The Classics of World and Life Conception
A sentence in Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling's Philosophy of
Nature strikes us like a flash of lightning illuminating the past
and future path of the evolution of philosophy. It reads, To
philosophize about nature means to create nature. What had been
a deep conviction of Goethe and Schiller, namely, that creative
imagination must have a share in the creation of a world conception,
is monumentally expressed in this sentence. What nature yields
voluntarily when we focus our attention on it in observation and
perception does not contain its deepest meaning. Man cannot conceive
this meaning from without. He must produce it.
Schelling was especially gifted for this kind of creation. With him,
all spiritual energies tended toward the imagination. His mind was
inventive without compare. His imagination did not produce pictures as
the artistic imagination does, but rather concepts and ideas. Through
this disposition of mind he was well-suited to continue along Fichte's
path of thought. Fichte did not have this productive imagination. In
his search for truth he had penetrated as far as to the center of
man's soul, the ego. If this center is to become the
nucleus for the world conception, then a thinker who holds this view
must also be capable of arriving at thoughts whose content are
saturated with world and life as he proceeds from the ego
as a vantage point. This can only be done by means of the power of
imagination, and this power was not at Fichte's disposal. For this
reason, he was really limited in his philosophical position all his
life to directing attention to the ego and to pointing out
that it has to gain a content in thoughts. He, himself, had been
unable to supply it with such a content, which can be learned clearly
from the lectures he gave in 1813 at the University of Berlin on the
Doctrine of Science (Posthumous Works, Vol. 1). For those who
want to arrive at a world conception, he there demands a
completely new inner sense organ, which for the ordinary man does not
exist at all. But Fichte does not go beyond this postulate. He
fails to develop what such an organ is to perceive. Schelling saw the
result of this higher sense in the thoughts that his imagination
produced in his soul, and he calls this intellectual
imagination (intellectuelle Anschauung). For him, then,
who saw a product created by the spirit in the spirit's
statement about nature, the following question became urgent. How can
what springs from the spirit be the pattern of the law that rules in
the real world, holding sway in real nature? With sharp words
Schelling turns against those who believe that we merely
project our ideas into nature, because they have no
inkling of what nature is and must be for us. . . . For we are not
satisfied to have nature accidentally (through the intermediary
function of a third element, for instance) correspond to the laws of
our spirit. We insist that nature itself necessarily and fundamentally
should not only express, but realize, the laws of our spirit and that
it should only then be, and be called, nature if it did just this. . .
. Nature is to be the visible spirit: spirit the invisible nature.
At this point then, at the point of the absolute identity of the
spirit in us and of nature outside us, the problem must
be solved as to how a nature outside ourselves should be
possible.
Nature and spirit, then, are not two different entities at all but one
and the same being in two different forms. The real meaning of
Schelling concerning this unity of nature and spirit has rarely been
correctly grasped. It is necessary to immerse oneself completely into
his mode of conception if one wants to avoid seeing in it nothing but
a triviality or an absurdity. To clarify this mode of conception one
can point to a sentence in Schelling's book, On the World Soul,
in which he expresses himself on the nature of gravity. Many
people find a difficulty in understanding this concept because it
implies a so-called action in distance. The sun attracts
the earth in spite of the fact that there is nothing between the sun
and earth to act as intermediary. One is to think that the sun extends
its sphere of activity through space to places where it is not
present. Those who live in coarse, sensual perceptions see a
difficulty in such a thought. How can a body act in a place
where it is not? Schelling reverses this thought process. He
says, It is true that a body acts only where it is,
but it is just as true that it is only where it
acts. If we see that the sun affects the earth through
the force of attraction, then it follows from this fact that it
extends its being as far as our earth and that we have no right to
limit its existence exclusively to the place in which it acts through
its being visible. The sun transcends the limits where it is visible
with its being. Only a part of it can be seen; the other part reveals
itself through the attraction. We must also think of the relation of
spirit and nature in approximately this manner. The spirit is not
merely where it is perceived; it is also where it perceives. Its being
extends as far as to the most distant places where objects can still
be observed. It embraces and permeates all nature that it knows. When
the spirit thinks the law of an external process, this process does
not remain outside the spirit. The latter does not merely receive a
mirror picture, but extends its essence into a process. The spirit
permeates the process and, in finding the law of the process, it is
not the spirit in its isolated brain corner that proclaims this law;
it is the law of the process that expresses itself. The spirit has
moved to the place where the law is active. Without the spirit's
attention the law would also have been active but it would not have
been expressed. When the spirit submerges into the process, as it
were, the law is then, in addition to being active in nature,
expressed in conceptual form. It is only when the spirit withdraws its
attention from nature and contemplates its own being that the
impression arises that the spirit exists in separation from nature, in
the same way that the sun's existence appears to the eye as being
limited within a certain space when one disregards the fact that it
also has its being where it works through attraction. Therefore, if I,
within my spirit, cause ideas to arise in which laws of nature are
expressed, the two statements, I produce nature, and
nature produces itself within me, are equally true.
Now there are two possible ways to describe the one being that is
spirit and nature at the same time. First, I can point out the natural
laws that are at work in reality; second, I can show how the spirit
proceeds to arrive at these laws. In both cases I am directed by the
same object. In the first instance, the law shows me its activity in
nature; in the second, the spirit shows me the procedure used to
represent the same law in the imagination. In the one case, I am
engaged in natural science; in the other, in spiritual science. How
these two belong together is described by Schelling in an attractive
fashion:
The necessary trend of all natural science is to proceed from nature
toward intelligence. This, and nothing else, is at the bottom of the
tendency to bring theory into natural phenomena. The highest
perfection of natural science would be the perfect transfiguration of
all laws of nature into laws of imagination and thinking. The
phenomena (the material element) must completely vanish and only the
laws (the formal element) must remain. This is the reason for the fact
that the more the law-structure in nature, itself, emerges, as if it
were breaking the crust, the more the covering element vanishes. The
phenomena themselves become more spiritual and finally disappear. The
phenomena of optics are nothing but a geometry, the lines of which are
drawn by the light, and this light, itself, is already of an ambiguous
materiality. In the phenomena of magnetism, all material traces have
already vanished. Of the phenomena of gravity, which, even according
to natural scientists, can only be understood as a direct spiritual
effect of action into distance, nothing is left but their law, the
application of which is the mechanism of the celestial motions on a
large scale. The completed theory of nature would be the one through
which the whole of nature would dissolve into intelligence. The
inanimate and consciousless products of nature are only unsuccessful
attempts of nature to reflect itself, and the so-called dead nature
is, in general, an immature intelligence, so that the intelligent
character shines through unconsciously in its phenomena. The highest
aim of nature to become completely objective to itself can be
reached by it only through the highest and last reflection, which is
man, or, more generally speaking, what we call reason, through which
nature returns in its own track and whereby it becomes evident that
nature originally is identical with what is known in us as the
intelligent and conscious element.
Schelling spun the facts of nature into an artful network of thought
in such a fashion that all of its phenomena stood as in an ideal,
harmonious organism before his creative imagination. He was inspired
by the feeling that the ideas that appear in his imagination are also
the creative forces of nature's process. Spiritual forces, then, are
the basis of nature, and what appears dead and lifeless to our eyes
has its origin in the spiritual. In turning our spirit to this, we
discover the ideas, the spiritual, in nature. Thus, for man, according
to Schelling, the things of nature are manifestations of the spirit.
