; it ennobles human
life. Fortitude is the virtue of the will-exertive soul;
Temperance is that of the appetitive soul. These virtues come
to pass when the rational soul becomes the ruler over the other
manifestations of the soul. When all three virtues harmoniously act
together, there emerges what Plato calls, Justice, the
direction toward the Good, Dikaiosyne.
Plato's disciple, Aristotle (born 384 B.C. in Stageira,
Thracia, died 321 B.C.), together with his teacher, represents a
climax in Greek thinking. With him the process of the absorption of
thought life into the world conception has been completed and come to
rest. Thought takes its rightful possession of its function to
comprehend, out of its own resources, the being and events of the
world. Plato still uses his conceptual imagination to bring thought to
its rightful authority and to lead it into the world of ideas. With
Aristotle, this authority has become a matter of course. It is now a
question of confirming it everywhere in the various fields of
knowledge. Aristotle understands how to use thought as a tool that
penetrates into the essence of things. For Plato, it had been the task
to overcome the thing or being of the external world. When it has been
overcome, the soul carries in itself the idea of which the external
being had only been overshadowed, but which had been foreign to it,
hovering over it in a spiritual world of truth. Aristotle intends to
submerge into the beings and events, and what the soul finds in this
submersion, it accepts as the essence of the thing itself. The soul
feels as if it had only lifted this essence out of the thing and as if
it had brought this essence for its own consumption into the thought
form in order to be able to carry it in itself as a reminder of the
thing. To Aristotle's mind, the ideas are in the things and events.
They are the side of the things through which these things have a
foundation of their own in the underlying material, matter (hyle).
Plato, like Aristotle, lets his conception of the soul shed its light
on his entire world conception. In both thinkers we describe the
fundamental constitution of their philosophy as a whole if we succeed
in determining the basic characteristics of their soul conceptions. To
be sure, for both of them many detailed studies would have to be
considered that cannot be attempted in this sketch. But the direction
their mode of conception took is, for both, indicated in their soul
conceptions.
Plato is concerned with what lives in the soul and, as such, shares in
the spirit world. What is important for Aristotle is the question of
how the soul presents itself for man in his own knowledge. As it does
with other things, the soul must also submerge into itself in order to
find what constitutes its own essence. The idea, which, according to
Aristotle, man finds in a thing outside his soul, is the essence of
the thing, but the soul has brought this essence into the form of an
idea in order to have it for itself. The idea does not have its
reality in the cognitive soul but in the external thing in connection
with its material (hyle). If the soul submerges into itself, however,
it finds the idea as such in reality. The soul in this sense is idea,
but active idea, an entity exerting action, and it behaves also in the
life of man as such an active entity. In the process of germination of
man it lays hold upon material existence.
While idea and matter constitute an inseparable unity in an external
thing, this is not the case with the human soul and its body. Here the
independent human soul seizes upon the corporeal part, renders the
idea ineffective that has been active in the body before and inserts
itself in its place. In Aristotle's view, a soul-like principle is
active already in the bodily element with which the human soul unites
itself, for he sees also in the bodies of the plants and of animals,
soul-like entities of a subordinate kind at work. A body that carries
in itself the soul elements of the plant and animal is, as it were,
fructified by the human soul. Thus, for the terrestrial man, a
body-soul entity is linked up with a spirit-soul entity. The
spirit-soul entity suppresses the independent activity of the
body-soul element during the earth life of man and uses the body-soul
entity as an instrument. Five soul manifestations come into being
through this process. These, in Aristotle, appear as five members of
the soul: The plant-like soul (threptikon), the sentient soul
(aisthetikon), the desire-developing soul (orektikon), the
will-exerting soul (kinetikon) and the spirit-soul (dianoetikon). Man
is spiritual soul through what belongs to the spiritual world and
what, in the process of germination, links itself up with the
body-soul entity. The other members of the soul come into being as the
spiritual soul unfolds itself in the body and thereby leads its earth
life.
