The Age of Kant and Goethe
Those who struggled for clarity in the great problems of world and
life conceptions at the end of the eighteenth century looked up to two
men of great intellectual-spiritual power, Kant and Goethe.
Another person who strove for such a clarity in the most forceful
way was Johann Gottlieb Fichte. When he had become acquainted
with Kant's Critique of Practical Reason, he wrote:
I am living in a new world. . . . Things I had thought could
never be proven to me, for instance, the concept of absolute freedom
and duty, now have been proven to me and I feel much happier because
of it. It is incomprehensible what a high degree of respect for humanity,
what strength this philosophy gives us; what a blessing it is for an
age in which morality had been destroyed in its foundation, and in
which the concept of duty had been struck from all dictionaries.
And when, on the basis of Kant's conception, he had built his own
Groundwork of all Scientific Knowledge, he sent the book to
Goethe with the words:
I consider you, and always have considered you, to be the
representative of the purest spiritual force of feeling on the level
of development that mankind has reached at the present time. To you
philosophy rightly turns. Your feeling is its touchstone.
A similar attitude to both representative spirits was taken by
Schiller. He writes about Kant on October 28, 1794:
I am not at all frightened by the prospect that the law of change,
which shows no mercy to any human or divine work, will also destroy
the form of the Kantian as well as every other philosophy. Its
foundation, however, will not have to fear this destiny, for since the
human race exists, and as long as there has been a reason, this
philosophy has been silently acknowledged and mankind as a whole has
acted in agreement with its principles.
Schiller describes Goethe's conception in a letter addressed to him on
August 23, 1794:
For a long time I have, although from a considerable distance, watched
the course of your spirit, and with ever increasing admiration I have
observed the path you have marked out for yourself. You are seeking
the necessary in nature, but you are seeking it along the most
difficult road, which any spirit weaker than yours would be most
careful to avoid. You take hold of nature as a whole in order to
obtain light in a particular point; in the totality of nature's
various types of phenomena, you seek the explanation for the
individual. . . . Had you been born a Greek, or even an Italian, and
from the cradle been surrounded by an exquisite nature and an
idealizing art, your path would have been infinitely shortened;
perhaps it would have been made entirely unnecessary. With the first
perception of things you would have caught the form of the Necessary,
and from your first experiences the grand style would have developed
in you. But now, having been born a German, your Greek spirit having
thus been cast into a northern world, you had no choice but that of
becoming a northern artist yourself, or of supplying your imagination
with what it is refused by reality through the help of your power of
thought and thus, to produce a second Greece, as it were, from
within and by means of reason.
Seen from the present age, Kant and Goethe can be considered spirits
in whom the evolution of world conception of modern times reveals
itself as in an important moment of its development. These spirits
experience intensely the enigmatic problems of existence, which have
formerly, in a more preparatory stage, been latent in the substrata of
the life of the soul.
To illustrate the effect that Kant exerted on his age, the statements
of two men who stood at the full height of their time's culture may be
quoted. Jean Paul wrote to a friend in 1788:
For heaven's sake, do buy two books, Kant's Foundation for a
Metaphysics of Morals and his Critique of Practical Reason.
Kant is not a light of the world but a complete radiating solar
system all at once.
Wilhelm von Humboldt makes the statement:
Kant undertook the greatest work that philosophical reason has perhaps
ever owed to a single man. . . . Three things remain unmistakably
certain if one wants to determine the fame that Kant bestowed on his
nation and the benefit that he brought to speculative thinking. Some
of the things he destroyed will never be raised again, some of those
to which he laid the foundation will never perish; most important of
all, he brought about a reform that has no equal in the whole history
of human thought.
This shows how Kant's contemporaries saw a revolutionary event in the
development of world conception in his achievement. Kant himself
considered it so important for this development that he judged its
significance equal to that which Copernicus's discovery of the
planetary motion holds for natural science.
Various currents of philosophical development of previous times
continue their effect in Kant's thinking and are transformed in his
thought into questions that determine the character of his world
conception. The reader who feels the characteristic traits in those of
Kant's writings that are most significant for his view is aware of a
special appreciation of Kant for the mathematical mode of thinking as
one of these traits. Kant feels that what is known in the way
mathematical thinking knows, carries the certainty of its truth in
itself. The fact that man is capable of mathematics proves that he is
capable of truth. Whatever else one may doubt, the truth of
mathematics cannot be doubted.
With this appreciation of mathematics the thought tendency of modern
history of philosophy, which had put the characteristic stamp on
Spinoza's realm of thoughts, appears in Kant's mind. Spinoza wants to
construct his thought sequences in such a form that they develop
strictly from one another as the propositions of mathematical science.
Nothing but what is thought in the mode of thought of mathematics
supplies the firm foundation on which, according to Spinoza, the human
ego feels itself secure in the spirit of the modern age. Descartes had
also thought in this way, and Spinoza had derived from him many
stimulating suggestions. Out of the state of doubt he had to secure a
fulcrum for a world conception for himself. In the mere passive
reception of a thought into the soul, Descartes could not recognize
such a support yielding force. This Greek attitude toward the world of
thought is no longer possible for the man of the modern age. Within
the self-conscious soul something must be found that lends its support
to the thought. For Descartes, and again for Spinoza, this is supplied
by the fulfillment of the postulate that the soul should deal with
thought in general as it does in the mathematical mode of conception.
As Descartes proceeded from his state of doubt to his conclusion,
I think, therefore I am, and the statements connected with
it, he felt secure in these operations because they seemed to him to
possess the clarity that is inherent in mathematics. The same
general mental conviction leads Spinoza to elaborate a world picture
for himself in which everything is unfolding its effect with strict
necessity like the laws of mathematics. The one divine substance,
which permeates all beings of the world with the determination of
mathematical law, admits the human ego only if it surrenders itself
completely to this substance, if it allows its self-consciousness to
be absorbed by the world consciousness of the divine substance. This
mathematical disposition of mind, which is caused by a longing of the
ego for the security it needs, leads this ego
to a world picture in which, through its striving for security, it has
lost itself, its self-dependent, firm stand on a spiritual
world ground, its freedom and its hope for an eternal self-dependent
existence.
Leibniz's thoughts tended in the opposite direction. The human soul
is, for him, the self dependent monad, strictly closed off in itself.
But this monad experiences only what it contains within itself;
the world order, which presents itself from without, as it
were, is only a delusion. Behind it lies the true world, which
consists only of monads, the order of which is the predetermined
(pre-established) harmony that does not show itself to the
outer observation. This world conception leaves its self-dependence to
the human soul, the self-dependent existence in the universe, its
freedom and hope for an eternal significance in the world's evolution.
If, however, it means to remain consistent with its basic principle,
it cannot avoid maintaining that everything known by the soul is
only the soul itself, that it is incapable of going outside the
self-conscious ego and that the universe cannot become revealed to the
soul in its truth from without.
For Descartes and for Leibniz, the convictions they had acquired in
their religious education were still effective enough that they
adopted them in their philosophical world pictures, thereby following
motivations that were not really derived from the basic principles of
their world pictures. Into Descartes's world picture there crept the
conception of a spiritual world that he had obtained through religious
channels. It unconsciously permeated the rigid mathematical necessity
of his world order and thus he did not feel that his world picture
tended to extinguish his ego. In Leibniz, religious
impulses exerted their influence in a similar way, and it is for this
reason that it escaped him that his world picture provided for no
possibility to find anything except the content of the soul itself.
Leibniz believed, nevertheless, that he could assume the existence of
the spiritual world outside the ego. Spinoza, through a
certain courageous trait of his personality, actually drew the
consequences of his world picture. To obtain the security for this
world picture on which his self-consciousness insisted, he renounced
the self-dependence of this self-consciousness and found his supreme
happiness in feeling himself as a part of the one divine substance.
With regard to Kant we must raise the question of how he was compelled
to feel with respect to the currents of world conception, which had
produced its prominent representatives in Descartes, Spinoza and
Leibniz. For all soul impulses that had been at work in these three
were also active in him, and in his soul these impulses effected each
other and caused the riddles of world and mankind with which Kant
found himself confronted. A glance at the life of the spirit in the
Age of Kant informs us of the general trend of Kant's feeling with
respect to these riddles. Significantly, Lessing's (1729
1781) attitude toward the questions of world conception is symptomatic
of this intellectual life. Lessing sums up his credo in the words,
The transformation of revealed truths into truths of reason is
absolutely necessary if the human race is to derive any help from
them. The eighteenth century has been called the century of the
Enlightenment. The representative spirits of Germany understood
enlightenment in the sense of Lessing's remark. Kant declared the
enlightenment to be man's departure from his self-caused bondage
of mind, and as its motto he chose the words, Have courage
to use your own mind. Even thinkers as prominent as
Lessing, however, at first had succeeded in no more than transforming
rationally traditional doctrines of belief derived from the state of
the self-caused bondage of mind. They did not penetrate to
a pure rational view as Spinoza did. It was inevitable that Spinoza's
doctrine, when it became known in Germany, should make a deep
impression on such spirits.
Spinoza really had undertaken the task of using his own mind, but in
the course of this process he had arrived at results that were
entirely different from those of the German philosophers of the
enlightenment. His influence had to be so much the more significant
since the lines of his reasoning, constructed according to
mathematical methods, carried a much greater convincing power than the
current of Leibniz's philosophy, which effected the spirits of that
age in the form developed by Wolff. From Goethe's
autobiography, Poetry and Truth, we receive an idea of how this
school of thought impressed deeper spirits as it reached them through
the channels of Wolff's conceptions. Goethe tells of the impressions
the lectures of Professor Winckler in Leipzig, given in the spirit of
Wolff, had made on him.
At the beginning, I attended my classes industriously and faithfully,
but the philosophy offered in no way succeeded in enlightening me. It
seemed strange to me that in logic I was to tear apart, isolate and
destroy, as it were, the intellectual operations I had been handling
with the greatest ease since the days of my childhood, in order to
gain an insight into their correct use. I thought I knew just about as
much as the lecturer about the nature of things, the world and God,
and on more than one occasion it seemed to me that there was a
considerable hitch in the matter.
About his occupation with Spinoza's writings, however, the poet tells
us, I surrendered to this reading and, inspecting myself, I
believed never to have seen the world so distinctly.
There were, however, only a few people who could surrender to
Spinoza's mode of thought as frankly as Goethe. Most readers were led
into deep convicts of world conception by this philosophy. Goethe's
friend, F. H. Jacobi, is typical of them. He believed that he had to
admit that reason, left to its own resources, would not lead to the
doctrines of belief, but to the view at which Spinoza had arrived
that the world is ruled by eternal, necessary laws. Thus, Jacobi found
himself confronted with an important decision: Either to trust his
reason and abandon the doctrines of his creed or to deny reason the
possibility to lead to the highest insights in order to be able to
retain his belief. He chose the latter. He maintained that man
possessed a direct certainty in his innermost soul, a secure belief
by virtue of which he was capable of feeling the truth of the
conception of a personal God, of the freedom of will and of
immortality, so that these convictions were entirely independent of
the insights of reason that were leaning on logical conclusions, and
had no reference to these things but only to the external things of
nature. In this way, Jacobi deposed the knowledge of reason to
make room for a belief that satisfied the needs of the heart.
Goethe who was not at all pleased by this dethronement of reason,
wrote to his friend, God has punished you with metaphysics and
placed a thorn in your flesh; he has blessed me with physics. I cling
to the atheist's (Spinoza's) worship of God and leave everything to
you that you call, and may continue to call, religion. Your trust
rests in belief in God; mine in seeing. The
philosophy of the enlightenment ended by confronting the spirits with
the alternative, either to supplant the revealed truths by truths of
reason in the sense of Spinoza, or to declare war on the knowledge of
reason itself.
Kant also found himself confronted with this choice. The attitude he
took and how he made his decision is apparent from the clear account
in the preface to the second edition of his Critique of Pure
Reason.