The spirit conceals itself behind these manifestations as behind a
cover, so to speak. It shows itself in our own inner life in its right
form. In this way, man knows what is spirit, and he is therefore able
to find the spirit that is hidden in nature. The manner in which
Schelling has nature return as spirit in himself reminds one of what
Goethe believes is to be found in the perfect artist. The artist, in
Goethe's opinion, proceeds in the production of a work of art as
nature does in its creations. Therefore, we should observe in the
artist's creation the same process through which everything has come
into being that is spread out before man in nature. What nature
conceals from the outer eye is presented in perceptible form to man in
the process of artistic creation. Nature shows man only the finished
works; man must decipher from these works how it proceeded to produce
them. He is confronted with the creatures, not with the creator. In
the case of the artist, creation and creator are observed at the same
time. Schelling wants to penetrate through the products of nature to
nature's creative process. He places himself in the position of
creative nature and brings it into being within his soul as an artist
produces his work of art. What are, then, according to Schelling, the
thoughts that are contained in his world conception? They are the
ideas of the creative spirit of nature. What preceded the things and
what created them is what emerges in an individual human spirit as
thought. This thought is to its original real existence as a memory
picture of an experience is to the experience itself. Thereby, human
science becomes for Schelling a reminiscence of the spiritual
prototypes that were creatively active before the things existed. A
divine spirit created the world and at the end of the process it also
creates men in order to form in their souls as many tools through
which the spirit can, in recollection, become aware of its creative
activity. Schelling does not feel himself as an individual being at
all as he surrenders himself to the contemplation of the world
phenomena. He appears to himself as a part, a member of the creative
world forces. Not he thinks, but the spirit of the world forces
thinks in him. This spirit contemplates his own creative activity in
him.
Schelling sees a world creation on a small scale in the production of
a work of art. In the thinking contemplation of things, he sees a
reminiscence of the world creation on a large scale. In the panorama
of the world conception, the very ideas, which are the basis of things
and have produced them, appear in our spirit. Man disregards
everything in the world that the senses perceive in it and preserves
only what pure thinking provides. In the creation and enjoyment of a
work of art, the idea appears intimately permeated with elements that
are revealed through the senses. According to Schelling's view, then,
nature, art and world conception (philosophy) stand in the following
relation to one another. Nature presents the finished products; world
conception, the productive ideas; art combines both elements in
harmonious interaction. On the one side, artistic activity stands
halfway between creative nature, which produces without being aware of
the ideas on the basis of which it creates, and, on the other, the
thinking spirit, which knows these ideas without being able at the
same time to create things with their help. Schelling expresses this
with the words:
The ideal world of art and the real world of objects are therefore
products of one and the same activity. The concurrence of both (the
conscious and the unconscious) without consciousness leads to
the real world, with consciousness to the esthetic world. The
objective world is only the more primitive, still unconscious poem of
the spirit, the general organon of philosophy, and the philosophy
of art is the crowning piece of its entire structure.
The spiritual activities of man, his thinking contemplation and his
artistic creation, appear to Schelling not merely as the separate
accomplishments of the individual person, but, if they are understood
in their highest significance, they are at the same time the
achievement of the supreme being, the world spirit. In truly
dithyrambic words, Schelling depicts the feeling that emerges in the
soul when it becomes aware of the fact that its life is not merely an
individual life limited to a point of the universe, but that its
activity is one of general spirituality. When the soul says, I
know; I am aware, then, in a higher sense, this means that the
world spirit remembers its action before the existence of things; when
the soul produces a work of art, it means that the world spirit
repeats, on a small scale, what that spirit accomplished on a large
scale at the creation of all nature.
The soul in man is not the principle of individuality, then, but that
through which he lifts himself above all selfhood, through which he
becomes capable of self-sacrifice, of selfless love, and, to crown it
all, of the contemplation and knowledge of the essence of things and
thereby of art. The soul is no longer occupied with matter, nor is it
engaged in any direct intercourse with matter, but it is alone with
spirit as the life of things. Even when appearing in the body, the
soul is nevertheless free from the body, the consciousness of which
in its most perfect formation merely hovers like a light dream by
which it is not disturbed. The soul is not a quality, nor faculty, nor
anything of that kind in particular. The soul does not know, but is
knowledge. The soul is not good, not beautiful in the way that
bodies also can be beautiful, but it is beauty itself. (On the
Relation of Fine Arts to Nature.)
Such a mode of conception is reminiscent of the German mysticism that
had a representative in Jakob Boehme (1575 1624). In Munich, where
Schelling lived with short interruptions from 1806 1842, he enjoyed
the stimulating association with Franz Benedict Baader, whose
philosophical ideas moved completely in the direction of this older
doctrine. This association gave Schelling the occasion to penetrate
deeply into the thought world that depended entirely on a point of
view at which he had arrived in his own thinking. If one reads the
above quoted passage from the address, On the Relation of the Fine
Arts to Nature, which he gave at the Royal Academy of Science in
Munich in 1807, one is reminded of Jakob Boehme's view, As thou
beholdest the depth and the stars and the earth, thou seest thy God,
and in the same thou also livest and hast thy being, and the
same God ruleth thee also . . . thou art created out of this
God and thou livest in Him; all thy knowledge also standeth in
this God and when thou diest thou wilt be buried in this God.
As Schelling's thinking developed, his contemplation of the world
turned into the contemplation of God, or theosophy. In 1809, when he
published his Philosophical Inquiries Concerning the Nature of
Human Freedom and Topics Pertinent to This Question, he had
already taken his stand on the basis of such a theosophy. All
questions of world conception are now seen by him in a new light. If
all things are divine, how can there be evil in the world since God
can only be perfect goodness? If the soul is in God, how can it still
follow its selfish interests? If God is and acts within me, how can I
then still be called free, as I, in that case, do not at all act as a
self-dependent being?
Thus does Schelling attempt to answer these questions through
contemplation of God rather than through world contemplation. It would
be entirely incongruous to God if a world of beings were created that
he would continually have to lead and direct as helpless creatures.
God is perfect only if he can create a world that is equal to himself
in perfection. A god who can produce only what is less perfect than
he, himself, is imperfect himself. Therefore, God has created beings
in men who do not need his guidance, but are themselves free and
independent as he is. A being that has its origin in another being
does not have to be dependent on its originator, for it is not a
contradiction that the son of man is also a man. As the eye, which is
possible only in the whole structure of the organism, has nevertheless
an independent life of its own, so also the individual soul is, to be
sure, comprised in God, yet not directly activated by him as a part in
a machine.
God is not a God of the dead, but of the living. How he could find his
satisfaction in the most perfect machine is quite unintelligible. No
matter in what form one might think the succession of created beings
out of God, it can never be a mechanical succession, not a mere
causation or production so that the products would not be anything in
themselves. Nor could it be an emanation such that the emanating
entity would remain merely a part of the being it sprang from and
therefore would have no being of its own, nothing that would be
self-dependent. The sequence of things out of God is a self-revelation
of God. God, however, can only become revealed to himself in an
element similar to him, in beings that are free and act out of their
own initiative, for whose existence there is no ground but God but who
are themselves like God.