With Aristotle's focus on a spiritual soul the perspective toward a
spiritual world in general is naturally given. The world picture of
Aristotle stands before our contemplative eye in such a way that we
see below the life of things and events, thus presenting matter and
idea; the higher we lift our eye, the more we see vanish whatever
bears a material character. Pure spiritual essence appears,
representing itself to man as idea, that is, the sphere of the world
in which deity as pure spirituality that moves everything has its
being. The spiritual soul of man belongs to this world sphere; before
it is united with a body-soul entity, it does not exist as an
individual being but only as a part of the world spirit. Through this
connection it acquires its individual existence separated from the
world spirit and continues to live after the separation from the body
as a spiritual being. Thus, the individual soul entity has its
beginning with the human earthly life and then lives on as immortal. A
preexistence of the soul before earth life is assumed by Plato but not
by Aristotle. The denial of the soul's preexistence is as natural to
Aristotle, who has the idea exist in the thing, as the opposite view
is natural to Plato, who conceives of the idea as hovering over the
thing. Aristotle finds the idea in the thing, and the soul acquires in
its body what it is to be in the spirit world as an individuality.
Aristotle is the thinker who has brought thought to the point where it
unfolds to a world conception through its contact with the essence of
the world. The age before Aristotle led to the experience of thought;
Aristotle seizes the thoughts and applies them to whatever he finds in
the world. The natural way, peculiar to Aristotle, in which he lives
in thought as a matter of course, leads him also to investigate logic,
the laws of thought itself. Such a science could only come into being
after the awakened thought had reached a stage of great maturity and
of such a harmonious relationship to the things of the outer world as
we find it in Aristotle.
Compared with Aristotle, the other thinkers of antiquity who appear as
his contemporaries or as his successors seem to be of much less
significance. They give the impression that their abilities lack a
certain energy that prevents them from attaining the stage of insight
Aristotle had reached. One gets the feeling that they disagree with
him because they are stating opinions about things they do not
understand as well as he. One is inclined to explain their views by
pointing to the deficiency that led them to utter opinions that have
already been disproved essentially in Aristotle's work.
To begin with, one can receive such an impression from the Stoics
and the Epicureans. Zeno of Kition (342 270 B.C.),
Kleanthes (born 200 B.C.), Chrysippus (282 209 B.C.),
and others belong to the Stoics, whose name was derived from the Hall
of Columns in Athens, the Stoa. They accept what appears reasonable to
them in earlier world conceptions, but they are mainly concerned with
finding out what man's position is in the world by contemplation of
it. They want to base on this, their decision as to how to arrange
life in such a way that it is in agreement with the world order, and
also in such a way that man can unfold his life in this world order
according to his own nature. According to them, man dulls his natural
being through desire, passion and covetousness. Through equanimity and
freedom from desire, he feels best what he is meant to be and what he
can be. The ideal man is the sage who does not hamper the
process of the inner development of the human being by any vice.
As the thinkers before Aristotle were striving to obtain the knowledge
that, after him, becomes accessible to man through the ability to
perceive thoughts in the full consciousness of his soul, with the
Stoics, reflection concentrates on the question as to what man is to
do in order to express his nature as a human being in the best way.
Epicurus (born 324 B.C., died 270 B.C.) developed in his own way
the elements that had already been latent in the earlier atomistic
thinkers. He builds a view of life on this foundation that can be
considered to be an answer to the question: As the human soul emerges
as the blossom of world processes, how is it to live in order to shape
its separate existence, its self-dependence in accordance with thinking
guided by reason? Epicurus could answer this question only by a method
that considered life only between birth and death, for nothing else can,
with perfect intellectual honesty, be derived from the atomistic world
conception. The fact of pain must appear to such a conception as a
peculiar enigma of life. For pain is one of those facts that drive the
soul out of the consciousness of its unity with the things of the world.