Now let us assume that morality necessarily presupposes freedom (in
its strictest sense) as a property of our will, pleading practical
principles inherent in our reason that would be positively impossible
without the presupposition of freedom. Speculative reason, however,
having proven that this is not even thinkable, the former assumption,
made on behalf of morality, would have to give way to the latter,
whose opposite contains an obvious self-contradiction and therefore
freedom, and with it morality, would have to give way to the
mechanism of nature. But since, as the case lies, for the
possibility of morality nothing more is required than that the idea of
freedom be not contradictory in itself, and may at least be considered
as thinkable without the future necessity of being understood,
such that granting the freedom of a given action would not place
any obstacle into the attempt of considering the same action (see in
other relation) as a mechanism of nature. In this way, the doctrine of
morality maintains its place . . . which could, however, not have
happened if our critical philosophy had not previously enlightened us
about our inevitable ignorance with respect to things in
themselves, restricting all that we can know theoretically to mere
phenomena. In the same way, the positive value of the critical
principles of pure reason can be brought to light with regard to the
concepts of God and of the simple nature of our soul, which I
do, however, leave undiscussed here for the sake of brevity. I cannot
even assume God, freedom and immortality for the use of
practical reason if I do not at the same time deprive
speculative reason of its pretensions to excessive insight. . . .
I, therefore, had to suspend knowledge in order to make room for
belief. . . .
We see here how Kant stands on a similar ground as Jacobi in regard to
knowledge and belief.
The way in which Kant had arrived at his results had led through the
thought world of Hume. In Hume he had found the view that the things
and events of the world in no way reveal connections of thought to the
human soul, that the human mind imagined such connections only through
habit while it is perceiving the things and events of the world
simultaneously in space and successively in time. Kant was impressed
by Hume's opinion according to which the human mind does not receive
from the world what appears to it as knowledge. For Kant, the thought
emerged as a possibility: What is knowledge for the human mind does
not come from the reality of the world.
Through Hume's arguments, Kant was, according to his own confession,
awakened out of the slumber into which he had fallen in following
Wolff's train of ideas. How can reason produce judgments about God,
freedom and immortality if its statement about the simplest events
rests on such insecure foundation? The attack that Kant now had to
undertake against the knowledge of reason was much more far-reaching
than that of Jacobi. He had at least left to knowledge the possibility
of comprehending nature in its necessary connection. Now Kant had
produced an important accomplishment in the field of natural science
with his General Natural History and Theory of the Heavens,
which had appeared in 1755. He was satisfied to have shown that
our whole planetary system could be thought to have developed out of a
ball of gas, rotating around its axis. Through strictly necessary
mathematically measurable physical forces, he thought the sun and
planets to have consolidated, and to have assumed the motions in which
they proceed according to the teachings of Copernicus and Kepler. Kant
thus believed he had proven, through a great discovery of his own, the
fruitfulness of Spinoza's mode of thought, according to which
everything happens with strict, mathematical necessity. He was so
convinced of this fruitfulness that in the above-mentioned work he
went so far as to exclaim, Give me matter, and I will build you
a universe! The absolute certainty of all mathematical truths
was so firmly established for him that he maintains in his Basic
Principles of Natural Science that a science in the proper
sense of the word is only one in which the application of
mathematics is possible. If Hume were right, it would be out of the
question to assume such a certainty for the knowledge of mathematical
natural science, for, in that case, this knowledge would consist of
nothing but thought habits that man had developed because he had seen
the course of the world along certain lines. But there would not be
the slightest guaranty that these thought habits had anything to do
with the law-ordered connection of the things of the world. From his
presupposition Hume draws the conclusion:
The scenes of the universe are continually shifting, and one object
follows another in an uninterrupted succession, but the power of force
which actuates the whole machine is entirely concealed from us and
never discovers itself in any of the sensible qualities of body. .
. . . (Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Sec. VII, part 1.)
If we then place the world conception of Spinoza into the light of
Hume's view, we must say, In accordance with the perceived
course of the processes of the world, man has formed the habit of
thinking these processes in a necessary, law-ordered connection, but
he is not entitled to maintain that this connection is
anything but a mere thought habit. Now if this were the case,
then it would be a mere deception of the human reason to imagine that
it could, through itself, gain any insight into the nature of the
world, and Hume could not be contradicted when he says about every
world conception that is gained out of pure reason, Throw it
into the fire, for it is nothing but deception and illusion.
Kant could not possibly adopt this conclusion of Hume as his own. For
him, the certainty of the knowledge of mathematical natural science
was irrevocably established. He would not allow this certainty to be
touched but was unable to deny that Hume was justified in saying that
we gain all knowledge about real things only by observing them and by
forming for ourselves thoughts about their connection that are based
on this observation. If a law-ordered connection is inherent in
things, then we must also extract this connection out of them, but
what we really derive from the things is such that we know no more
about it than that it has been so up to the present time. We do not
know, however, whether such a connection is really so linked up with
the nature of things that it cannot change in any moment. If we form
for ourselves today a world conception based on our observations,
events can happen tomorrow that compel us to form an entirely
different one. If we received all our knowledge from things, there
would be no certainty. Mathematics and natural sciences are a proof of
this. That the world does not give its knowledge to the human
mind was a view Kant was ready to adopt from Hume. That this knowledge
does not contain certainty and truth, however, is a conclusion he was
not willing to draw. Thus, Kant was confronted with the question that
disturbed him deeply: How is it possible that man is in possession of
true and certain knowledge and that he is, nevertheless, incapable of
knowing anything of the reality of the world in itself?
Kant found an answer that saved the truth and certainty of human
knowledge by sacrificing human insight into the grounds of the world.
Our reason could never claim certainty about anything in a world lying
spread out around us so that we would be affected by it through
observation only. Therefore, our world can only be one that is
constructed by ourselves: A world that lies within the limits of our
minds. What is going on outside myself as a stone falls and causes a
hole in the ground, I do not know. The law of this entire process is
enacted within me, and it can proceed within me only in accordance
with demands of my own mental organization. The nature of my mind
requires that every effect should have a cause and that two times two
is four. It is in accordance with this nature that the mind constructs
a world for itself. No matter how the world outside ourselves might be
constructed, today's world may not coincide in even a single trait
with that of yesterday. This can never concern us for our mind
produces its own world according to its own laws. As long as the human
mind remains unchanged, it will proceed in the same way in the
construction of the world. Mathematics and natural science do not
contain the laws of the external world but those of our mental
organization. It is, therefore, only necessary to investigate this
organization if we want to know what is unconditionally true.
Reason does not derive its laws from nature but
prescribes them to nature. Kant sums up his conviction in
this sentence, but the mind does not produce its inner world without
an impetus or impression from without. When I perceive the color red,
the perception, red, is, to be sure, a state, a process
within me, but it is necessary for me to have an occasion to perceive
red. There are, therefore, things in
themselves, but we know nothing about them but the fact that
they exist. Everything we observe belongs to the appearances within
us. Therefore, in order to save the certainty of the mathematical and
natural scientific truths, Kant has taken the whole world of
observation in the human mind. In doing so, however, he has raised
insurmountable barriers to the faculty of knowledge, for everything
that we can know refers merely to processes within ourselves, to
appearances or phenomena, not to things in themselves, as Kant
expresses it. But the objects of the highest questions of reason
God, Freedom and Immortality can never become phenomena. We see the
appearances within ourselves; whether or not these have their origin
in a divine being we cannot know. We can observe our own psychic
conditions, but these are also only phenomena. Whether or not there is
a free immortal soul behind them remains concealed to our knowledge.
About the things in themselves, our knowledge cannot
produce any statement. It cannot determine whether the ideas
concerning these things in themselves are true or false.
If they are announced to us from another direction, there is no
objection to assume their existence, but a knowledge concerning
them is impossible for us. There is only one access to these highest
truths. This access is given in the voice of duty, which speaks within
us emphatically and distinctly, You are morally obliged
to do this and that. This Categorical Imperative
imposes on us an obligation we are incapable of avoiding. But how
could we comply with this obligation if we were not in the possession
of a free will? We are, to be sure, incapable of knowledge
concerning this quality of our soul, but we must believe
that it is free in order to be capable of following its
inner voice of duty. Concerning this freedom, we have, therefore, no
certainty of knowledge as we possess it with respect to the objects of
mathematics and natural science, but we have moral certainty
for it instead. The observance of the categorical imperative leads
to virtue. It is only through virtue that man can arrive at his
destination. He becomes worthy of happiness. Without this possibility
his virtue would be void of meaning and significance. In order that
virtue may result from happiness, it is mandatory that a being exists
who secures this happiness as an effect of virtue. This can only be an
intelligent being, determining the highest value of things: God.
Through the existence of virtue, its effect is guaranteed, and through
this guarantee, in turn, the existence of God. Because man is a
sensual being and cannot obtain perfect happiness in this imperfect
world, his existence must transcend this sensual existence; that is to
say, the soul must be immortal. The very thing about which we are
denied possible knowledge is, therefore, magically produced by
Kant out of the moral belief in the voice of duty. It was
respect for the feeling of duty that restored a real world for Kant
when, under the influence of Hume, the observable world withered away
into a mere inner world. This respect for duty is beautifully
expressed in his Critique of Practical Reason:
Duty! Thou sublime, great name that containest nothing pleasurable to
bid for our favor, but demandest submission, . . . proclaiming a law
in the presence of which all inclinations are silenced although they
may secretly offer resistance. . . .
That the highest truths are not truths of knowledge but moral truths
is what Kant considered as his discovery. Man has to renounce all
insight into a supersensible world, but from his moral nature springs
a compensation for this knowledge. No wonder Kant sees the highest
demand on man in the unconditional surrender to duty. If it were not
for duty to open a vista for him beyond the sensual world, man would
be enclosed for his whole life in the world of the senses. No matter,
therefore, what the sensual world demands; it has to give way before
the peremptory claims of duty, and the sensual world cannot, out of
its own initiative, agree with duty. Its own inclination is directed
toward the agreeable, toward pleasure. These aims have to be opposed
by duty in order to enable man to reach his destination. What man does
for his pleasure is not virtuous; virtue is only what he does in
selfless devotion to duty. Submit your desires to duty; this is the
rigorous task that is taught by Kant's moral philosophy. Do not allow
your will to be directed toward what satisfies you in your egotism,
but so act that the principles of your action can become those of all
men. In surrendering to the moral law, man attains his perfection. The
belief that this moral law has its being above all other events of the
world and is made real within the world by a divine being is, in
Kant's opinion, true religion. It springs from the moral life. Man is
to be good, not because of his belief in a God whose will demands the
good; he is to be good only because of his feeling for duty. He is to
believe in God, however, because duty without God would be
meaningless. This is religion within the Limits of Mere Reason.
It is thus that Kant entitles his book on religious world
conception.
The course that the development of the natural sciences took since
they began to flourish has produced in many people the feeling that
every element that does not carry the character of strict necessity
should be eliminated from our thought picture of nature. Kant had this
feeling also. In his Natural History of the Heavens, he had
even outlined such a picture for a certain realm of nature that was in
accordance with this feeling. In a thought picture of this kind, there
is no place for the conception of the self-conscious ego that the man
of the eighteenth century felt necessary. The Platonic and the
Aristotelian thought could be considered as the revelation of nature
in the form in which that idea was accepted in the earlier age, and as
that of the human soul as well. In thought life, nature and the soul
met. From the picture of nature as it seems to be demanded by modern
science, nothing leads to the conception of the self-conscious soul.
Kant had the feeling that the conception of nature offered nothing to
him on which he could base the certainty of self-consciousness. This
certainty had to be created for the modern age had presented the
self-conscious ego as a fact. The possibility had to be created to
acknowledge this fact, but everything that can be recognized as
knowledge by our understanding is devoured by the conception of
nature. Thus, Kant feels himself compelled to provide for the
self-conscious ego as well as for the spiritual world connected with
it, something that is not knowledge but nevertheless supplies
certainty.
Kant established selfless devotion to the voice of the spirit as the
foundation of moral life. In the realm of virtuous action, such a
devotion is not compatible with a surrender to the sensual world.
There is, however, a field in which the sensual is elevated in such a
way that it appears as the immediate expression of the spirit. That is
the field of beauty and art. In our ordinary life we want the sensual
because it excites our desire, our self-seeking interest. We desire
what gives us pleasure, but it is also possible to take a selfless
interest in an object. We can look at it in admiration, filled by a
heavenly delight and this delight can be quite independent of the
possession of the thing. Whether or not I should like to own a
beautiful house that I pass has nothing to do with the
disinterested pleasure that I may take in its beauty. If I
eliminate all desire from my feeling, there may still be found as a
remaining element a pleasure that is clearly and exclusively linked to
the beautiful work of art. A pleasure of this kind is an
esthetic pleasure. The beautiful is to be distinguished
from the agreeable and the good. The agreeable excites my interest
because it arouses my desire; the good interests me because it is to
be made real by me. In confronting the beautiful I have no such
interest that is connected with my person. What is it then, by means
of which my selfless delight is attracted? I can be pleased by a thing
only when its purpose is fulfilled, when it is so organized that it
serves an end. Fitness to purpose pleases; incongruity displeases, but
as I have no interest in the reality of the beautiful thing, as the
mere sight of it satisfies me, it is also not necessary that the
beautiful object really serves a purpose. The purpose is of no
importance to me; what I demand is only the appropriateness. For this
reason, Kant calls an object beautiful in which we
perceive fitness to purpose without thinking at the same time of a
definite purpose.