If God were a God of the dead and all world phenomena merely like a
mechanism, the individual processes of which could be derived from him
as their cause and mover, then it would only be necessary to describe
God and everything would be comprehended thereby. Out of God one would
be able to understand all things and their activity, but this is not
the case. The divine world has self-dependence. God created it, but it
has its own being. Thus, it is indeed divine, but the divine appears
in an entity that is independent of God; it appears in a non-divine
element. As light is born out of darkness, so the divine world is born
out of non-divine existence, and from this non-divine element springs
evil, selfishness. God thus has not all beings in his power. He can
give them the light, but they, themselves, emerge from the dark night.
They are the sons of this night, and God has no power over whatever is
darkness in them. They must work their way through the night into the
light. This is their freedom. One can also say that the world is God's
creation out of the ungodly. The ungodly, therefore, is the first, and
the godly the second.
Schelling started out by searching for the ideas in all things, that
is to say, by searching for what is divine in them. In this way, the
whole world was transformed into a manifestation of God for him. He
then had to proceed from God to the ungodly in order to comprehend the
imperfect, the evil, the selfish. Now the whole process of world
evolution became a continuous conquest of the ungodly by the godly for
him. The individual man has his origin in the ungodly. He works his
way out of this element into the divine. This process from the ungodly
to the godly was originally the dominating element in the world. In
antiquity men surrendered to their natures. They acted naively out of
selfishness. The Greek civilization stands on this ground. It was the
age in which man lived in harmony with nature, or, as Schiller
expresses it in his essay, On Naive and Sentimental Poetry,
man, himself, was nature and therefore did not seek nature. With
the rise of Christianity, this state of innocence of humanity
vanishes. Mere nature is considered as ungodly, as evil, and is seen
as the opposite of the divine, the good. Christ appears to let the
light of the divine shine in the darkness of the ungodly. This is the
moment when the earth becomes waste and void for the second
time, the moment of birth of the higher light of the
spirit, which was from the beginning of the world, but was not
comprehended by the darkness that operated by and for itself, and was
then still in its concealed and limited manifestation. It appears in
order to oppose the personal and spiritual evil, also in personal and
human shape, and as mediator in order to restore again the connection
of creation and God on the highest level. For only the personal can
heal the personal, and God must become man to enable man to come to
God.
Spinozism is a world conception that seeks the ground of all
world events in God, and derives all processes according to external
necessary laws from this ground, just as the mathematical truths are
derived from the axioms. Schelling considers such a world conception
insufficient. Like Spinoza, he also believes that all things are in
God, but according to his opinion, they are not determined only by
the lifelessness of his system, the soullessness of its form,
the poverty of its concepts and expressions, the inexorable harshness
of its statements that tallies perfectly with its abstract mode of
contemplation. Schelling, therefore, does find Spinoza's
mechanical view of nature perfectly consistent, but
nature, itself, does not show us this consistency.
All that nature tells us is that it does not exist as a result of a
geometric necessity. There is in it, not clear, pure reason, but
personality and spirit; otherwise, the geometric intellect, which has
ruled so long, ought to have penetrated it long ago. Intellect would
necessarily have realized its idol of general and eternal laws of
nature to a far greater extent, whereas it has everyday to acknowledge
nature's irrational relation to itself more and more.
As man is not merely intellect and reason but unites still other
faculties and forces within himself, so, according to Schelling, is
this also the case with the divine supreme being. A God who is clear,
pure reason seems like personified mathematics. A God, however, who
cannot proceed according to pure reason with his world creation but
continuously has to struggle against the ungodly, can be regarded as
a wholly personal living being. His life has the greatest
analogy with the human life. As man attempts to overcome the imperfect
within himself as he strives toward his ideal of perfection, so such a
God is conceived as an eternally struggling God whose activity is the
progressive conquest of the ungodly. Schelling compares Spinoza's God
to the oldest pictures of divinities, who appeared the more
mysterious the less individually-living features spoke out of
them. Schelling endows his God with more and more individualized
traits. He depicts him as a human being when he says, If we
consider what is horrible in nature and the spirit-world, and how much
more a benevolent hand seems to cover it up for us, then we cannot
doubt that the deity is reigning over a world of horror, and that God
could be called the horrible, the terrible God, not merely
figuratively but literally.
Schelling could no longer look upon a God like this in the same way in
which Spinoza had regarded his God. A God who orders everything
according to the laws of reason can also be understood through reason.
A personal God, as Schelling conceived him in his later life, is
incalculable, for he does not act according to reason alone. In a
mathematical problem we can predetermine the result through mere
thinking; with an acting human being this is not possible. With him,
we have to wait and see what action he will decide upon in a given
moment. Experience must be added to reason. A pure rational science
is, therefore, insufficient for Schelling for a conception of world
and God. In the later period of his world conception, he calls all
knowledge that is derived from reason a negative knowledge that has to
be supplemented by a positive knowledge. Whoever wants to know the
living God must not merely depend on the necessary conclusions of
reason; he must plunge into the life of God with his whole personal
being. He will then experience what no conclusion, no pure
reason can give him. The world is not a necessary effect of the divine
cause, but a free action of the personal God. What Schelling believed
he had reached, not by the cognitive process of the method of
reason, but by intuition as the free incalculable acts of
God, he has presented in his Philosophy of Revelation and
Philosophy of Mythology. He used the content of these two works
as the basis of the lectures he gave at the University of Berlin after
he had been called to the Prussian capital by Frederic Wilhelm IV.
They were published only after Schelling's death in 1854.
With views of this kind, Schelling shows himself to be the boldest and
most courageous of the group of philosophers who were stimulated to
develop an idealistic world conception by Kant. Under Kant's
influence, the attempt to philosophize about things that transcended
thinking and observation was abandoned. One tried to be satisfied with
staying within the limits of observation and thinking. Where Kant,
however, had concluded from the necessity of such a resignation that
no knowledge of transcendent things was possible, the post-Kantians
declared that as observation and thinking do not point at a
transcendent divine element, they are this divine element
themselves. Among those who took this position, Schelling was the most
forceful. Fichte had taken everything into the ego; Schelling had
spread this ego over everything. What he meant to show was not, as
Fichte did, that the ego was everything, but that everything was ego.
Schelling had the courage to declare not only the ego's content of
ideas as divine, but the whole human spirit-personality. He not only
elevated the human reason into a godly reason, but he made the human
life content into the godly personal entity. A world explanation that
proceeds from man and thinks of the course of the whole world as
having as its ground an entity that directs its course in the same way
as man directs his actions, is called anthropomorphism. Anyone
who considers events as being dependent on a general world reason,
explains the world anthropomorphically, for this general world
reason is nothing but the human reason made into this general reason.
When Goethe says, Man never understands how anthropomorphic he
is, he has in mind the fact that our simplest statements
concerning nature contain hidden anthropomorphisms. When we say a body
rolls on because another body pushed it, we form such a conception
from our own experience. We push a body and it rolls on.
