Reactionary World Conceptions
The bud vanishes in the breaking of the blossom, and one could
say that the former is contradicted by the latter. In the same way,
the fruit declares the blossom to be a false existence and replaces it
as its truth. These forms are not merely different from one another
but they crowd each other out as they are incompatible. Their Quid
nature makes them at once into moments of the organic whole in which
they not only do not contradict each other, but in which the one is as
necessary as the other, and it is only this equal necessity that
constitutes the life of the whole.
In these words of Hegel, the most significant traits of his mode of
conception are expressed. He believes that the things of reality carry
within themselves their own contradiction and that the incentive for
their growth, for the living process of their development, is given by
the fact that they continually attempt to overcome this contradiction.
The blossom would never become fruit if it were without contradiction.
It would have no reason to go beyond its unquestioned existence.
An exactly opposite intellectual conviction forms the point of
departure of Johann Friedrich Herbart (1776 1841). Hegel is a
sharp thinker, but at the same time a spirit with a great thirst for
reality. He would like to have only things that have absorbed the
rich, saturated content of the world into themselves. For this reason,
Hegel's thoughts must also be in an eternal flux, in a continuous
state of becoming, in a forward motion as full of contradictions as
reality itself. Herbart is a completely abstract thinker. He does not
attempt to penetrate into things but looks at them from the corner
into which he has withdrawn as an isolated thinker. The purely logical
thinker is disturbed by a contradiction. He demands clear concepts
that can exist side by side. One concept must not interfere with
another. The thinker sees himself in a strange situation because he is
confronted with reality that is full of contradictions, no matter what
he may undertake. The concepts that he can derive from this reality
are unsatisfactory to him. They offend his logical sense. This feeling
of dissatisfaction becomes the point of departure. Herbart feels that
if the reality that is spread out before his senses and before his
mind supplies him with contradictory concepts, then it cannot be the
true reality for which his thinking is striving. He derives his task
from this situation. The contradictory reality is not real being but
only appearance. In this view he follows Kant to a certain degree, but
while Kant declares true being unattainable to thinking cognition,
Herbart believes one penetrates from appearance to being by
transforming the contradictory concepts of appearance and changing
them into concepts that are free from contradictions. As smoke
indicates fire, so appearance points at a form of being as its ground.
If, through our logical thinking, we elaborate out of a contradictory
world picture given to us by our senses and our mind, one that is not
contradictory, then we gain from this uncontradictory world picture
what we are looking for. This world picture, to be sure, does not
appear in this form that is free from contradictions, but it
lies behind the apparent one as true reality. Herbart does not set out
to comprehend the directly given reality, but creates another reality
through which the former is to become explainable. He arrives in this
fashion at an abstract thought system that looks rather meager as
compared to the rich, full reality. The true reality cannot be a
unity, for a unity would have to contain within itself the infinite
variety of the real things and events. It must be a plurality of
simple entities, eternally equal to themselves, incapable of change
and development. Only a simple entity that unchangeably preserves its
qualities is free from contradictions. An entity in development is
something different in one moment from what it is in another, that is,
its qualities are contradictory at various times. The true world is,
therefore, a plurality of simple, never-changing entities, and what we
perceive are not these simple entities but their relations to one
another. These relations have nothing to do with the real being. If
one simple entity enters into a relationship with another, the two
entities are not changed thereby, but I do perceive the result of
their relationship. The reality we perceive directly is a sum of
relations between real entities. When one entity abandons its relation
to another and replaces it by a relationship with a third entity,
something happens without touching the being of the entities
themselves. It is this event that we perceive, namely, our apparent
contradictory reality. It is interesting to note how Herbart, on the
basis of this conception, forms his thoughts concerning the life of
the soul. The soul is, as are all other real entities, simple and
unchangeable in itself. This entity is now engaged in relations with
other beings. The expression of these relations is life in
thought-pictures. Everything that happens within us imagination,
feeling, will is an interplay between the soul and the rest of the
world of real entities. Thus, for Herbart, the soul life becomes the
appearance of relations into which the simple soul-entity enters with
the world. Herbart has a mathematical mind, and his whole world
conception is derived fundamentally from mathematical conceptions. A
number does not change when it becomes the link of an arithmetical
operation. Three remains three, whether it is added to four or
subtracted from seven. As the numbers have their place within the
mathematical operations, so do the individual entities within the
relationships that develop between them. For this reason, psychology
becomes an arithmetical operation for Herbart. He attempts to apply
mathematics to psychology. How the thought-images condition each
other, how they effect one another, what results they produce through
their coexistence are things calculated by Herbart. The
ego is not the spiritual entity that we lay hold of in our
self-consciousness, but it is the result of the cooperation of all
thought-pictures and thereby also nothing more than a sum, a last
expression of relationships. Of the simple entity, which is the basis
of our soul life, we know nothing, but its continual relation to other
entities is apparent to us. In this play of relations one
entity is entangled. This condition is expressed by the fact that
all these relationships are tending toward a center, and this tendency
expresses itself in the thought of the ego.