What Kant gives in this exposition is not merely an explanation but
also a justification of art. This is best seen if one remembers Kant's
feeling in regard to his world conception. He expresses his feeling in
profound, beautiful words:
Two things fill the heart with ever new and always increasing
admiration and awe: The starred heaven above me and the moral law
within me. At first, the sight of an innumerable world quantity
annihilates, as it were, my importance as a living creature, which
must give back to the planet that is a mere dot in the universe the
matter out of which it became what it is, after having been for a
short while (one does not know how) provided with the energy of life.
On second consideration, however, this spectacle infinitely raises my
value as an intelligent being, through my (conscious and free)
personality in which the moral law reveals to me a life that is
independent of the whole world of the senses, at least insofar as this
can be concluded from the purpose-directed destination of my
existence, which is not hemmed in by the conditions and limitations of
this life but extends into the infinite.
The artist now transplants this purpose-directed destination, which,
in reality, rules in the realm of the moral world, into the world of
the senses. Thus, the world of art stands between the realm of the
world of observation that is dominated by the eternal stern laws of
necessity, which the human mind itself has previously laid into this
world, and the realm of free morality in which commands of duty, as
the result of a wise, divine world-order, set out direction and aim.
Between both realms the artist enters with his works. Out of the realm
of the real he takes his material, but he reshapes this material at
the same time in such a fashion that it becomes the bearer of a
purpose-directed harmony as it is found in the realm of freedom. That
is to say, the human spirit feels dissatisfied both with the realms of
external reality, which Kant has in mind when he speaks of the starred
heaven and the innumerable things of the world, and also with the
realm of moral law. Man, therefore, creates a beautiful realm of
semblance, which combines the rigid necessity of nature
with the element of a free purpose. The beautiful now is not only
found in human works of art, but also in nature. There is
nature-beauty as well as art-beauty. This beauty of nature is there
without man's activity. It seems, therefore, as if there were
observable in the world of reality, not merely the rigid law-ordered
necessity, but a free wisdom-revealing activity as well. The
phenomenon of the beautiful, nevertheless, does not force us to accept
a conception of this kind, for what it offers is the form of a
purpose-directed activity without implying also the thought of a real
purpose. Furthermore, there is not only the phenomenon of integrated
beauty but also that of integrated ugliness. It is, therefore,
possible to assume that in the multitude of natural events, which are
interconnected according to necessary laws, some happen to occur
accidentally, as it were in which the human mind observes an analogy
with man's own works of art. As it is not necessary to assume a real
purpose, this element of free purpose, which appears as it were by
accident, is quite sufficient for the esthetic contemplation of
nature.
The situation is different when we meet the entities in nature to
which the purpose concept is not merely to be attributed as accidental
but that carry this purpose really within themselves. There are also
entities of this kind according to Kant's opinion. They are the
organic beings. The necessary law-determined connections are
insufficient to explain them; these, in Spinoza's world conception are
considered not only necessary but sufficient, and by Kant are
considered as those of the human mind itself. For an organism is
a product of nature in which everything is, at the same time,
purpose, just as it is cause and also effect. An organism,
therefore, cannot be explained merely through rigid laws that operate
with necessity, as is the case with inorganic nature. It is for this
reason that, although Kant himself had, in his General Natural
History and Theory of the Heavens, undertaken the attempt to
discuss the constitution and the mechanical origin of the entire
world structure according to Newtonian principles, he is of the
opinion that a similar attempt, applied to the world of organic
beings, would necessarily fail. In his Critique of Judgment, he
advances the following statement:
It is, namely, absolutely certain that in following merely mechanical
principles of nature we cannot even become sufficiently acquainted
with organisms and their inner possibility, much less explain them.
This is so certain that one can boldly say that it would be absurd for
man to set out on any such attempt or to hope that at some future time
a Newton could arise who would explain as much as the production of a
blade of grass according to natural laws into which no purpose had
brought order and direction. Such a knowledge must, on the contrary,
be altogether denied to man.
Kant's view that it is the human mind itself that first projects the
laws into nature that it then finds in it, is also irreconcilable with
another opinion concerning a purpose-directed entity, for a purpose
points to its originator through whom it was laid into such an entity,
that is, to the rational originator of the world. If the human mind
could explain a teleological being in the same way as an entity that
is merely constituted according to natural necessity, it would also
have to be capable of projecting laws of purpose out of itself into
the things. Not merely would the human mind have to provide laws for
the things that would be valid with regard to them insofar as they are
appearances of his inner world, but it would have to be capable of
prescribing their own destination to the things that are completely
independent of the mind. The human mind would, therefore, have to be
not merely a cognitive, but a creative, spirit; its reason would, like
that of God, have to create the things.
Whoever calls to mind the structure of the Kantian world conception as
it has been outlined here will understand its strong effect on Kant's
contemporaries and also on the time after him, for he leaves intact
all of the conceptions that had formed and impressed themselves on the
human mind in the course of the development of western culture. This
world conception leaves God, freedom and immortality, to the religious
spirit. It satisfies the need for knowledge in delineating a territory
for it inside the limits of which it recognizes unconditionally
certain truths. It even allows for the opinion that the human reason
is justified to employ, not merely the eternal rigorous natural laws
for the explanation of living beings, but the purpose concept that
suggests a designed order in the world.
But at what price did Kant obtain all this! He transferred all of
nature into the human mind and transformed its laws into laws of this
mind. He ejected the higher world order entirely from nature and
placed this order on a purely moral foundation. He drew a sharp line
of demarcation between the realm of the inorganic and that of the
organic, explaining the former according to mechanical laws of natural
necessity and the latter according to teleological ideas. Finally, he
tore the realm of beauty and art completely out of its connection with
the rest of reality, for the teleological form that is to be observed
in the beautiful has nothing to do with real purposes. How a
beautiful object comes into the world is of no importance; it is
sufficient that it stimulates in us the conception of the purposeful
and thereby produces our delight.
Kant not only presents the view that man's knowledge is possible so
far as the law-structure of this knowledge has its origin in the
self-conscious soul, and the certainty concerning this soul comes out
of a source that is different from the one out of which our knowledge
of nature springs. He also points out that our human knowledge has to
resign before nature, where it meets the living organism in which
thought itself seems to reign in nature. In taking this position, Kant
confesses by implication that he cannot imagine thoughts that are
conceived as active in the entities of nature themselves. The
recognition of such thoughts presupposes that the human soul not
merely thinks, but in thinking shares the life of nature in its
inner experience. If somebody discovered that thoughts are capable not
merely of being received as perceptions, as is the case with the
Platonic and Aristotelian ideas, but that it is possible to
experience thoughts by penetrating into the entities of nature,
then this would mean that again a new element had been found that
could enter the picture of nature as well as the conception of the
self-conscious ego. The self-conscious ego by itself does not find a
place in the nature picture of modern times. If the self-conscious
ego, in filling itself with thought, is not merely aware that it forms
this thought, but recognizes in thought a life of which it can
know, This life can realize itself also outside myself,
then this self-conscious ego can arrive at the insight, I hold
within myself something that can also be found without. The
evolution of modern world conception thus urges man on to the step: To
find the thought in the self-conscious ego that is felt to be alive.
This step Kant did not take; Goethe did.
In all essential points, Goethe arrived at the opposite to Kant's
conception of the world. Approximately at the same time that Kant
published his Critique of Pure Reason, Goethe laid down his
creed in his prose hymn, Nature, in which he placed man
completely into nature and in which he presented nature as bearing
absolute sway, independent of man: Her own and man's lawgiver as well.
Kant drew all nature into the human mind. Goethe considered everything
as belonging to this nature; he fitted the human spirit into the
natural world order:
Nature! We are surrounded and enveloped by her, incapable of leaving
her domain, incapable of penetrating deeper into her. She draws us
into the rounds of her dance, neither asking nor warning, and whirls
away with us until we fall exhausted from her arms. . . . A11 men are
in her and she is in them. . . . Even the most unnatural is Nature;
even the clumsiest pedantry has something of her genius. . . .We obey
her laws even when we resist them; we are working with her even
when we mean to work against her. . . . Nature is everything. .
. . She rewards and punishes, delights and tortures herself. . . . She
has placed me into life, she will also lead me out of it. I trust
myself into her care. She may hold sway over me. She will not hate her
work. It was not I who spoke of her. Nay, it was Nature who spoke it
all, true and false. Nature is the blame for all things; hers is the
merit.
This is the polar opposite to Kant's world conception. According to
Kant, nature is entirely in the human spirit; according to Goethe, the
human spirit is entirely in nature because nature itself is spirit. It
is, therefore, easily understandable when Goethe tells us in his
essay, Influence of Modern Philosophy:
Kant's Critique of Pure Reason was completely outside my world.
I attended many conversations concerning this book, and with some
attention I could observe that the old main question of how much our
own self contributed to our spiritual existence, and how much the
outside world did, was renewed. I never separated them, and when I
philosophized in my own way about objects, I did so with an
unconscious naiveté, really believing that I saw my opinion before my
very eyes.
We need not waver in this estimate of Goethe's attitude toward Kant,
in spite of the fact that Goethe uttered many a favorable judgment
about the philosopher of Koenigsberg. This opposition between Kant and
himself would only then have become quite clear to him if he had
engaged himself in a thorough study of Kant, but this he did not do.
In the above-mentioned essay he says, It was the introductory
passages that I liked; into the labyrinth itself, however, I could not
venture to go; I was kept from it now by my poetic imagination, now by
my common sense, and nowhere did I feel myself furthered.
Goethe has, nevertheless, expressed his opposition distinctly on one
occasion in a passage that has been published only from the papers of
the residuary estate in the Weimar Goethe Edition (Weimarische
Ausgabe, 2; Abteilung, Band XI, page 377). The fundamental error of
Kant was, as here expressed by Goethe, that he considers the
subjective faculty of knowledge as an object and discriminates the
point where the subjective and the objective meet with great
penetration but not quite correctly. Goethe just happens
to be convinced that it is not only the spirit as such that speaks in
the subjective human faculty of cognition, but that it is the spirit
of nature that has created for itself an organ in man through which it
reveals its secrets. It is not man at all who speaks about nature, but
it is nature who speaks in man about itself. This is Goethe's
conviction. Thus, he could say that whenever the controversy
concerning Kant's world view was brought up, I liked to take the
side that gave most honor to man, and I completely agreed with all
those friends who maintained with Kant that, although all our
knowledge begins with experience, it nevertheless does not originate
from experience. For Goethe believed that the eternal laws
according to which nature proceeds are revealed in the human spirit,
but for this reason, they were not merely the subjective laws of the
spirit for him, but the objective laws of the order of nature itself.
It is for this reason also that Goethe could not agree when Schiller,
under the influence of Kant, erected a forbidding wall of separation
between the realms of natural necessity and of freedom. Goethe
expressed himself on this point in his essay, First Acquaintance
with Schiller:
Schiller and some friends had absorbed the Kantian philosophy, which
elevates the subject to such height while apparently narrowing it. It
developed the extraordinary traits that nature had laid into his
character and he, in his highest feeling of freedom and self
determination, tended to be ungrateful to the great mother who had
certainly not treated him stingily. Instead of considering nature as
self-supporting, alive and productively spreading order and law from
the lowest to the highest point, Schiller took notice of it only in
the shape of a few empirical human natural inclinations.
In his essay, Influence of Modern Philosophy, Goethe points to
his difference with Schiller in these words. He preached the
gospel of freedom; I was unwilling to see the rights of nature
infringed upon. There was, indeed, an element of Kant's mode of
conception in Schiller, but so far as Goethe is concerned, we are
right in accepting what he himself said with regard to some
conversations he had with the followers of Kant. They heard what
I had to say but they could not answer me or further me in any way.
More than once it happened that one or the other of them admitted to
me with a surprised smile that my conception was, to be sure,
analogous to that of Kant, but in a curious fashion indeed.