One can consider the motion of the stars and the fall of rain to be like
the motion of one's own hand, as was done in the world conception of
more remote antiquity. That is to say, one can feel in both kinds of
events the same uniform spirit-soul reality. The fact that events can
produce pain in man but cannot do so in the external world, however,
drives the soul to the recognition of its own special nature. A doctrine
of virtues, which, like the one of Epicurus, endeavors to live in
harmony with world reason, can, as may easily be conceived, appreciate
an ideal of life that leads to the avoidance of pain and displeasure.
Thus, everything that does away with displeasure becomes the highest
Epicurean life value.
This view of life found numerous followers in later antiquity,
especially among Roman gentlemen of cultural aspiration. The Roman
poet, T. Lucretius Carus (95 52 B.C.), has expressed it in perfect
artistic form in his poem, De Rerum Natura.
The process of perceiving thoughts leads the soul to the recognition
of its own being, but it can also occur that the soul feels powerless
to deepen its thought experience sufficiently to find a connection
with the grounds of the world through this experience. The soul then
finds itself torn loose from these grounds through its own thinking.
It feels that thinking contains its own being, but it does not find a
way to recognize in its thought life anything but its own statement.
The soul can then only surrender to a complete renunciation of any
kind of true knowledge. Pyrrho (360 270 B.C.) and his
followers, whose philosophical belief is called scepticism, were in
such a situation. Scepticism, the philosophy of doubt, attributes no
other power to the thought experience than the formation of human
opinions about the world. Whether or not these opinions have any
significance for the world outside man is a question about which it is
unwilling to make a decision.
[A true skeptic is agnostic on a subject. Doubt denotes
an opinion for which a burden of proof is needed. Skepticism should be
neutral – e.Ed]
In a certain sense, one can see a well-rounded picture in the series
of Greek thinkers. One will have to admit, of course, that such an
attempt to connect the views of the individual thinkers only too
easily brings out irrelevant aspects of secondary significance. What
remains most important is still the contemplation of the individual
personalities and the impressions one can gain concerning the fact of
how, in these personalities, the general human element is brought to
manifestation in special cases. One can observe a process in this line
of Greek thinkers that can be called the birth, growth and life of
thought: in the pre-Socratic thinkers, the prelude; in Socrates, Plato
and Aristotle, the culmination; after them, a decline and a kind of
dissolution of thought life.
Whoever contemplates this development can arrive at the question as to
whether thought life really has the power to give everything to the
soul toward which it has led it by bringing it to the complete
consciousness of itself. For the unbiased observer, Greek thought life
has an element that makes it appear perfect in the best
sense of the word. It is as if the energy of thought in the Greek
thinkers had worked out everything that it contains in itself. Whoever
judges differently will notice on closer inspection that somewhere in
his judgment an error is involved. Later world conceptions have
produced accomplishments through other forces of the soul. Of the
later thoughts as such, it can always be shown that with respect to
their real thought content they can already be found in some earlier
Greek thinker. What can be thought and how one can doubt about
thinking and knowledge, all enters the field of consciousness in Greek
civilization, and in the manifestation of thought the soul takes
possession of its own being.
Has Greek thought life, however, shown the soul that it has the power
to supply it with everything that it has stimulated in it? The
philosophical current called Neo-Platonism, which in a way forms an
aftermath of Greek thought life, was confronted with this question.
Plotinus (205 270 A.D.) was its chief representative.
Philo, who lived at the beginning of the Christian era in
Alexandria, could be considered a forerunner of this movement. He does
not base his effort to construct a world conception on the creative
energy of thought. Rather, he applies thought in order to
understand the revelation of the Old Testament. He interprets what is
told in this document as fact in an intellectual, allegorical manner.
For him, the accounts of the Old Testament turn into symbols for soul
events to which he attempts to gain access intellectually.