When we now see that a ball moves against another ball that thereupon
rolls on, we form the conception that the first ball pushed the
second, using the analogy of the effect we ourselves exert. Haeckel
observes that the anthropomorphic dogma compares God's creation
and rule of the world with the artful creation of an ingenious
technician or engineer, or with the government of a wise ruler. God,
the Lord, as creator, preserver and ruler of the world is, in all his
thinking and doing, always conceived as similar to a human
being.
Schelling had the courage of the most consistent anthropomorphism. He
finally declared man, with all his life-content, as divinity, and
since a part of this life-content is not only the reasonable but the
unreasonable as well, he had the possibility of explaining also the
unreasonable in the world. To this end, however, he had to supplement
the view of reason by another view that does not have its source in
thinking. This higher view, according to his opinion, he called
"positive philosophy.
It is the free philosophy in the proper sense of the word;
whoever does not want it, may leave it. I put it to the free choice of
everybody. I only say that if, for instance, somebody wants to get at
the real process, a free world creation, etc., he can have all this
only by means of such a philosophy. If he is satisfied with a rational
philosophy and has no need beyond it, he may continue holding this
position, only he must give up his claim to possess with and in a
rational philosophy what the latter simply cannot supply because of
its very nature, namely, the real God, the real process and a free
relation between God and world.
The negative philosophy will remain the preferred philosophy for
the school, the positive philosophy, that for life. Only if both of
them are united will the complete consecration be obtained that can be
demanded of philosophy. As is well-known in the Eleusinian mysteries,
the minor mysteries were distinguished from the major ones and the
former were considered as a prerequisite stage of the latter . . . The
positive philosophy is the necessary consequence of the correctly
understood negative one and thus one may indeed say that in the
negative philosophy are celebrated the minor mysteries of philosophy,
in the positive philosophy, the major ones.
If the inner life is declared to be the divine life, then it appears
to be an inconsistency to limit this distinction to a part of this
inner life. Schelling is not guilty of this inconsistency. The moment
he declared that to explain nature is to create nature, he set the
direction for all his life conception. If thinking contemplation of
nature is a repetition of nature's creation, then the fundamental
character of this creation must also correspond to that of human
action; it must be an act of freedom, not one of geometric necessity.
We cannot know a free creation through the laws of reason; it must
reveal itself through other means.
The individual human personality lives and has its being in and
through the ground of the world, which is spirit. Nevertheless, man is
in possession of his full freedom and self-dependence. Schelling
considered this conception as one of the most important in his whole
philosophy. Because of it, he thought he could consider his
idealistic trend of ideas as a progress from earlier views since
those earlier views thought the individual to be completely determined
by the world spirit when they considered it rooted in it, and thereby
robbed it of its freedom and self-dependence.
For until the discovery of idealism, the real concept of freedom was
lacking in all systems, in that of Leibniz as well as in that of
Spinoza. A freedom that many of us had conceived and even boasted of
because of the vivid inner experience it touched on, namely, one that
is to consist merely in the domination of the intelligent principle
over the forces of sensuality and desire, such a freedom could be
derived from Spinoza's presupposition, not merely as a last resort,
but with clarity and the greatest of ease.
A man who had only this kind of freedom in mind and who, with the aid
of thoughts that had been borrowed from Spinozism, attempted a
reconciliation of the religious consciousness with a thoughtful world
contemplation, of theology and philosophy, was Schelling's
contemporary, Friedrich Daniel Ernst Schleiermacher (1768
1834). In his speeches on Religion Addressed to the Educated Among
Its Scorners (1799), he exclaimed, Sacrifice with me in
reverence to the spirit of the saintly departed Spinoza! The lofty
world spirit filled him; the infinite was his beginning and end; the
universe his only and eternal love. He reflected himself in holy
innocence and deep humility in the eternal world, and could observe
how he, in turn, was the world's most graceful mirror.
Freedom for Schleiermacher is not the ability of a being to decide
itself, in complete independence, on its life's own aim and direction.
It is, for him, only a development out of oneself. But a
being can very well develop out of itself and yet be unfree in a
higher sense. If the supreme being of the world has planted a definite
seed into the separate individuality that is brought to maturity by
him, then the course of life of the individual is precisely
predetermined but nevertheless develops out of itself. A freedom of
this kind, as Schleiermacher thinks of it, is readily thinkable in a
necessary world order in which everything occurs according to a strict
mathematical necessity. For this reason, it is possible for him to
maintain that the plant also has its freedom.
Because Schleiermacher knew of a freedom only in this sense, he
could also seek the origin of religion in the most unfree feeling, in
the feeling of absolute dependence. Man feels that he
must rest his existence on a being other than himself, on God. His
religious consciousness is rooted in this feeling. A feeling is always
something that must be linked to something else. It has only a derived
existence. The thought, the idea, have so distinctly a self-dependent
existence that Schelling can say of them, Thus thoughts, to be
sure, are produced by the soul, but the produced thought is an
independent power continuing its own action by itself, and indeed
growing within the soul to the extent that it conquers and subdues its
own mother. Whoever, therefore, attempts to grasp the supreme
being in the form of thoughts, receives this being and holds it as a
self-dependent power within himself. This power can then be
followed by a feeling, just as the conception of a beautiful
work of art is followed by a certain feeling of satisfaction.
Schleiermacher, however, does not mean to seize the object of
religion, but only the religious feeling. He leaves the object,
God, entirely indefinite. Man feels himself as dependent, but he does
not know the being on which he depends. All concepts that we form of
the deity are inadequate to the lofty character of this being. For
this reason, Schleiermacher avoids going into any definite concepts
concerning the deity. The most indefinite, the emptiest conception, is
the one he likes best. The ancients experienced religion when
they considered every characteristic form of life throughout the world
to be the work of a deity. They had absorbed the peculiar form of
activity of the universe as a definite feeling and designated it as
such. This is why the subtle words that Schleiermacher uttered
concerning the essence of immortality are indefinite:
The aim and character of a religious life is not an immortality that
is outside of time, or behind time, or else merely after this
time, but one that is still in time. It is the immortality
that we can already have here in this temporal life and that is a
problem, the solution of which continually engages us. To become one
with the infinite in the midst of the finite, and to be eternal in
every moment, is the immortality of religion.
Had Schelling said this, it would have been possible to connect it
with a definite conception. It would then mean, Man produces the
thought of God. This would then be God's memory of his own being. The
infinite would be brought to life in the individual person. It would
be present in the finite. But as Schleiermacher writes those
sentences without Schelling's foundations, they do no more than create
a nebulous atmosphere. What they express is the dim feeling that man
depends on something infinite. It is the theology in Schleiermacher
that prevents him from proceeding to definite conceptions concerning
the ground of the world. He would like to lift religious feeling,
piety, to a higher level, for he is a personality with rare depth of
soul. He demands dignity for true religious devotion. Everything that
he said about this feeling is of noble character. He defended the
moral attitude that is taken in Schlegel's Lucinde, which
springs purely out of the individual's own arbitrary free choice and
goes beyond all limits of traditional social conceptions. He could do
so because he was convinced that a man can be genuinely religious even
if he is venturesome in the field of morality. He could say,
There is no healthy feeling that is not pious.