Goethe did not consider art and beauty as a realm that was torn out of
the interconnection of reality, but as a higher stage of nature's
order. At the sight of artistic creations that especially interested
him during his Italian journey he wrote, Like the highest works
of nature, the lofty works of art have been produced by men according
to true and natural laws. Everything that is arbitrary
and merely imagined fades away before them. Here is necessity; here
is God. When the artist proceeds as the Greeks did, namely,
according to the laws that Nature herself follows, then
his works contain the same godly element that is to be found in nature
itself. For Goethe, art is a manifestation of secret natural
laws. What the artist creates are works of nature on a higher
level of perfection. Art is the continuation and human completion of
nature, for as man finds himself placed at the highest point of
nature, he again considers himself a whole nature and as such has
again to produce a peak in himself. For this purpose he raises his own
existence by penetrating himself with all perfections and virtues,
produces choice, order, harmony and meaning, and finally lifts himself
as far as to the production of the work of art. Everything is
nature, from the inorganic stone to the highest of man's works of art,
and everything in this nature is ruled by the same eternal,
necessary and thereby divine laws, such that the godhead
itself could not change anything about it (Poetry and Truth,
Book XVI).
When, in 1811, Goethe read Jacobi's book, On Things Divine, it
made him uneasy.
How could the book of a so warmly beloved friend, in which I was to
see the thesis developed that nature conceals God, be welcome to me!
My mode of world conception purely felt, deeply-seated, inborn and
practised daily as it was had taught me inviolably to see God in
Nature, Nature in God, and this to such an extent that this world
view formed the basis of my entire existence. Under these
circumstances, was not such a strange, one-sided and narrow-minded
thesis to estrange me in spirit from this most noble man for whose
heart I felt love and veneration? I did not, however, allow my painful
vexation to linger with me but took refuge in my old asylum, finding
my daily entertainment for several weeks in Spinoza's Ethics,
and as my inner education had progressed in the meantime, to my
astonishment I became aware of many things that revealed themselves to
me in a new and different light and affected me with a peculiar
freshness.
The realm of necessity in Spinoza's sense is a realm of inner
necessity for Kant. For Goethe, it is the universe itself, and man
with all his thinking, feeling, willing and actions is a link in this
chain of necessities. In this realm there is only one order of
law, of which the natural and the moral represent only the two sides
of its essence. The sun sheds its light over those good and
evil, and to the guilty as to the best, the moon and the stars shine
brightly. Out of one root, out of the eternal springs of nature,
Goethe has everything pour forth: The inorganic and the organic
beings, and man with all the fruits of his spirit, his knowledge, his
moral order and his art.
What God would just push the world from without,
And let it run in circles on his finger?
Him it behooves to move it in its core,
Be close to nature, hug her to her breast
So that what lives and weaves in him and is,
Will never lack his power and his spirit.
In these words Goethe summed up his credo. Against Hailer, who had
written the lines, Into nature's sacred center, no created
spirits enter, Goethe turns with his sharpest words:
Into nature's sacred center,
O, Philistine past compare
No created spirits enter
Wished you never would remind
Me and all those of my kind
Of this shallow verbal banter.
We think we are everywhere
With every step in Nature's care.
Happy he to whom she just
Shows her dry external crust.
I hear that repeated these sixty years
Curse under my breath so no one hears,
And to myself I a thousand times tell:
Nature has neither core nor shell,
Everything yields she gladly and well.
Nature is at our beck and call
Nature herself is one and all.
Better search yourself once more
Whether you be crust or core.
In following this world conception Goethe could also not recognize the
difference between inorganic and organic nature, which Kant had
ascertained in his Critique of Judgment. Goethe tended to
explain living organisms according to the laws by which lifeless
nature is explained. Concerning the various species in the plant
world, the leading botanist of that time, Linné, states that there
were as many species as there have been created fundamentally
different forms. A botanist who holds such an opinion can only
attempt to study the quality of the individual forms and to
differentiate them carefully from one another. Goethe could not
consent to such a view of nature. What Linnaeus wanted with
might and main to separate, I felt in the very roots of my being as
striving into union. Goethe searched for an entity that was
common to all species of plants. On his Italian journey this general
archetype in all plant forms becomes clearer to him step by step.
The many plants I have heretofore been used to see only in buckets and
pots, here grow merrily and vigorously under the open sky, and while
they thus fulfill their destination, they become clearer to us. At the
sight of such a variety of new and renewed forms, my curious and
favorite idea again occurred to me. Could I not discover in this crowd
the archetypal plant (Urpflanze)? There really must be such a
thing. How should I otherwise know that this or that given form is a
plant if they had not all been designed after one model?
On another occasion Goethe expresses himself concerning this
archetypal plant by saying, It is going to become the strangest
creature of the world for which nature herself shall envy me. With
this model and the corresponding key, one is then capable of inventing
plants to infinity, but they must be consistent in themselves, that is
to say, plants that, even if they do not exist, at least could
exist, and that are not merely shadows and schemes of a
picturesque or poetic imagination, but have an inner truth and
necessity. As Kant, in his Natural History and Theory of the
Heavens, exclaims, Give me matter and I will build you a
world out of it, because he has gained insight into the
law-determined interconnection of this world, so Goethe pronounces
here that with the aid of the archetypal plant one could invent
plants indefinitely that would be capable of existence because one
would be in possession of the law of their origin and their
development. What Kant was ready to acknowledge only for inorganic
nature, that is, that its phenomena can be understood according to
necessary laws, Goethe extends also to the world of organisms. In the
letter in which he tells Herder about his discovery of the archetypal
plant, he adds, The same law will be applicable to all other
living beings, and Goethe applies it, indeed. In 1795, his
persevering studies of the animal world led him to feel free to
maintain boldly that all perfect organic beings, among which we see
fishes, amphibia, birds, mammals, and at the top of the ladder, man,
were formed after one model, which in its constant parts only
varies in one or another direction and still develops and transforms
daily through propagation.
In his conception of nature as well, therefore, Goethe stands in full
opposition to Kant. Kant had called it a risky adventure of
reason, should reason attempt to explain the living with regard
to its origin. He considered the human faculty of cognition as unfit
for such an explanation.
It is of infinite importance for reason not to eliminate the mechanism
of nature in its productions, and not to pass by this idea in their
explanation because without it no insight into the nature of things
can be obtained. Even if it is admitted to us that the highest
architect has created the forms of nature as they have been forever,
or predetermined those that form according to the same model in the
course of their development, our knowledge of nature would thereby
nevertheless not be furthered in the slightest degree because we do
not know at all the mode of action and the ideas of this being
that are to contain the principles of the possibility of the
natural beings and therefore cannot explain nature by means of them
from above.
Against Kantian arguments of this kind, Goethe answers:
If, in the moral realm through faith in God, virtue and immortality,
we are to lift ourselves into the higher region and to approach the
first Being, we should be in the same situation in the intellectual
field, so that we, through the contemplation of an ever creative
nature, should make ourselves worthy of a spiritual participation in
its productions. As I had at first unconsciously and, following an
inner instinct, insisted upon and relentlessly striven toward the
archetypal, the typical, as I had even succeeded in constructing an
appropriate picture, there was now nothing to keep me from
courageously risking the adventure of reason, as the old man
from Koenigsberg himself calls it.
In his archetypal plant, Goethe had seized upon an idea with
which one can . . . invent plants to infinity, but they must be
consistent, that is to say, even if they do not exist, nevertheless
they could exist and are not merely shadows and schemes of a
picturesque or poetic imagination but have an inner truth and
necessity. Thus, Goethe shows that he is about to find not
merely the perceptible idea, the idea that is thought, in the
self-conscious ego, but the living idea. The self-conscious ego
experiences a realm in itself that manifests itself as both
self-contained and at the same time appertaining to the external
world, because the forms of the latter prove to be moulded after the
models of the creative powers. With this step the self-conscious ego
can appear as a real being. Goethe has developed a conception through
which the self-conscious ego can feel itself enlivened because it
feels itself in union with the creative entities of nature. The
world conception of modern times attempted to master the riddle of the
self-conscious ego; Goethe plants the living idea into this
ego, and with this force of life pulsating in it, it proves to be a
life-saturated reality. The Greek idea is akin to the picture; it is
contemplated like a picture. The idea of modern times must be akin to
life, to the living being; it is inwardly experienced. Goethe was
aware of the fact that there is such an inward experience of the idea.
In the self-conscious ego he perceived the breath of the living idea.
Goethe says of Kant's Critique of Judgment that he owed a
most happy period of his life to this book. The great
leading thoughts of this work were quite analogous to my previous
creations, actions and thinking. The inner life of art and nature, the
unfolding of the activity in both cases from within, was distinctly
expressed in this book. Yet, this statement of Goethe must not
deceive us concerning his opposition to Kant, for in the essay in
which it occurs, we also read, Passionately stimulated, I
proceeded on my own paths so much the quicker because I, myself, did
not know where they led, and because I found little resonance with
the Kantians for what I had conquered for myself and for
the methods in which I had arrived at my results. For I
expressed what had been stirred up in me and not what I had
read.
A strictly unitary (monastic) world conception is peculiar to
Goethe. He sets out to gain one viewpoint from which the whole
universe reveals its law structure from the brick that falls
from the roof to the brilliant flash of inspiration that dawns on you
and that you convey. For all effects of whatever kind they
may be that we observe in experience are interconnected in the most
continuous fashion and flow into one another.
A brick is loosened from a roof. We ordinarily call this
accidental. It hits the shoulder of a passerby, one would say
mechanically, but not completely mechanically; it follows the
laws of gravity and so its effect is physical. The torn vessels
of living tissue immediately cease to function; at the same moment,
the fluids act chemically, their elementary qualities emerge.
But the disturbed organic life resists just as quickly and
tries to restore itself. In the meantime, the whole human being is
more or less unconscious and psychically shattered. Upon
regaining consciousness the person feels ethically deeply hurt,
deploring the interrupted activity of whatever kind it might have
been, for man will only reluctantly yield to patience. Religiously,
however, it will be easy for him to ascribe this incident to
Providence, to consider it a prevention against a greater evil, as
a preparation for a good of a higher order. This may be
sufficient for the patient, but the recovered man arises genially,
trusts in God and in himself and feels himself saved. He may well
seize upon the accidental and turn it to his own advantage, thus
beginning a new and eternally fresh cycle of life.
Thus, with the example of a fallen brick Goethe illustrates the
interconnection of all kinds of natural effects. It would be an
explanation in Goethe's sense if one could also derive their strictly
law-determined interconnection out of one root.
Kant and Goethe appear as two spiritual antipodes at the most
significant moment in the history of modern world conception, and the
attitude of those who were interested in the highest questions was
fundamentally different toward them. Kant constructed his world
conception with all the technical means of a strict school philosophy;
Goethe philosophized naively, depending trustfully on his healthy
nature. For this reason, Fichte, as mentioned above, believed that in
Goethe he could only turn to the representative of the purest
spirituality of Feeling as it appears on the stage of humanity
that has been reached at the present time. But he had the
opinion of Kant that no human mind can advance further than to
the limit at which Kant had stood, especially in his Critique of
Judgment. Whoever penetrates into the world conception of
Goethe, however, which is presented in the cloak of naiveté, will,
nevertheless, find a firm foundation that can be expressed in the form
of clear ideas. Goethe himself did not raise this foundation into the
full light of consciousness. For this reason, his mode of conception
finds entrance only slowly into the evolution of philosophy, and at
the beginning of the nineteenth century it is Kant's position with
which the spirits first attempt to come to clarity and with whom they
begin to settle their account.
No matter how great Kant's influence was, his contemporaries could not
help feeling that their deeper need for knowledge could not become
satisfied by him. Such a demand for enlightenment urgently seeks after
a unitary world conception as it is given in Goethe's case. With Kant,
the individual realms of existence are standing side by side without
transition. For this reason, Fichte, in spite of his unconditional
veneration for Kant, could not conceal from himself the fact
that Kant had only hinted at the truth, but had neither
presented nor proved it. And further:
This wonderful, unique man had either a divination for the truth
without being aware of the reasons for it, or he estimated his
contemporaries as insufficient to have these reasons conveyed to them,
or, again, he was reluctant during his lifetime to attract the
superhuman veneration that sooner or later would have been bestowed
upon him. No one has understood him as yet, and nobody will succeed in
doing so who does not arrive at Kant's results in following his own
ways; when it does happen, the world really will be astonished.
But I know just as certainly that Kant had such a system in mind,
that all statements that he actually did express are fragments and
results of this system, and have meaning and consistence only under
this presupposition.