Plotinus does not regard thought experience as something that embraces
the soul in its full life. Behind thought life another life of the
soul must lie, a soul life that would be concealed rather than
revealed by the action of thought. The soul must overcome the life in
thought, must extinguish it in itself and only after this extinction
can it arrive at a form of experience that unites it with the origin
of the world. Thought leads the soul to itself; now it must seize
something in itself that will again lead it out of the realm into
which thought has brought it. What Plotinus strives for is an
illumination that begins in the soul after it has left the
realm to which it has been carried by thought. In this way he expects
to rise up to a world being that does not enter into thought life.
World reason, therefore, toward which Plato and Aristotle strive, is
not, according to Plotinus, the last reality at which the soul
arrives. It is rather the outgrowth of a still higher reality that
lies beyond all thinking. From this reality beyond all thought, which
cannot be compared with anything that could be a possible object of
thought, all world processes emanate.
Thought, as it could manifest itself in Greek spiritual life, has, as
it were, gone through a complete revolution and thereby all possible
relationships of man to thought seem to be exhausted. Plotinus looks
for sources other than those given in thought revelation. He leaves
the continuing evolution of thought life and enters the realm of
mysticism. It is not intended to give a description of the development
of mysticism here, but only the development of thought life and what
has its origin in this process is to be outlined. There are, however,
at various points in the spiritual development of mankind connections
between intellectual world conceptions and mysticism. We find such a
point of contact in Plotinus. His soul life is not ruled only by
thinking. He has a mystical experience that presents an inner
awareness without the presence of thoughts in his soul. In this
experience he finds his soul united with the world foundation. His way
of presenting the connection of the world with its ground, however, is
to be expressed in thoughts. The reality beyond thought is the most
perfect; what proceeds from it is less perfect. In this way, the
process continues down into the visible world, the most imperfect. Man
finds himself in this world of imperfection. Through the act of
perfecting his soul, he is to cast off what the world in which he
finds himself can give him, and is thus to find a path of development
through which he becomes a being that is of one accord with the
perfect origin.
We see a personality in Plotinus who feels the impossibility to
continue Greek thought life. He cannot find anything that would grow
as a further branch of world conception out of thought itself. If one
looks for the sense in which the evolution of philosophy proceeds, one
is justified in saying that the formation of picture conception has
turned into that of thought conceptions. In a similar way, the
production of thought conception must change again into something
else, but the evolution of the world conception is not ready for this
in the age of Plotinus. He therefore abandons thought and searches
outside thought experience. Greek thoughts, however, fructified by his
mystical experiences, develop into the evolutionary ideas that present
the world process as a sequence of stages proceeding in a descending
order, from a highest most perfect being to imperfect beings. In the
thinking of Plotinus, Greek thoughts continue to have their effect.
They do not develop as an organic growth of the original forces,
however, but are taken over into the mystical consciousness. They do
not undergo a transformation through their own energies but through
nonintellectual forces.
Ammonius Sakkas (175 242), Porphyrius
(232 304), Iamblichus (who lived in the fourth century A.D.),
Proclus (410 485), and others are followers and expounders
of this philosophy.
In a way similar to that of Plotinus and his successors, Greek
thinking in its more Platonic shade continued under the influence of a
nonintellectual element. Greek thought in its Pythagorean nuance is
treated by Nigidius Figulus, Apollonius of Tyana, Moderatus of
Gades, and others.
* This book, which is to give a picture of the world and life
conceptions of the nineteenth century is, in its second edition,
supplemented by a brief account of the preceding philosophies insofar
as they are based on an intellectual conception of the world. I
have done this because I feel that the ideas of the last century are
better shown in their inner significance if they are not taken by
themselves, but if the highlights of thought of the preceding ages
fall on them. In such an introduction not all the
documentary materials can be given that must form the
basis of this short sketch. If I should have the opportunity to
develop the sketch into an independent book, it would become clear
that the appropriate basis really exists. I also have no doubt that
others who want to see in this sketch a suggestion for new viewpoints
will find the documentary evidence in the historical sources that have
been traditionally handed down to us.
|