Schleiermacher did understand religious feeling. He was
well-acquainted with the feeling that Goethe, in his later age,
expressed in his poem, Trilogy of Passion:
From our heart's pureness springs a yearning tender
Unto an unknown Being, lofty, blameless,
In gratefulness unchallenged to surrender,
Unriddling for ourselves the Ever-Nameless
In pious awe
Because he felt this religious feeling deeply, he also knew how to
describe the inner religious life. He did not attempt to know
the object of this devotion but left it to be done by the various
kinds of theology, each in its own fashion. What he intended to
delineate was the realm of religious experience that is independent of
a knowledge of God. In this sense, Schleiermacher was a peacemaker
between belief and knowledge.
In most recent times religion has increasingly contracted the
developed extent of its content and withdrawn into the intensive life
of religious fervor or feeling and often, indeed, in a
fashion that manifests a thin and meager content. Hegel wrote
these words in the preface of the second edition of his
Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1827). He continued
by saying:
As long as religion still has a creed, a doctrine, a dogmatic system,
it has something that philosophy can make its concern and use to join
hands with religion. This fact, however, must not be approached by the
inferior, dividing intellect through which modern religion is blinded.
It considers the realms of philosophy and religion as being mutually
exclusive and in separating them in this way assumes that they can
only be linked together externally. The real relation, and this is
implied also in the previous statement, is such that religion can, to
be sure, be without philosophy. Philosophy, however, cannot be without
religion, but comprises it within its own realm. The true religion,
the religion of the spirit, must have such a credo, must have a
content. The spirit is essentially consciousness of content
that has become objective. As feeling, it is the nonobjective content
itself and only the lowest stage of consciousness, and, indeed,
of the very form of soul life that man has in common with the animals.
It is thinking only that makes the spirit out of the soul, the soul
with which the animal also is gifted. Philosophy is only a
consciousness of this content, of the spirit and of its truth. It is
consciousness of man's essential nature that distinguishes him from
the animal and makes him capable of religion.
The whole spiritual physiognomy of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel
(1770 1831) becomes apparent when we hear words like these from
him, through which he wanted to express clearly and poignantly that he
regarded thinking that is conscious of itself as the highest
activity of man, as the force through which alone man can gain a
position with respect to the ultimate questions. The feeling of
dependence, which was considered by Schleiermacher as the originator
of religious experience, was declared to be characteristically the
function of the animal's life by Hegel. He stated paradoxically that
if the feeling of dependence were to constitute the essence of
Christianity, then the dog would be the best Christian. Hegel is a
personality who lives completely in the element of thought.
Because man is a thinking being, common sense, no more than
philosophy, will ever relinquish its prerogative to rise from the
empirical world conception to God. This elevation has as its
prerequisite the world contemplation of thinking, not merely that
of the sensual, animal consciousness.
Hegel makes into the content of his world conception what can be
obtained by self-conscious thinking. For what man finds in any other
way can be nothing but a preparatory stage of a world conception.
The elevation of thinking above the sensual, its transcendence
from the finite to the infinite, the leap into the
supersensible that is taken with an abrupt termination of sensual
content all this is thinking itself; this transition itself is
thinking. When such a transition is not to be made, it means
that no thinking is taking place. In fact, animals do not go beyond
sensual perception and immediate impression, and do not make this
leap. For this reason, they have no religion.
What man can extract from things through thinking is the highest
element that exists in them and for him. Only this element can he
recognize as their essence. Thought is, therefore, the essence of
things for Hegel. All perceptual imagination, all scientific
observation of the world and its events do, finally, result in man's
production of thoughts concerning the connection of things.
Hegel's work now proceeds from the point where perceptual imagination
and scientific observation have reached their destination: With
thought as it lives in self-consciousness. The scientific
observer looks at nature; Hegel observes what the scientific observer
states about nature. The observer attempts to reduce the variety of
natural phenomena to a unity. He explains one process through the
other. He strives for order, for organic systematic simplicity in the
totality of the things that are presented to the senses in chaotic
multiplicity. Hegel searches for systematic order and harmonious
simplicity in the results of the scientific investigator. He adds to
the science of nature a science of the thoughts about nature. All
thoughts that can be produced about the world form, in a natural way,
a uniform totality. The scientific observer gains his thoughts from
being confronted with the individual things. This is why the thoughts
themselves appear in his mind also, at first individually, one beside
another. If we consider them now side by side, they become joined
together into a totality in which every individual thought forms an
organic link. Hegel means to give this totality of thoughts in his
philosophy. No more than the natural scientist, who wants to determine
the laws of the astronomical universe, believes that he can construct
the starry heavens out of these laws, does Hegel, who seeks the
law-ordered connections within the thought world, believe he can
derive from these thoughts any laws of natural science that can only,
be determined through empirical observation. The statement, repeated
time and again, that it was Hegel's intention to exhaust the full and
unlimited knowledge of the whole universe through pure thinking is
based on nothing more than a naive misunderstanding of his view. He
has expressed it distinctly enough: To comprehend what is,
is the task of philosophy, for what is reasonable is real, and
what is real is reasonable. . . . When philosophy paints its
picture gray on gray, a figure of life has become old. . . . Minerva's
owl begins its fight only as the twilight of nightfall sets
in.
From these words it should be apparent that the factual knowledge must
already be there when the thinker arrives to see them in a new light
from his viewpoint. One should not demand of Hegel that he derive new
natural laws from pure thought, for he had not intended to do this at
all. What he had set out to do was to spread philosophical light over
the sum total of natural laws that existed in his time. Nobody demands
of a natural scientist that he create the starry sky, although in his
research he is concerned with the firmament. Hegel's views, however,
are declared to be fruitless because he thought about the laws of
nature and did not create these laws at the same time.
What man finally arrives at as he ponders over things is their
essence. It is the foundation of things. What man receives as his
highest insight is at the same time the deepest nature of things. The
thought that lives in man is, therefore, also the objective
content of the world. One can say that the thought is at first in the
world in an unconscious form. It is then received by the human spirit.
It becomes apparent to itself in the human spirit. Just as man, in
directing his attention into nature, finally finds the thought that
makes the phenomena comprehensible, so he also finds thought within
himself, as he turns his attention inward. As the essence of nature is
thought, so also man's own essence is thought. In the human
self-consciousness, therefore, thought contemplates itself. The
essence of the world arrives at its own awareness. In the other
creatures of nature thought is active, but this activity is not
directed toward itself but toward something other than itself. Nature,
then, does contain thought, but in thinking, man's thought is not
merely contained; it is here not merely active, but is directed toward
itself. In external nature, thought, to be sure, also unfolds life,
but there it only flows into something else; in man, it lives in
itself. In this manner the whole process of the world appears to Hegel
as thought process, and all occurrences in this process are
represented as preparatory phases for the highest event that there is:
The thoughtful comprehension of thought itself. This event takes place
in the human self-consciousness. Thought then works its way
progressively through until it reaches its highest form of
manifestation in which it comprehends itself.
Thus, in observing any thing or process of reality, one always sees a
definite phase of development of thought in this thing or
process. The world process is the progressive evolution of thought.