For, if this were not the case, Fichte would be more inclined to
consider the Critique of Pure Reason the product of the
strangest accident than as the work of a mind.
Other contemporaries also judged Kant's world of ideas to be
insufficient. Lichtenberg, one of the most brilliant and at the
same time most independent minds of the second half of the eighteenth
century, who appreciated Kant, nevertheless could not suppress
significant objections to his philosophy. On the one hand he says,
What does it mean to think in Kant's spirit? I believe it
means to find the relation of our being, whatever that may be, toward
the things we call external, that is to say, to define the relation of
the subjective to the objective. This, to be sure, has always been the
aim of all thorough natural scientists, but it is questionable if they
ever proceeded so truly philosophically as did Herr Kant. What
is and must be subjective was taken as objective.
On the other hand, however, Lichtenberg observes, Should it
really be an established fact that our reason cannot know anything
about the supersensible? Should it not be possible for us to weave our
ideas of God and immortality to as much purpose as the spider weaves
his net to catch flies? In other words, should there not be beings who
admire us because of our ideas of God and immortality just as we
admire the spider and silkworm?
One could, however, raise a much more significant objection. If it is
correct that the law of human reason refers only to the inner worlds
of the mind, how do we then manage even to speak of things outside
ourselves at all? In that case, we should have to be completely caught
in the cobweb of our inner world. An objection of this kind is raised
by G. E. Schulze (1761 1833) in his book, Aenesidemus,
which appeared anonymously in 1792. In it he maintains that all
our knowledge is nothing but mere conceptions and we could in
no way go beyond the world of our inner thought pictures. Kant's
moral truths are also finally refuted with this step, for if
not even the possibility to go beyond the inner world is thinkable,
then it is also impossible that a moral voice could lead us into such
a world that is impossible to think. In this way, a new doubt with
regard to all truths develops out of Kant's view, and the philosophy
of criticism is turned into scepticism.
One of the most consistent followers of scepticism is S. Maimon
(1753 1800), who, from 1790 on, wrote several books that were
under the influence of Kant and Schulze. In them he defended with
complete determination the view that, because of the very nature of
our cognitive faculty, we are not permitted to speak of the existence
of external objects. Another disciple of Kant, Jacob Sigismund
Beck, went even so far as to maintain that Kant himself had really
not assumed things outside ourselves and that it was nothing but a
misunderstanding if such a conception was ascribed to him.
One thing is certain; Kant offered his contemporaries innumerable
points for attack and interpretations. Precisely through his
unclarities and contradictions, he became the father of the classical
German world conceptions of Fichte, Schelling, Schopenhauer, Hegel,
Herbart and Schleiermacher. His unclarities became new questions for
them. No matter how he endeavored to limit knowledge in order to make
place for belief, the human spirit can confess to be satisfied in the
true sense of the word only through knowledge, through cognition. So
it came to pass that Kant's successors strove to restore knowledge to
its full rights again, that they attempted to settle through
knowledge the highest needs of man.
Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762 1814) seemed to be chosen by
nature to continue Kant's work in this direction. Fichte confessed,
The love of knowledge and especially speculative knowledge, when
it has laid hold on man, occupies him to such an extent that no other
wish is left in him but that to pursue it with complete calm and
concentration. Fichte can be called an enthusiast of world
conception. Through this enthusiasm he must have laid a charm on his
contemporaries and especially on his students. Forberg, who was one of
his disciples, tells us:
In his public addresses his speech rushes powerfully on like a
thunderstorm that unloads its fire in individual strokes of lightning;
he lifts the soul up; he means to produce not only good men but great
men; his eye is stern; his step bold; through his philosophy he
intends to lead the spirit of the age; his imagination is not flowery,
but strong and powerful; his pictures are not graceful but bold and
great. He penetrates into the innermost depths of his object and he
moves in the realm of concepts with an ease that betrays that he not
only lives in this invisible land, but rules there.
The most outstanding trait in Fichte's personality is the grand,
serious style of his life conception. He measures everything by
the highest standards. In describing the calling of the writer, for
instance, he says:
The idea itself must speak, not the writer. All his arbitrary traits,
his whole individuality, all the manner and art peculiar to himself
must have died in his utterances so that the manner and art of his
idea alone may live, the highest life it can obtain in this language
and this age. Since he is free from the obligations of the oral
teacher, he is also free to conform to the-receptivity of others
without their excuses. He has not a given reader in mind but
postulates the one who reads him, laying down the law as to how he
must do so.
But the work of the writer is a work for eternity. Let future ages
swing up to a higher level in the science he has deposited in his
work. What he has laid down in his book is not only the science, but
the definite and perfect character of an age in regard to this
science, and this will retain its interest as long as there are human
beings in this world. Independent of all vicissitude, his writing
speaks in all ages to all men who are capable of bringing his letters
to life and who are stirred by his message, elevated and ennobled
until the end of the world.
A man speaks in these words who is aware of his call as a spiritual
leader of his age, and who seriously means what he says in the preface
to his Doctrine of Science: My person is of no importance
at all, but Truth is of all importance for I am a priest of
Truth. We can understand that a man who, like him, lives
in the Kingdom of Truth does not merely mean to guide
others to an understanding, but that he intended to force
them to it. Thus, he could give one of his writings the title,
A Radiantly Clear Report to the Larger Public Concerning the Real
Essence of the Newest Philosophy. An Attempt to Force the Readers to
Understand. Fichte is a personality who believes that, in order to
walk life's course, he has no need of the real world and its facts;
rather, he keeps his eyes riveted on the world of idea. He holds those
in low esteem who do not understand such an idealistic attitude of
spirit.
While in the narrow horizon that is given through ordinary experience,
people think and judge more objectively and correctly than perhaps
ever before, most are, nevertheless, completely confused and dazzled
as soon as they are to go even one step further. Where it is
impossible to rekindle the once extinguished spark of the higher
genius, one has to leave them within the circle of their horizon and,
insofar as they are useful and necessary in this circle, one can grant
them their value in and for it without curtailment. But when they now
demand of us to bring down to their level everything they, themselves,
cannot reach up to, when they, for instance, demand that everything
printed should be useful as a cookbook, or as a textbook of
arithmetic, or as a book of general regulations and orders, and then
decry everything that cannot be used in such a fashion, then they are
very wrong indeed.
We know as well, and possibly better than they, that ideals cannot be
presented in the real world. What we maintain, however, is that the
reality has to be judged by them, to be modified through those who
feel the necessary strength for it within themselves. Suppose they
could not convince themselves of this necessity. Then they would lose
very little of what they are by nature anyway, and humanity would lose
nothing at all. Their decision would merely make clear that they alone
are not counted on in the scheme of providence for mankind's
perfection. Providence will doubtless continue to pursue its course;
we commend those people, however, to the care of a kind nature, to
supply them in due time with rain and sunshine, with wholesome food
and an undisturbed circulation of their gastric juices, at the same
time endowing them with clever thoughts!
Fichte wrote these words in the preface to the publication of the
lectures in which he had spoken to the students of Jena on the
Destination of the Scholar. Views like those of Fichte have
their origin in a great energy of the soul, giving sureness for
knowledge of world and life. Fichte had blunt words for all those who
did not feel the strength in themselves for such a sureness. When the
philosopher, Reinhold, ventured the statement that the inner voice of
man could also be in error, Fichte replied, You say the
philosopher should entertain the thought that he, as an individual,
could also be mistaken and that he, therefore, could and should learn
from others. Do you know whose thought mood you are describing with
these words? That of a man who has never in his whole life been really
convinced of something. To this vigorous personality,
whose eyes were entirely directed to the inner life, it was repugnant
to search anywhere else for a world conception, the highest aim man
can obtain, except in his inner life. All culture should be the
exercise of all faculties toward the one purpose of complete
freedom, that is to say, of the complete independence from everything
that is not we, ourselves, our pure Self (reason, moral law), for
only this is ours. . . .
This is Fichte's judgment in his Contributions Toward the
Corrections of the Public Judgments Concerning the French Revolution,
which appeared in 1793. Should not the most valuable energy in
man, his power of knowledge, be directed toward this one
purpose of complete independence from everything that is not we,
ourselves? Could we ever arrive at a complete independence if we were
dependent in our world conception on any kind of being? If it had been
predetermined by such a being outside ourselves of what nature our
soul and our duties are, and that we thereby procured a
knowledge afterwards out of such an accomplished fact? If we
are independent, then we must be independent also with regard to the
knowledge of truth. If we receive something that has come into
existence without our help, then we are dependent on this something.
For this reason, we cannot receive the highest truths. We must
create them, they must come into being through us. Thus, Fichte can
only place something at the summit of his world conception that
obtains its existence through ourselves. When we say about a thing of
the external world, It is, we are doing so because
we perceive it. We know that we are recognizing the existence of
another being. What this other being is does not depend on us.
We can know its qualities only when we direct our faculty of
perception toward it. We should never know what red,
warm, cold is, if we did not know it through
perception. We cannot add anything to these qualities of the thing,
nor can we subtract anything from them. We say, They
are. What they are is what they tell us. This is
entirely different in regard to our own existence. Man does not say to
himself, It is, but, I am. He says, thereby,
not only that he is, but also what he is, namely, an
I. Only another being could say concerning me,
It is. This is, in fact, what another being would have
to say, for even in the case that this other being should have
created me, it could not say concerning my existence, I
am. The statement, I am, loses all meaning if it is
not uttered by the being itself that speaks about its own existence.
There is, therefore, nothing in the world that can address me as
I except myself. This recognition of myself as an
I, therefore, must be my own original action. No being
outside myself can have influence on this.
At this point Fichte found something with respect to which he saw
himself completely independent of every foreign entity. A
God could create me, but he would have to leave it to myself to
recognize myself as an I. I give my ego-consciousness to
myself. In this way, Fichte obtained a firm point for his world
conception, something in which there is certainty. How do matters
stand now concerning the existence of other beings? l ascribe this
existence to them, but to do so I have not the same right as with
myself. They must become part of my I if I am to recognize
an existence in them with the same right, and they do become a part of
myself as I perceive them, for as soon as this is the case, they are
there for me. What I can say is only, my self feels
red, my self' feels warm. Just as truly
as I ascribe to myself an existence, I can also ascribe it to my
feeling, to my sensation. Therefore, if I understand myself rightly, I
can only say, I am, and I myself ascribe existence also to an external
world.
For Fichte, the external world lost its independent existence in this
way: It has an existence that is only ascribed to it by the ego,
projected by the ego's imagination. In his endeavor to give to his own
self the highest possible independence, Fichte deprived
the outer world of all self-dependence. Now, where such an independent
external world is not supposed to exist, it is also quite
understandable if the interest in a knowledge concerning this external
world ceases. Thereby, the interest in what is properly called
knowledge is altogether extinguished, for the ego learns nothing
through its knowledge but what it produces for itself. In all
such knowledge the human ego holds soliloquies, as it were, with
itself. It does not transcend its own being. It can do so only through
what can be called living action. When the ego acts, when it
accomplishes something in the world, then it is no longer alone by
itself, talking to itself. Then its actions flow out into the world.
They obtain a self-dependent existence. I accomplish something and
when I have done so, this something will continue to have its effect,
even if I no longer participate in its action. What I know has being
only through myself, what I do, is part and parcel of a moral world
order independent of myself. But what does all certainty that we
derive from our own ego mean compared to this highest truth of a moral
world order, which must surely be independent of ourselves if
existence is to have any significance at all? All knowledge is
something only for the ego, but this world order must be
something outside the ego. It must be, in spite of the fact that we
cannot know anything of it. We must, therefore, believe it.
In this manner Fichte also goes beyond knowledge and arrives at
a belief. Compared to this belief, all knowledge is as dream to
reality. The ego itself has only such a dream existence as long as it
contemplates itself. It makes itself a picture of itself, which
does not have to be anything but a passing picture; it is action
alone that remains. Fichte describes this dream life of the world
with significant words in his Vocation of Man:
There is nowhere anything permanent, neither within myself nor
outside, but there is only a never ceasing change. Nowhere do I know
of any being, not even of my own being. I, myself, do
not know at all, and I am not. Pictures are; they are the only
thing that is, and they know of themselves after the fashion of
pictures; hovering pictures that pass by, without anything that
they pass: interconnected through pictures of pictures, pictures
without anything that is depicted in them, without meaning and
purpose. I, myself, am one of these pictures; in fact, I am not even
that but only a confused picture of pictures. All reality is changed
into a strange dream without a life of which to dream, without a
spirit to do the dreaming; it changes into a dream, which is held
together by a dream of itself. Seeing this is the dream;
thinking the source of all beings, of all reality, which I
imagine, of my being, my strength of my purposes. This is
the dream of that dream.