All phases except the highest contain within themselves a
self-contradiction. Thought is in them, but they contain more
than it reveals at such a lower stage. For this reason,, it overcomes
the contradictory form of its manifestation and speeds on toward a
higher one that is more appropriate. The contradiction then is the
motor that drives the thought development ahead. As the natural
scientist thoughtfully observes things, he forms concepts of them that
have this contradiction within themselves. When the philosophical
thinker thereupon takes up these thoughts that are gained from the
observation of nature, he finds them to be self-contradictory forms.
But it is this very contradiction that makes it possible to develop a
complete thought structure out of the individual thoughts. The thinker
looks for the contradictory element in a thought; this element is
contradictory because it points toward a higher stage of its
development. Through the contradiction contained in it, every thought
points to another thought toward which it presses on in the course of
its development. Thus, the philosopher can begin with the simplest
thought that is bare of all content, that is, with the abstract
thought of being. From this thought he is driven by the contradiction
contained therein toward a second phase that is higher and less
contradictory, etc., until he arrives at the highest stage, at thought
living within itself, which is the highest manifestation of the
spirit.
Hegel lends expression to the fundamental character of the evolution
of modern world conception. The Greek spirit knows thought as
perception; the modern spirit knows it as the self-engendered product
of the soul. In presenting his world conception, Hegel turns to the
creations of self-consciousness. He starts out by dealing only with
the self-consciousness and its products, but then he proceeds to
follow the activity of the self-consciousness into the phase in which
it is aware of being united with the world spirit. The Greek thinker
contemplates the world, and his contemplation gives him
an insight into the nature of the world. The modern thinker, as
represented by Hegel, means to live with his inner experience in the
world's creative process. He wants to insert himself into it. He is
then convinced that he discovers himself in the world, and he listens
to what the spirit of the world reveals as its being while this very
being is present and alive in his self-consciousness. Hegel is in the
modern world what Plato was in the world of the Greeks. Plato lifted
his spirit-eye contemplatively to the world of ideas so as to catch
the mystery of the soul in this contemplation. Hegel has the soul
immerse itself in the world-spirit and unfold its inner life after
this immersion. So the soul lives as its own life what has its ground
in the world spirit into which it submerged.
Hegel thus seized the human spirit in its highest activity, that is,
in thinking, and then attempted to show the significance of this
highest activity within the entirety of the world. This activity
represents the event through which the universal essence, which is
poured out into the whole world, finds itself again. The highest
activities through which this self-finding is accomplished are art,
religion and philosophy. In the work of nature, thought is contained,
but here it is estranged from itself. It appears not in its own
original form. A real lion that we see is, indeed, nothing but the
incarnation of the thought, lion. We are, however, not
confronted here with the thought, lion, but with the corporeal being.
This being, itself, is not concerned with the thought. Only I, when I
want to comprehend it, search for the thought. A work of art that
depicts a lion represents outwardly the form that, in being confronted
with a real lion, I can only have as a thought-image. The
corporeal element is there in the work of art for the sole purpose of
allowing the thought to appear. Man creates works of art in order to
make outwardly visible that element of things that he can otherwise
only grasp in thoughts. In reality, thought can appear to itself in
its appropriate form only in the human self-consciousness. What really
appears only inwardly, man has imprinted into sense-perceived matter
in the work of art to give it an external expression. When Goethe
stood before the monuments of art of the Greeks, he felt impelled to
confess that here is necessity, here is God. In Hegel's
language, according to which God expresses himself in the thought
content of the world manifested in human self-consciousness, this
would mean: In the works of art man sees reflected the highest
revelations of the world in which he can really participate only
within his own spirit. Philosophy contains thought in its perfectly
pure form, in its original nature. The highest form of manifestation
of which the divine substance is capable, the world of thought, is
contained in philosophy. In Hegel's sense, one can say the whole world
is divine, that is to say, permeated by thought, but in philosophy the
divine appears directly in its godliness while in other
manifestations it takes on the form of the ungodly. Religion stands
halfway between art and philosophy. In it, thought does not as yet
live as pure thought but in the form of the picture, the symbol. This
is also the case with art, but there the picture is such that it is
borrowed from the external perception. The pictures of religion,
however, are spiritualized symbols.
Compared to these highest manifestations of thought, all other human
life expressions are merely imperfect preparatory stages. The entire
historical life of mankind is composed of such stages. In following
the external course of the events of history one will, therefore, find
much that does not correspond to pure thought, the object of reason.
In looking deeper, however, we see that in historical evolution the
thought of reason is nevertheless in the process of being realized.
This realization just proceeds in a manner that appears as ungodly on
the surface. On the whole, one can maintain the statement,
Everything real is reasonable. This is exactly the
decisive point, that thought, the historical world spirit, realizes
itself in the entirety of history. The individual person is merely a
tool for the realization of the purpose of this world spirit. Because
Hegel recognizes the highest essence of the world in thought,
he also demands of the individual that he subordinate himself to
the general thoughts that rule the world evolution.
The great men in history are those whose special personal purposes
contain the substantial element that is the will of the world spirit.
This content is their true power. It is also contained in the general
unconscious instincts of the people. They are inwardly driven to it
and have nothing further to fall back upon that would enable them to
resist the individual who has made the execution of such a purpose his
own interest. The people gather around his colors. He shows them and
brings into reality their own immanent purposes. If we appraise the
fate of these world-historical individuals, we must say that they have
had the good fortune to be the executive agent of a purpose that
represented a step in the progress of the general spirit. We can call
a stratagem or reason, the way in which reason employs
individuals as its tools, for it has them execute their own purposes
with all fury of passion, and in so doing, it not only remains
unharmed, but actually realizes itself. The particular is mostly
negligible in comparison with the general; the individuals are
sacrificed and abandoned. World history thus presents the spectacle of
struggling individuals and, in the field of the particular, everything
happens in an entirely natural fashion. Just as in the animal nature
the preservation of life is purpose and instinct of the individual
specimen, and just as general reason holds sway while the individual
drops out, in the same way things also happen in the spiritual world.
The passions work mutual destruction on each other. Reason alone
wakes, follows its purpose and prevails.
Man as an individual can seize the comprehensive spirit only in his
thinking. Only in the contemplation of the world is God entirely
present. When man acts, when he enters the active life, he becomes a
link and therefore can also participate only as a link in the complete
chain of reason.
Hegel's doctrine of state is also derived from thoughts of this kind.
Man is alone with his thinking; with his actions he is a link of the
community. The reasonable order of community, the thought by which it
is permeated, is the state. The individual person, according to
Hegel, is valuable only insofar as the general reason, thought,
appears within such a person, for thought is the essence of things. A
product of nature does not possess the power to bring thought in its
highest form into appearance; man has this power. He will, therefore,
fulfill his destination only if he makes himself a carrier of thought.
As the state is realized thought, and as the individual man is only a
member within its structure, it follows that man has to serve the
state and not the state, man.
If the state is confused with society, and if its end is then defined
as the security and protection of property and individual freedom,
then it follows that the interest of the individual as such is the
last purpose for which the two are associated, and from this again it
would follow that it is merely a matter of an arbitrary choice of the
individual to become a member of the state or not. The state has,
however, an entirely different relation toward the individual. As it
is objective spirit, the individual man himself has objectivity, truth
and morality only insofar as he is a member of it. The union as such
is the true content and purpose, and it is the destination of the
individuals to lead a generally valid life. Their subsequent
satisfaction, activity and behavior has this substantial element of
general validity as its basis and as its result.
What place is there for freedom in such a life-conception? The
concept of freedom through which the individual human being is granted
an absolute to determine aim and purpose of his own activity is not
admitted as valid by Hegel. For what could be the advantage if the
individual did not derive his aim from the reasonable world of
thoughts but made his decision in a completely arbitrary fashion?
This, according to Hegel, would really be absence of freedom. An
individual of this kind would not be in agreement with his own
essence; he would be imperfect. A perfect individual can only want to
realize his essential nature, and the ability to do this is his
freedom. This essential nature now is embodied in the state.
Therefore, if man acts according to the state, he acts in freedom.
The state, in and by itself, is the moral universe, the realization of
freedom, and it is reason's absolute purpose that freedom be real. The
state is the spirit that has a foothold in the world, whereas in
nature it realizes itself only in a self-estranged form as dormant
spirit. . . . The fact that the state exists testifies to God's walk
through the world. It has its ground in the power of reason that
causes its self-realization through the force of will.
Hegel is never concerned with things as such, but always with their
reasonable, thoughtful content. As he always searched for
thoughts in the field of world contemplation, so he also wanted to see
life directed from the viewpoint of thought. It is for this
reason that he fought against indefinite ideals of state and society
and made himself the champion of the order existing in reality.
Whoever dreams of an indefinite ideal for the future believes, in
Hegel's opinion, that the general reason has been waiting for him to
make his appearance. To such a person it is necessary to explain
particularly that reason is already contained in everything that is
real. He called Professor Fries, whose colleague he was in Jena and
whose successor he became later in Heidelberg, the General Field
Marshal of all shallowness because he had intended to form such
an ideal for the future out of the mush of his heart.
The comprehensive defense of the real and existing order has earned
Hegel strong reproaches even from those who were favorably inclined
toward the general trend of his ideas. One of Hegel's followers,
Johann Eduard Erdmann, writes in regard to this point:
The decided preponderance that Hegel's philosophy is granted in the
middle of the 1820's over all other contemporary systems has its cause
in the fact that the momentary calm that it established in the wake of
the wild struggles in the field of politics, religion and church
policy, correspond appropriately to a philosophy that has been called
in reprehension by its antagonists, and in praise by its friends
the philosophy of the restoration.
This name is justified to a much greater extent than its coiners had
realized.
One should not overlook the fact also that Hegel created, through his
sense of reality, a view that is in a high degree close and favorable
to life. Schelling had meant to provide a view of life in his
Philosophy of Revelation, but how foreign are the
conceptions of his contemplation of God to the immediately experienced
real life! A view of this kind can have its value, at most, in festive
moments of solitary contemplation when man withdraws from the bustle'
of everyday life to surrender to the mood of profound meditation; when
he is engaged, so to speak, not in the service of the world, but of
God. Hegel, however, had meant to impart to man the all-pervading
feeling that he serves the general divine principle also in his
everyday activities. For him, this principle extends, as it were, down
to the last detail of reality, while with Schelling it withdraws to
the highest regions of existence. Because Hegel loved reality
and life, he attempted to conceive it in its most reasonable form. He
wanted man to be guided by reason every step of his life. In the last
analysis he did not have a low estimation of the individual's value.
This can be seen from utterances like the following.
The richest and most concrete is the most subjective, and the
element that withdraws the most into profundity is the most powerful
and all-comprehensive. The highest and most pointed peak is the
pure personality, which alone through the absolute dialectic,
which is nature, encompasses everything within itself and at the same
time, because it develops to the highest stage of freedom and insists
on simplicity, which is the first immediacy and generality.
But in order to become pure personality the individual has
to permeate himself with the whole element of reason and to absorb it
into his self, for the pure personality, to be sure, is
the highest point that man can reach in his development, but man
cannot claim this stage as a mere gift of nature. If he has lifted
himself to this point, however, the following words of Hegel become
true:
That man knows of God is a communal knowledge in the meaning of the
ideal community, for man knows of God only insofar as God knows of
himself in man. This knowledge is self-consciousness of God, but also
a knowledge that God has of man; this knowledge that God has of man
is the knowledge that man has of God. The spirit of man, to know of
God, is only the spirit of God himself.
According to Hegel, only a man in whom this is realized deserves the
name of personality, for with him reason and individuality
coincide. He realizes God within himself for whom he supplies in his
consciousness the organ to contemplate himself. All thoughts would
remain abstract, unconscious, ideal forms if they did not obtain
living reality in man. Without man, God would not be there in his
highest perfection. He would be the incomplete basic substance of the
world. He would not know of himself. Hegel has presented this God
before his realization in life. The content of the presentation is
Hegel's Logic. It is a structure of lifeless, rigid, mute
thoughts. Hegel, himself, calls it the realm of shadows.
It is, as it were, to show God in his innermost, eternal essence
before the creation of nature and of the finite spirit. But as
self-contemplation necessarily belongs to the nature of God, the
content of the Logic is only the dead God who demands
existence. In reality, this realm of the pure abstract truth does not
occur anywhere. It is only our intellect that is capable of separating
it from living reality. According to Hegel, there is nowhere in
existence a completed first being, but there is only one in eternal
motion, in the process of continual becoming. This eternal
being is the eternally real truth in which the eternally active
reason is free for itself, and for which necessity, nature and history
only serve as forms of manifestation and as vessels of its
glory.
Hegel wanted to show how, in man, the world of thoughts comprehends
itself. He expressed in another form Goethe's conception:
When a man's healthy nature acts in its entirety, when he feels
himself in the world as in a great, beautiful. worthy and cherished
whole, when inner harmony fills him with pure and free delight, then
the universe, if it could become aware of itself, would rejoice as
having reached its destination and would admire the peak of its own
becoming and being.
Translated into Hegel's language, this means that when man experiences
his own being in his thinking, then this act has not merely an
individual personal significance, but a universal one. The nature of
the universe reaches its peak in man's self-knowledge; it arrives at
its completion without which it would remain a fragment.
In Hegel's conception of knowledge this is not understood as the
seizing of a content that, without the cognitive process, exists
somewhere ready-made in the world; it is not an activity that produces
copies of the real events. What is created in the act of
thinking cognition exists, according to Hegel, nowhere else in the
world but only in the act of cognition. As the plant produces a
blossom at a certain stage of development, so the universe produces
the content of human knowledge. Just as the blossom is not there
before its development, so the thought content of the world
does not exist before it appears in the human spirit. A world
conception in which the opinion is held that in the process of
knowledge only copies of an already existing content come into being,
makes man into a lazy spectator of the world, which would also be
completely there without him. Hegel, however, makes man into the
active co-agent of the world process, which would be lacking its peak
without him.