In what a different light the moral world order, the world of belief,
appears to Fichte:
My will is to exert its effect absolutely through itself, without any
tool that would only weaken its expression, in a completely
homogeneous sphere, as reason upon reason, as spirit upon what is also
spirit; in a sphere to which, however, my will is not to give
the law of life, of activity, of progression, but which contains
this in itself. My will, then, is to exert itself upon self-active
reason, but self-active reason is will. The law of the supersensible
world accordingly would be a will. . . . This sublime will,
therefore, does not pursue its course separated from the rest of the
world of reason in a detached fashion. There is a spiritual bond
between the sublime will and all finite rational beings, and the
sublime will itself is this spiritual bond within the world of
reason. . . . I hide my face before you and I lay my hands on my lips.
What you are for yourself and how you appear to yourself, I can never
know as surely as I can never become you. After having lived through a
thousand spirit worlds a thousand times, I shall be able to understand
you as little as now in this house of clay. What I understand becomes
finite merely through my understanding it, and the finite can never be
changed into the infinite, not even through an infinite growth and
elevation. You are separated from the finite not by a difference in
degree but in kind. Through that gradation they will make you into a
greater and greater man, but never into God, into the infinite that is
capable of no measure.
Because knowledge is a dream and the moral world order is the only
true reality for Fichte, he places the life through which man
participates in the moral world order higher than knowledge, the
contemplation of things. Nothing, so Fichte maintains,
has unconditional value and significance except life; everything
else, for instance thinking, poetic imagination and knowledge, has
value only insofar as it refers in some way to the living, insofar as
it proceeds from it or means to turn back into it.
This is the fundamental ethical trait in Fichte's personality, which
extinguished or reduced in significance everything in his world
conception that does not directly tend toward the moral destination of
man. He meant to establish the highest, the purest aims and standards
for life, and for this purpose he refused to be distracted by any
process of knowledge that might discover contradictions with the
natural world order in these aims. Goethe made the statement,
The active person is always without conscience; no one has
conscience except the onlooker. He means to say that the
contemplative man estimates everything in its true, real value,
understanding and recognizing everything in its own proper place. The
active man, however, is, above everything else, bent on seeing his
demands fulfilled; he is not concerned with the question of whether or
not he thereby encroaches upon the rights of things. Fichte was, above
all, concerned with action; he was, however, unwilling to be charged
by contemplation with lack of conscience. He, therefore, denied the
value of contemplation.
To effect life immediately this was Fichte's continuous endeavor. He
felt most satisfied when he believed that his words could become
action in others. It is under the influence of this ardent desire that
he composed the following works. Demand to the Princess of Europe
to Return the Freedom of Thought, Which They Have Heretofore
Suppressed. Heliopolis in the Last Year of the Old Darkness 1792;
Contributions Toward the Correction of the Public Judgment Concerning
the French Revolution 1793. This ardent desire also caused him to
give his powerful speeches, Outline of the Present Age
Presented in Lectures in Berlin in 1804 5; Direction Toward
the Beatific Life or Doctrine of Religion, Lectures given in
Berlin in 1806; finally, his Speeches to the German Nation,
1808.
Unconditional surrender to the moral world order, action that springs
out of the deepest core of man's nature: These are the demands through
which life obtains value and meaning. This view runs through all of
Fichte's speeches and writings as the basic theme. In his Outline
of the Present Age, he reprimands this age with flaming words for
its egotism. He claims that everybody is only following the path
prescribed by his lower desires, but these desires lead him away from
the great totality that comprises the human community in moral
harmony. Such an age must needs lead those who live in its tendency
into decline and destruction. What Fichte meant to enliven in the
human soul was the sense of duty and obligation.
In this fashion, Fichte attempted to exert a formative influence on
the life of his time with his ideas because he saw these ideas as
vigorously enlivened by the consciousness that man derives the highest
content of his soul life from a world to which he can obtain access by
settling his account with his ego all by himself. In so
doing man feels himself in his true vocation. From such a conviction,
Fichte coins the words, I, myself, and my necessary purpose are
the supersensible.
To be aware of himself as consciously living in the supersensible is,
according to Fichte, an experience of which man is capable. When he
arrives at this experience, he then knows the I within
himself, and it is only through this act that he becomes a
philosopher. This experience, to be sure, cannot be proven
to somebody who is unwilling to undergo it himself. How little
Fichte considers such a proof possible is documented by
expressions like, The gift of a philosopher is inborn, furthered
through education and then obtained by self-education, but there is no
human art to make philosophers. For this reason, philosophy
expects few proselytes among those men who are already formed,
polished and perfected. . . .
Fichte is intent on finding a soul constitution through which the
human ego can experience itself. The knowledge of nature
seems unsuitable to him to reveal anything of the essence of the
ego. From the fifteenth to the eighteenth century,
thinkers arose who were concerned with the question: What element
could be found in the picture of nature by means of which the human
being could become explainable in this picture? Goethe did not see the
question in this way. He felt a spiritual nature behind the externally
manifested one. For him, the human soul is capable of experiences
through which it lives not only in the externally manifested, but
within the creative forces. Goethe was in quest of the idea, as were
the Greeks, but he did not look for it as perceptible idea. He meant
to find it in participating in the world processes through
inner experience where these can no longer be perceived. Goethe
searched in the soul for the life of nature. Fichte also
searched in the soul itself, but he did not focus his search where
nature lives in the soul but immediately where the soul feels its own
life kindled without regard to any other world processes and world
entities with which this life might be connected. With Fichte, a world
conception arose that exhausted all its endeavor in the attempt to
find an inner soul life that compared to the thought life of the
Greeks, as did their thought life to the picture conception of the age
before them. In Fichte, thought becomes an experience of the ego as
the picture had become thought with the Greek thinkers. With Fichte,
world conception is ready to experience self-consciousness;
with Plato and Aristotle, it had arrived at the point to think
soul consciousness.
Just as Kant dethroned knowledge in order to make place for belief, so
Fichte declared knowledge to be mere appearance in order to open the
gates for living action, for moral activity. A similar attempt was
also made by Schiller. Only in his case, the part that was
claimed by belief in Kant's philosophy, and by action in that of
Fichte, was now occupied by beauty. Schiller's significance in
the development of world conception is usually underestimated. Goethe
had to complain that he was not recognized as a natural scientist just
because people had become accustomed to take him as a poet, and those
who penetrate into Schiller's philosophical ideas must regret that he
is appreciated so little by the scholars who deal with the history of
world conception, because Schiller's field is considered to be limited
to the realm of poetry.
As a thoroughly self-dependent thinker, Schiller takes his attitude
toward Kant, who had been so stimulating and thought-provoking to him.
The loftiness of the moral belief to which Kant meant to lift man was
highly appreciated by the poet who, in his Robbers, and
Cabal and Love, had held a mirror to the corruption of his
time. But he asked himself the question: Should it indeed be a
necessary truth that man can be lifted to the height of the
categorical imperative only through the struggle against his
desires and urges? Kant wanted to ascribe to the sensual nature of man
only the inclination toward the low, the self-seeking, the
gratification of the senses, and only he who lifted himself above the
sensual nature, who mortified the flesh and who alone allowed the pure
spiritual voice of duty to speak within him: Only he could be
virtuous. Thus, Kant debased the natural man in order to be able to
elevate the moral man so much the higher. To Schiller this judgment
seemed to contain something that was unworthy of man. Should it not be
possible to ennoble the impulses of man to become in themselves
inclined toward the life of duty and morality? They would then not
have to be suppressed to become morally effective. Schiller,
therefore, opposes Kant's rigorous demand of duty in the epigram:
Gladly I serve my friends, but, alas, I do so with pleasure
And so I oftentimes grieve that I lack virtue indeed.
There is no better advice; you must try to despise them
And with disgust you must do strictly as duty commands.
Schiller attempted to dissolve these scruples of
conscience in his own fashion. There are actually two impulses
ruling in man: The impulses of the sensual desire and the impulse of
reason. If man surrenders to the sensual impulse, he is a plaything of
his desires and passions, in short, of his egoism. If he gives himself
completely up to the impulses of reason, he is a slave of its rigorous
commands, its inexorable logic, its categorical imperative. A man who
wants to live exclusively for the sensual impulse must silence
reason; a man who wants to serve reason only must mortify
sensuality. If the former, nevertheless, listens to the voice of
reason, he will yield to it only reluctantly against his own will; if
the latter observes the call of his desires, he feels them as a burden
on his path of virtue. The physical nature of man and his spiritual
character then seem to live in a fateful discord. Is there no state in
man in which both the impulses, the sensual and the spiritual, live in
harmony? Schiller's answer to this question is positive. There is,
indeed, such a state in man. It is the state in which the beautiful
is created and enjoyed. He who creates a work of art follows a
free impulse of nature. He follows an inclination in doing so, but it
is not physical passion that drives him. It is imagination; it is the
spirit. This also holds for a man who surrenders to the enjoyment of a
work of art. The work of art, while it affects his sensuality,
satisfies his spirit at the same time. Man can yield to his desires
without observing the higher laws of the spirit; he can comply with
his duties without paying attention to sensuality. A beautiful work of
art affects his delight without awakening his desires, and it
transports him into a world in which he abides by virtue of his own
disposition. Man is comparable to a child in this state, following his
inclinations in his actions without asking if they run counter to the
laws of reason. The sensual man is led through beauty . . . into
thinking; through beauty, the spiritual man is led back to matter,
returned to the world of the senses (Letters on the Esthetic
Education of Man; Letter 18).
The lofty freedom and equanimity of the spirit, combined with strength
and vigor is the mood in which we should part from a genuine work of
art; there is no surer test of its true esthetic quality. If, after an
enjoyment of this kind, we find ourselves inclined to some particular
sentiment or course of action, but awkward and ill at ease for
another, then this can serve as infallible proof that we have not
experienced a pure esthetic effect; this may be caused by the
object or our mode of approach, or (as is almost always the case) by
both causes simultaneously. (Letter 22.)
As man is, through beauty, neither the slave of sensuality nor of
reason, but because through its mediation both factors contribute
their effect in a balanced cooperation in man's soul, Schiller
compares the instinct for beauty with the child's impulse who, in his
play, does not submit his spirit to the laws of reason, but employs it
freely according to his inclination. It is for this reason that
Schiller calls the impulse for beauty, play-impulse:
In relation to the agreeable, to the good, to the perfect, man is
only serious, but he plays with beauty. In this respect, to be
sure, we must not think of the games that go on in real life and that
ordinarily are concerned with material objects, but in real life we
should also search in vain for the beauty that is meant here. The
beauty existing in reality is on the same level as the play-impulse in
the real world, but through the ideal of beauty, which is upheld by
reason, an ideal is also demanded of the play-impulse that man is to
consider wherever he plays. (Letter 15.)
In the realization of this ideal play-impulse, man finds the reality
of freedom. Now, he no longer obeys reason, nor does he
follow sensual inclinations any longer. He now acts from inclination
as if the spring of his action were reason. Man shall only play
with beauty and it is only with beauty that he shall play. . To
state it without further reserve, man plays only when he is human in
the full sense of the word and he is only wholly human when he is
playing. Schiller could also have said: In play man is
free; in following the command of duty, and in yielding to
sensuality, he is unfree. If man wants to be human in the full
meaning of the word, and also with regard to his moral actions, that
is to say, if he really wants to be free, then he must live in the
same relation to his virtues as he does to beauty. He must ennoble his
inclinations into virtues and must be so permeated by his virtues that
he feels no other inclination than that of following them. A man who
has established this harmony between inclination and duty can, in
every moment, count on the morality of his actions as a matter of
course.
From this viewpoint, one can also look at man's social life. A man who
follows his sensual desires is self-seeking. He would always be bent
on his own well-being if the state did not regulate the social
intercourse through laws of reason. The free man accomplishes through
his own impulse what the state must demand of the self-seeking. In a
community of free men no compulsory laws are necessary.
In the midst of the fearful world of forces, and in the awe-demanding
sanctuary of laws, the esthetic formative impulse is imperceptibly
building a third delightful realm of play and appearances in which man
is released from the fetters of all circumstances and freed from
everything that is called compulsion, both in the physical and in the
moral world. (Letter 27.)
This realm extends upward as far as the region where reason rules with
unconditional necessity and where all matter ceases; it stretches
below as far as the world in which the force of nature holds sway with
blind compulsion.
Thus, Schiller considers a moral realm as an ideal in which the temper
of virtue rules with the same ease and freedom as the esthetic taste
governs in the realm of beauty. He makes life in the realm of beauty
the model of a perfect moral social order in which man is liberated in
every direction. Schiller closes the beautiful essay in which he
proclaims this ideal with the question of whether such an order had
anywhere been realized. He answers with the words:
As a need, it exists in every delicately attuned soul; as an actuality
it can probably only be found, like the pure church and the pure
republic, in a few select circles where, not the thoughtless imitation
of heterogeneous customs, but the inherent beautiful nature guides the
demeanor, where man goes with undismayed simplicity and undisturbed
innocence through the most complicated situations without the need of
offending the freedom of others nor of defending his own, without need
of offending his dignity in order to show charm and grace.
In this virtue refined into beauty, Schiller found a mediation between
the world conceptions of Kant and Goethe. No matter how great the
attraction that Schiller had found in Kant when the latter had
defended the ideal of a pure humanity against the prevailing moral
order, when Schiller became more intimately acquainted with Goethe, he
became an admirer of Goethe's view of world and life. Schiller's mind,
always relentlessly striving for the purest clarity of thought, was
not satisfied before he had succeeded in penetrating also conceptually
into this wisdom of Goethe. The high satisfaction Goethe derived from
his view of beauty and art, and also for his conduct of life,
attracted Schiller more and more to the mode of Goethe's conception.
In the letter in which Schiller thanks Goethe for sending him his
Wilhelm Meister, he says:
I cannot express to you how painfully I am impressed when I turn from
a product of this kind to the bustle of philosophy. In the one world
everything is so serene, so alive, so harmoniously dissolved, so truly
human; in the other, everything is so rigorous, so rigid and abstract,
so unnatural, because nature is always nothing but synthesis and
philosophy is antithesis. I may claim, to be sure, to have in all my
speculations remained as faithful to nature as is compatible with the
concept of analysis; I may, indeed, have remained more faithful to her
than our Kantians considered permissible and possible. I feel,
nevertheless, the infinite distance between life and reflection, and
in such a melancholy moment I cannot help considering as a defect in
my nature what, in a more cheerful hour, I must regard as merely a
trait inherent in the nature of things. In the meantime, I am certain
of this at least: The poet is the only true man and, compared
to him, the best philosopher is merely a caricature.
This judgment of Schiller can only refer to the Kantian philosophy
with which he had had his experiences. In many respects, it estranges
man from nature. It approaches nature with no confidence in it but
recognizes as valid truth only what is derived from man's own mental
organization. Through this trait all judgments of that philosophy seem
to lack the lively content and color so characteristic of everything
that has its source in the immediate experience of nature's events and
things themselves. This philosophy moves in bloodless, gray and cold
abstractions. It has sacrificed the warmth we derive from the
immediate touch with things and beings and has exchanged the frigidity
of its abstract concepts for it. In the field of morality, also,
Kant's world conception presents the same antagonism to nature. The
duty-concept of pure reason is regarded as its highest aims. What man
loves, what his inclinations tend to, everything in man's being that
is immediately rooted in man's nature, must be subordinated to this
ideal of duty. Kant goes even as far as the realm of beauty to
extinguish the share that man must have in it according to his
original sensations and feelings. The beautiful is to produce a
delight that is completely free from interest. Compare
that with how devoted, how really interested Schiller
approaches a work in which he admires the highest stage of artistic
production. He says concerning Wilhelm Meister:
I can express the feeling that permeates me and takes possession of me
as I read this book no better than as a sweet well-being, as a feeling
of spiritual and bodily health, and I am firmly convinced that this
must be the feeling with all readers in general. . . . I explain this
well-being with the quiet clarity, smoothness and transparence that
prevails throughout the book, leaving the reader without the slightest
dissatisfaction and disturbance, and producing no more emotion than is
necessary to kindle and support a cheerful life in his soul.
These are not the words of somebody who believes in delight without
interest, but of a man who is convinced that the pleasure in the
beautiful is capable of being so refined that a complete surrender to
this pleasure does not involve degradation. Interest is not to be
extinguished as we approach the work of art; rather are we to become
capable of including in our interest what has its source in the
spirit. The true man is to develop this kind of interest
for the beautiful also with respect to his moral conceptions. Schiller
writes in a letter to Goethe, It is really worth observing that
the slackness with regard to esthetic things appears always to be
connected with moral slackness, and that a pure rigorous striving for
high beauty with the highest degree of liberality concerning
everything that is nature will contain in itself rigorism in moral
life.
The estrangement from nature in the world conception and in all of the
culture of the time in which he lived was felt so strongly by Schiller
that he made it the subject of his essay, On Naive and Sentimental
Poetry. He compares the life conception of his time with that of
the Greeks and raises the question, How is it that we, who are
infinitely surpassed by the ancients in everything that is nature, can
render homage to nature to a higher degree, cling to her with fervour
and can embrace even the lifeless world with the warmest
sentiments. He answers this question by saying:
This is caused by the fact that, with us, nature has vanished out of
humanity and we therefore find her in reality only outside humanity in
the inanimate world. It is not our greater naturalness, but,
quite to the contrary, the unnaturalness of our lives, state of
affairs and customs that drives us to give satisfaction in the
physical to the awakening sense for truth and simplicity, which, like
the moral faculty from which it springs, lies without corruption and
inextinguishably in all men's hearts because we no longer can hope to
find it in the moral world. It is for this reason that the feeling
with which we cling to nature is so closely related to the sentiment
with which we lament the loss of the age of childhood and of the
child's innocence. Our childhood is the only unspoiled nature that we
still find in civilized humanity, and it is, therefore, no wonder that
every footstep of nature leads us back to our own childhood.
This was entirely different with the Greeks. They lived their lives
within the bounds of the natural. Everything they did sprang from
their natural conception, feeling and sentiment. They were
intimately bound to nature. Modern man feels himself in his own being
placed in contrast to nature. As the urge toward this primeval mother
of being cannot be extinguished, it transforms itself in the modern
soul into a yearning for nature, into a search for it. The Greek
had nature; modern man searches for nature.
As long as man is still pure nature and, to be sure, not brutal, he
acts as an undivided sensual unity and as a harmonizing whole. His
senses and his reason, his receptive and his self-active faculties,
have not as yet separated in their function and certainly do not act
in contradiction to each other. His sentiments are not the formless
play of chance; his thoughts, not the empty play of his imagination.
These thoughts have their origin in the law of necessity; the
sentiments, in reality. As soon as man comes into the state of
civilization, and as soon as art enters into his sphere of life, the
sensual harmony is dissolved and he can now only act as a
moral unity, that is to say, as striving for unity. The
agreement between his perception and his thought, which in his former
state was actual, is now merely ideal; it is no longer
in him, but beyond him; as a thought whose realization
is demanded, it is no longer a fact of his life.
The fundamental mood of the Greek spirit was naive, that of
modern man is sentimental. The Greeks' world conception could,
for this reason, be rightly realistic, for he had not yet separated
the spiritual from the natural; for him, nature included the spirit.
If he surrendered to nature, it was to a spirit-saturated nature.
This is not so with modern man. He has detached the spirit from
nature; he has lifted the spirit into the realm of gray abstractions.
If he were to surrender to his nature, he would yield to a
nature deprived of all spirit. Therefore, his loftiest striving must
be directed toward the ideal; through the striving for this
goal, spirit and nature are to be reconciled again. In Goethe's mode
of spirit, however, Schiller found something that was akin to the
Greek spirit. Goethe felt that he saw his ideas and thoughts with his
eyes because he felt reality as an undivided unity of spirit and
nature. According to Schiller, Goethe had preserved something in
himself that will be attained again by the sentimental man
when he has reached the climax of his striving. Modern man arrives at
such a summit in the esthetic mood as Schiller describes it in the
state of soul in which sensuality and reason are harmonized again.
The nature of the development of modern world conception is
significantly characterized in the observation Schiller made to Goethe
in his letter of August 23, 1794:
Had you been born a Greek and been surrounded since birth by exquisite
nature and idealizing art, your road would have been infinitely
shortened; perhaps it would have been made entirely unnecessary. With
the very first perception of things, you would have absorbed the form
of the necessary, and with your first experience, the grand style
would have developed within you. As it is now . . . since your Greek
spirit was cast into this nordic creation, you had no other choice
than either to become a nordic artist yourself or to supplement your
imagination by means of thought for what reality fails to supply, and
thus to give birth from within to another Greece.
Schiller, as these sentences show, is aware of the course that the
development of soul life has taken from the age of the ancient Greeks
until his own time, for the Greek soul life disclosed itself in the
life of thought and he could accept this unveiling because thought was
for him a perception like the perception of color and sounds. This
kind of thought life has faded away for modern man. The powers
that weave creatively through the world must be experienced by him as
an inner soul experience, and in order to render this imperceptible
thought life inwardly visible, it nevertheless must be filled by
imagination. This imagination must be such that it is felt as one with
the creative powers of nature.
Because soul consciousness has been transformed into
self-consciousness in modern man, the question of world
conception arises: How can self-consciousness experience itself so
vividly that it feels its conscious process as permeating the creative
process of the living world forces? Schiller answered this question
for himself in his own fashion when he claimed the life in the
artistic experience as his ideal. In this experience the human
self-consciousness feels its kinship with an element that transcends
the mere nature picture. In it, man feels himself seized by the
spirit as he surrenders as a natural and sensual being to the
world. Leibniz had attempted to understand the human soul as a
monad. Fichte had not proceeded from a mere idea to gain clarity of
the nature of the human soul; he searched for a form of experience
in which this soul lays hold on its own being. Schiller raises the
question: Is there a form of experience for the human soul in which it
can feel how it has its roots in spiritual reality? Goethe experiences
ideas in himself that present themselves to him at the same time as
ideas of nature.
In Goethe, Fichte and Schiller, the experienced idea one
could also say, the idea-experience forces its way into the
soul. Such a process had previously happened in the world of the
Greeks with the perceived idea, the idea-perception.
The world and life conception that lived in Goethe in a natural
(naive) way, and toward which Schiller strove on all detours of his
thought development, does not feel the need for the kind of
universally valid truth that sees its ideal in the mathematical form.
It is satisfied by another truth, which our spirit derives from the
immediate intercourse with the real world. The insights Goethe derived
from the contemplation of the works of art in Italy were, to be sure,
not of the unconditional certainty as are the theorems of mathematics,
but they also were less abstract. Goethe approached them with the
feeling, Here is necessity, here is God. A truth that
could not also be revealed in a perfect work of art did not exist for
Goethe. What art makes manifest with its technical means of tone,
marble, color, rhythm, etc., springs from the same source from which
the philosopher also draws who does not avail himself of visual means
of presentation but who uses as his means of expression only thought,
the idea itself. Poetry points at the mysteries of nature
and attempts to solve them through the picture, says Goethe.
Philosophy points at the mysteries of reason and attempts
to solve them through the word. In the final analysis, however,
reason and nature are, for him, inseparably one; the same truth is the
foundation of both. An endeavor for knowledge, which lives in
detachment from things in an abstract world, does not seem to him to
be the highest form of cognitive life. It would be the highest
attainment to understand that all factual knowledge is already
theory. The blueness of the sky reveals the fundamental law of
color phenomena to us. One should not search for anything behind
the phenomena; they, themselves, are the message.
The psychologist, Heinroth, in his Anthology, called the mode
of thinking through which Goethe arrived at his insights into the
natural formation of plants and animals, an object-related
thinking (Gegenstaendliches Denken). What he means is
that this mode of thinking does not detach itself from its objects,
but that the objects of observation are intimately permeated with this
thinking, that Goethe's mode of thinking is at the same time a form of
observation, and his mode of observation a form of thinking. Schiller
becomes a subtle observer as he describes this mode of spirit. He
writes on this subject in a letter to Goethe:
Your observing eye, which so calmly and clearly rests on things, keeps
you from being ever exposed to the danger of going astray in the
direction where speculation and an arbitrary, merely introspective
imagination so easily lose their way. Your correct intuition contains
everything, and in a far greater completeness, for which an analytical
mind searches laboriously; only because everything is at your disposal
as a complete whole are you unaware of your own riches, for
unfortunately we know only what we dissect. Spirits of your kind,
therefore, rarely know how far advanced they are and how little cause
they have to borrow from philosophy, which in turn can only learn from
them.