Grillparzer, in his way, characterized Hegel's opinion concerning the
relation of thinking and world in a significant epigram:
It may be that you teach us prophetically God's form of thinking. But
it's human form, friend, you have decidedly spoiled.
What the poet has in mind here in regard to human thinking is just the
thinking that presupposes that its content exists ready-made in the
world and means to do nothing more than to supply a copy of it. For
Hegel, this epigram contains no rebuke, for this thinking about
something else is, according to his view, not the highest, most
perfect thinking. In thinking about a thing of nature one searches for
a concept that agrees with an external object. One then
comprehends through the thought that is thus formed what the external
object is. One is then confronted with two different elements, that
is, with the thought and with the object. But if one intends to ascend
to the highest viewpoint, one must not hesitate to ask the question:
What is thought itself? For the solution of this problem, however,
there is again nothing but thought at our disposal. In the highest
form of cognition, then, thought comprehends itself. No longer does
the question of an agreement with something outside arise. Thought
deals exclusively with itself. This form of thinking that has no
support in any external object appears to Grillparzer as destructive
for the mode of thinking that supplies information concerning the
variety of things spread out in time and space, and belonging to both
the sensual and spiritual world of reality. But no more than the
painter destroys nature in reproducing its lines and color on canvas,
does the thinker destroy the ideas of nature as he expresses them in
their spiritually pure form. It is strange that one is inclined to see
in thinking an element that would be hostile to reality because it
abstracts from the profusion of the sensually presented content. Does
not the painter, in presenting in color, shade and line, abstract from
all other qualities of an object? Hegel suitably characterized all
such objections with his nice sense of humor. If the primal substance
whose activity pervades the world slips, and from the ground on
which it walks, falls into the water, it becomes a fish, an organic
entity, a living being. If it now slips and falls into the element of
pure thinking for even pure thinking they will not allow as
its proper element then it suddenly becomes something bad and
finite; of this one really ought to be ashamed to speak, and would be
if it were not officially necessary and because there is simply no use
denying that there is some such thing as logic. Water is such a cold
and miserable element; yet life nevertheless feels comfortably at home
in it. Should thinking be so much worse an element? Should the
absolute feel so uncomfortable and behave so badly in it?
It is entirely in Hegel's sense if one maintains that the first being
created the lower strata of nature and the human being as well. Having
arrived at this point, it has resigned and left to man the task to
create, as an addition to the external world and to himself, the
thoughts about the things. Thus, the original being, together with
the human being as a co-agent, create the entire content of the world.
Man is a fellow-creator of the world, not merely a lazy spectator
or cognitive ruminator of what would have its being just as well
without him.
What man is in regard to his innermost existence he is through nothing
else but himself. For this reason, Hegel considers freedom, not as a
divine gift that is laid into man's cradle to be held by him forever
after, but as a result toward which he progresses gradually in the
course of his development. From life in the external world, from the
stage in which he is satisfied in a purely sensual existence, he rises
to the comprehension of his spiritual nature, of his own inner world.
He thereby makes himself independent of the external world; he follows
his inner being. The spirit of a people contains natural necessity and
feels entirely dependent on what is moral public opinion in regard to
custom and tradition, quite apart from the individual human being. But
gradually the individual wrests himself loose from this world
of moral convictions that is thus laid down in the external world and
penetrates into his own inner life, recognizing that he can develop
moral convictions and standards out of his own spirit. Man lifts
himself up to the vantage point of the supreme being that rules within
him and is the source of his morality. For his moral commandment, he
no longer looks to the external world but within his own soul. He
makes himself dependent only on himself (paragraph 552 of Hegel's
Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences). This independence,
this freedom then is nothing that man possesses from the outset, but
it is acquired in the course of historical evolution. World
history is the progress of humanity in the consciousness of
freedom.
Since Hegel regards the highest manifestations of the human spirit as
processes in which the primal being of the world finds the completion
of its development, of its becoming, all other phenomena appear
to him as the preparatory stages of this highest peak; the final stage
appears as the aim and purpose toward which everything tends. This
conception of a purposiveness in the universe is different from the
one in which world creation and world government are thought to be
like the work of an ingenious technician or constructor of machines,
who has arranged all things according to useful purposes. A utility
doctrine of this kind was rigorously rejected by Goethe. On February
20th, 1831, he said to Eckermann (compare Conversations of Goethe
with Eckermann, Part II):
Man is inclined to carry his usual views from life also into science
and, in observing the various parts of an organic being, to inquire
after their purpose and use. This may go on for awhile and he may also
make progress in science for the time being, but he will come across
phenomena soon enough where such a narrow view will prove insufficient
and he will be entangled in nothing but contradictions if he does not
acquire a higher orientation. Such utilitarian teachers will say that
the bull has horns to defend itself with, but there I ask why the
sheep have none. Even when they have horns, why are they twisted
around the sheep's ears so that they cannot be of any use at all. It
is a different thing to say that the bull defends himself with his
horns because they are there. The question why is not
scientific at all. We fare a little better with the question how,
for if I ask the question, How does the bull have horns? I am
immediately led to the observation of his organization, and this shows
me at the same time why the lion has no horns and cannot have any.
Nevertheless, Goethe recognizes, in another sense, a purposeful
arrangement in all nature that finally reaches its aim in man and has
all its works so ordered, as it were, that he will fulfill his
destination in the end. In his essay on Winckelmann, he writes,
For to what avail is all expenditure and labor of suns and
planets and moons, of stars and galaxies, of comets and of nebulae,
and of completed and still growing worlds, if not at last a happy man
rejoices in his existence? Goethe is also convinced that the
nature of all world phenomena is brought to light as truth in and
through man (compare what is said
in Part 1 Chapter VI).
To comprehend how
everything in the world is so laid out that man has a worthy task and
is capable of carrying it out is the aim of this world conception.
What Hegel expresses at the end of his Philosophy of Nature
sounds like a philosophical justification of Goethe's words:
In the element of life nature has completed her course and has made
her peace as she turns into a higher phase of being. The spirit has
thus emerged from nature. The aim of nature is her own death, to break
through the crust of immediate sensual existence, to burn as a phoenix
in order to emerge from this external garment, rejuvenated as spirit.
Nature thus becomes estranged from herself in order that she may
recognize her own being, thereby bringing about a reconciliation with
herself. . . . The spirit therefore exists before nature as its
real purpose; nature originates from the spirit.
This world conception succeeded in placing man so high because it saw
realized in man what is the basis of the whole world, as the
fundamental force, the primal being. It prepares its realization
through the whole gradual progression of all other phenomena but is
fulfilled only in man. Goethe and Hegel agree perfectly in this
conception. What Goethe had derived from his contemplative
observation of nature and spirit, Hegel expresses through his
lucid pure thinking unfolding its life in self-consciousness.
The method by which Goethe explained certain natural processes
through the stages of their growth and development is applied by Hegel
to the whole cosmos. For an understanding of the plant organism Goethe
demanded:
Watch how the plant in its growth changes step by step and,
gradually led on, transforms from blossoms to fruits.
Hegel wants to comprehend all world phenomena in the gradual progress
of their development from the simplest dull activity of inert matter
to the height of the self-conscious spirit. In the self-conscious
spirit he sees the revelation of the primal substance of the world.
|