For the world conception of Goethe and Schiller, truth is not only
contained in science, but also in art. Goethe expresses his opinion as
follows, I think science could be called the knowledge of the
general art. Art would be science turned into action. Science would be
reason, and art its mechanism, wherefore one could also call it
practical science. Thus, finally, science would be the theorem
and art the problem. Goethe describes the
interdependence of scientific cognition and artistic expression of
knowledge thus:
It is obvious that an. . . . artist must become greater and more
erudite if he not only has his talent but is also a well-informed
botanist; if he knows, starting from the root, all the influences of
the various parts of a plant on its thriving and growth, their
function and mutual effect; if he has an insight into the successive
development of the leaves, the flowers, the fertilization, the fruit
and the new germ, and if he contemplates this process. Such an artist
will not merely show his taste through his power of selection from the
realm of appearances, but he will also surprise us with his correct
presentation of the characteristic qualities.
Thus, truth rules in the process of artistic creation for the
artistic style depends, according to this view, . . . on the
deepest foundations of knowledge, on the essence of things insofar as
it is permissible to know it in visible and touchable forms. The
fact that creative imagination is granted a share in the process of
knowledge and that the abstract intellect is no longer considered to
be the only cognitive faculty is a consequence of this view concerning
truth. The conceptions on which Goethe based his contemplation's on
plant and animal formations were not gray and abstract thoughts but
sensual-supersensual pictures, created by spontaneous
imagination. Only observation combined with imagination can really
lead into the essence of things, not bloodless abstraction; this is
Goethe's conviction. For this reason, Goethe said about Galileo that
he made his observations as a genius for whom one case
represents a thousand cases . . . when he developed the doctrine of
the pendulum and the fall of bodies from swinging church lamps.
Imagination uses the one case in order to produce a content-saturated
picture of what is essential in the appearances; the intellect that
operates by means of abstractions can, through combination, comparison
and calculation of the appearances, gain no more than a general rule
of their course. This belief in the possible cognitive function of an
imagination that rises into a conscious participation in the creative
world process is supported by Goethe's entire world conception.
Whoever, like him, sees nature's activity in everything, can also see
in the spiritual content of the human imagination nothing but higher
products of nature. The pictures of fantasy are products of nature
and, as they represent nature, they can only contain truth, for
otherwise nature would lie to herself in these afterimages that she
creates of herself. Only men with imagination can attain to the
highest stages of knowledge. Goethe calls these men the
comprehensive and the contemplative in
contrast to the merely intellectual-inquisitive, who have
remained on a lower stage of cognitive life.
The intellectual inquisitive need a calm, unselfish power of
observation, the excitement of curiosity, a clear intellect . . . ;
they only digest scientifically what they find ready-made.
The contemplative are already creative in their attitude, and
knowledge in them, as it reaches a higher level, demands contemplation
unconsciously and changes over into that form; much as they may shun
the word imagination, they will, nevertheless, before they
are aware of it, call upon the support of creative imagination.
. . The comprehensive thinkers who, with a prouder name, could be
called creative thinkers, are, in their attitude, productive in the
highest sense, for, as they start from ideas, they express from the
outset the unity of the whole. From then on, it is the task of nature,
as it were, to submit to these ideas.
It cannot occur to the believer in such a form of cognition to speak
of limitations of human knowledge in a Kantian fashion, for he
experiences within himself what man needs as his truth. The
core of nature is in the inner life of man. The world conception of
Goethe and Schiller does not demand of its truth that it should
be a repetition of the world phenomena in conceptual form. It does not
demand that its conception should literally correspond to
something outside man. What appears in man's inner life as an ideal
element, as something spiritual, is as such not to be found in any
external world; it appears as the climax of the whole development. For
this reason, it does not, according to this philosophy, have to appear
in all human beings in the same shape. It can take on an individual
form in any individual. Whoever expects to find the truth in the
agreement with something external can acknowledge only one form of
it, and he will look for it, with Kant, in the type of metaphysics
that alone will be able to present itself as
science. Whoever sees the element in which, as Goethe states in
his essay on Winckelmann, the universe, if it could feel itself,
would rejoice as having arrived at its aim in which it could admire
the climax of its own becoming and being, such a thinker can say
with Goethe, If I know my relation to myself and to the external
world, I call this truth; in this way everybody can have his own truth
and it is yet the same. For man in himself, insofar as he
uses his healthy senses, is the greatest and most exact apparatus of
physics that is possible. Yet, that the experiments separated, as it
were, from man, and that one wants to know nature only according to
the indications of artificial instruments, even intending to limit and
prove in this way what nature is capable of, is the greatest
misfortune of modern physics. Man, however, stands so high
that in him is represented what cannot be represented otherwise. What
is the string and all mechanical division of it compared to the ear of
the musician? One can even say, What are all elementary phenomena of
nature themselves compared to man who must master and modify them all
in order to be able to assimilate them to himself to a tolerable
degree.
Concerning his world picture, Goethe speaks neither of a mere
knowledge of intellectual concepts nor of belief; he speaks of a
contemplative perception in the spirit. He writes to Jacobi,
You trust in belief in God; I, in seeing. This seeing in
the spirit as it is meant here thus enters into the development of
world conception as the soul force that is appropriate to an age to
which thought is no longer what it had been to the Greek thinkers, but
in which thought had revealed itself as a product of
self-consciousness, a product, however, that is arrived at through the
fact that this self-consciousness is aware of itself as having its
being within the spiritually creative forces of nature. Goethe
is the representative of an epoch of world conception in which the
need is felt to make the transition from mere thinking to spiritual
seeing. Schiller strives to justify this transition against Kant's
position.
The close alliance that was formed by Goethe, Schiller and their
contemporaries between poetic imagination and world conception has
freed this conception from the lifeless expression that it must take
on when it exclusively moves in the region of the abstract intellect.
This alliance has resulted in the belief that there is a personal
element in world conception. It is possible for man to work out an
approach to the world for himself that is in accordance with his own
specific nature and enter thereby into the world of reality, not
merely into a world of fantastic schemes. His ideal no longer needs to
be that of Kant, which is formed after the model of mathematics and
arrives at a world picture that is once and for all finished and
completed. Only from a spiritual atmosphere of such a conviction that
has an inspiring effect on the human individuality can a conception
like that of Jean Paul (1763 1825) arise. The heart of
a genius, to whom all other splendor and help-giving energies are
subordinated, has one genuine symptom, namely, a new outlook on
world and life. How could it be the mark of the highest
developed man, of genius, to create a new world and life conception if
the conceived world consisted only in one form? Jean Paul is,
in his own way, a defender of Goethe's view that man experiences
inside his own self the ultimate existence. He writes to Jacobi:
Properly speaking, we do not merely believe in divine freedom,
God and virtue, but we really see them manifested or in the
process of manifestation; this very seeing is a knowing and a
higher form of knowing, while the knowledge of intellect merely refers
to a seeing of a lower order. One could call reason the
consciousness of the only positive, for everything positive
experienced by sense perception does finally dissolve into the
spiritual, and understanding carries on its bustle only with
the relative, which in itself is nothing, so that before God all
conditions of more or less, and all stages of comparison
cease to be.
Jean Paul will not allow anything to deprive him of the right to
experience truth inwardly and to employ all forces of the soul for
this purpose. He will not be restricted to the use of logical
intellect.
Transcendental philosophy (Jean Paul has in mind here the world view
following Kant) is not to tear the heart, man's living root, out of
his breast to replace it with a pure impulse of selfhood; I shall not
consent to be liberated from the dependence of Love, to be blessed by
pride only.
With these words he rejects the world-estranged moral order of Kant.
I remain firmly with my conviction that there are four last, and four
first things: Beauty, Truth, Morality and Salvation, and their
synthesis is not only necessary but also already a fact, but only in a
subtle spiritual-organic unity (and for just this reason it
is a unity), without which we could not find any understanding
of these four evangelists or world continents, nor any transition
between them.
The critical analysis of the intellect, which proceeded with an
extreme logical rigor, had, in Kant and Fichte, come to the point of
reducing the self-dependent significance of the real life-saturated
world to a mere shadow, to a dream picture. This view was unbearable
to men gifted with spontaneous imagination, who enriched life by the
creation of their imaginative power. These men felt the
reality; it was there in their perception, present in their souls, and
now it was attempted to prove to them its mere dreamlike quality.
The windows of the philosophical academic halls are too high to
allow a view into the alleys of real life, was the answer of
Jean Paul.
Fichte strove for the purest, highest experienced truth. He renounced
all knowledge that does not spring from our own inner source. The
counter movement to his world conception is formed by the Romantic
Movement. Fichte acknowledges only the truth, and the inner life
of man only insofar as it reveals the truth; the world conception of
the romanticists acknowledges only the inner life, and it declares as
valuable everything that springs from this inner life. The ego is not
to be chained by anything external. Whatever it produces is justified.
One may say about the romantic movement that it carries Schiller's
statement to its extreme consequence, Man plays only where he is
human in the full sense of the word, and he is only wholly human when
he is playing. Romanticism wants to make the whole world into a
realm of the artistic. The fully developed man knows no other norms
than the laws he creates through his freely ruling imaginative power,
in the same way as the artist creates those laws he impresses into his
works. He rises above everything that determines him from without and
lives entirely through the springs of his own self. The whole world is
for him nothing but a material for his esthetic play. The seriousness
of man in his everyday life is not rooted in truth. The soul that
arrives at true knowledge cannot take seriously the things by
themselves; for such a soul they are not in themselves valuable. They
are endowed with value only by the soul. The mood of a spirit that is
aware of his sovereignty over things is called by the romanticists,
the ironical mood of spirit.
Karl Wilhelm Ferdinand Solger (1780 1819) gave the
following explanation of the term romantic irony: The
spirit of the artist must comprise all directions in one sweeping
glance and this glance, hovering above everything, looking down on
everything and annihilating it, we call irony. Friedrich
Schlegel (1772 1829), one of the leading spokesmen for the
romantic turn of spirit, states concerning this mood of irony that it
takes everything in at a glance and rises infinitely above everything
that is limited, also above some form of art, virtue or genius. Whoever
lives in this mood feels bound by nothing; nothing determines the
direction of his activity for him. He can at his own pleasure
tune himself to be either philosophical or philological, critical or
poetical, historical or rhetorical, antique or modern. The
ironical spirit rises above an eternal moral world order, for this
spirit is not told what to do by anything except himself. The ironist
is to do what he pleases, for his morality can only be an esthetic
morality. The romanticists are the heirs of Fichte's thought of the
uniqueness of the ego. They were, however, unwilling to fill this ego
with a moral belief, as Fichte did, but stood above all on the right
of fantasy and of the unrestrained power of the soul. With them,
thinking was entirely absorbed by poetic imagination. Novalis says,
It is quite bad that poetry has a special name and that the poet
represents a special profession. It is not anything special by
itself. It is the mode of activity proper to the human spirit. Are
not the imaginations of man's heart at work every minute? The
ego, exclusively concerned with itself, can arrive at the highest
truth: It seems to man that he is engaged in a conversation,
and some unknown spiritual being causes him to develop the most
evident thoughts in a miraculous fashion.
Fundamentally, what the romanticists aimed at did not differ from what
Goethe and Schiller had also made their credo: A conception of man
through which he appeared as perfect and as free as possible.
Novalis experiences his poems and contemplation's in a soul
mood that had a relationship toward the world picture similar to that
of Fichte. Fichte's spirit, however, works the sharp contours of pure
concepts, while that of Novalis springs from a richness of soul,
feeling where others think, living in the element of love where others
aim to embrace what is and what goes on in the world with ideas. It is
the tendency of this age, as can be seen in its representative
thinkers, to search for the higher spirit nature in which the
self-conscious soul is rooted because it cannot have its roots in the
world of sense reality. Novalis feels and experiences himself as
having his being within the higher spirit nature. What he expresses he
feels through his innate genius as the revelations of this very spirit
nature. He writes:
One man succeeded; he lifted the veil of the goddess at Saris. What
did he see then? He saw wonder of wonders himself.
Novalis expresses his own intimate feeling of the spiritual mystery
behind the world of the senses and of the human self consciousness as
the organ through which this mystery reveals itself, in these words:
The spirit world is indeed already unlocked for us; it is always
revealed. If we suddenly became as elastic as we should be, we should
see ourselves in the midst of it.
|