Herbart is, in another sense than Goethe, Schiller, Schelling, Fichte
and Hegel, a representative of the development of modern world
conception. Those thinkers attempt a representation of the
self-conscious soul in a world picture capable of containing this
self-conscious soul as an element. In so doing they become the
spokesmen for the spiritual impulse of their age. Herbart is
confronted with this impulse and he must admit the feeling that this
impulse is there. He attempts to understand it, but in the form of
thinking that he imagines to be the correct one, he finds no
possibility of penetrating into the life of the self-conscious being
of the soul. He remains outside of it. One can see in Herbart's world
conception what difficulties man's thinking encounters when it tries
to comprehend what it has essentially become in the course of
mankind's evolution. Compared to Hegel, Herbart appears like a thinker
who strives in vain for an aim at which Hegel believes actually to
have arrived. Herbart's thought constructions are an attempt to
outline as an external spectator what Hegel means to present through
the inner participation of thought. Thinkers like Herbart are also
significant for the characterization of the modern form of world
conception. They indicate the aim that is to be reached by the very
display of their insufficient means for the attainment of this aim.
The spiritual aim of the age motivates Herbart's struggle; his
intellectual energy is inadequate to understand and to express this
struggle sufficiently. The course of the philosophical evolution shows
that, besides the thinkers who move on the crest of the time-impulses,
there are also always some active ones who form world conceptions
through their failure to understand these impulses. Such world
conceptions may well be called reactionary.
Herbart reverts to the view of Leibniz. His simple soul entity is
unchangeable; it neither grows nor decays. It existed when this
apparent life contained within man's ego began, and will again
withdraw from these relations when this life ceases to continue
independently. Herbart arrives at his conception of God through his
world picture, which contains many simple entities that produce the
events through their relations. Within these processes we observe
purpose-directed order. But the relations could only be accidental and
chaotic if the entities, which, according to their own nature, would
have nothing in common, were left entirely to themselves. The fact
that they are teleologically ordered, therefore, points toward a wise
world ruler who directs their relations. No one is capable of
giving a close definition of deity, says Herbart. He condemns
the pretensions of the systems that speak of God as of an object
to be comprehended in sharply drawn contours by means of which we
would rise to a knowledge for which we are simply denied the
data.
Man's actions and artistic creations are completely without foundation
in this world picture. All possibility to fit them into this system is
lacking. For what could a relationship of simple entities that are
completely indifferent to all processes mean to the actions of man? So
Herbart is forced to look for independent tools both for ethics and
for esthetics. He believes he finds them in human feeling. When man
perceives things or events, he can associate the feeling of pleasure
or displeasure with them. We are pleased when we see man's will going
in a direction that is in agreement with his convictions. When we make
the opposite observation, the feeling of displeasure overcomes us.
Because of this feeling we call the agreement of conviction and will
good; the discord, we call morally reprehensible. A feeling of this
kind can be attached only to a relationship between moral
elements. The will as such is morally indifferent, as is also the
conviction. Only when the two meet does ethical pleasure or
displeasure emerge. Herbart calls a relation of moral elements a
practical idea. He enumerates five such practical-ethical ideas: The
idea of moral freedom, consisting of the agreement of will and moral
conviction; the idea of perfection that has its basis in the fact that
the strong pleases rather than the weak; the idea of right, which
springs from displeasure with antagonism; the idea of benevolence,
which expresses the pleasure that one feels as one furthers the will
of another person; the idea of retribution, which demands that all
good and evil that has originated in a person is to be compensated
again in the same person.
Herbart bases his ethics on a human feeling, on moral sentiment. He
separates it from the world conception that has to do with what is,
and transforms it into a number of postulates of what should
be. He combines it with esthetics and, indeed, makes it a part of
them. For the science of esthetics also contains postulates concerning
what is to be. It, too, deals with relations that are associated with
feelings. The individual color leaves us esthetically indifferent.
When one color is joined to another, this combination can be either
satisfactory or displeasing to us. What pleases in a combination is
beautiful; what displeases, is ugly. Robert Zimmermann (1824
1898) has ingeniously constructed a science of art on these
principles. Only a part of it, the part that considers those relations
of beauty that are concerned with the realm of action, is to be the
ethics or the science of the good. The significant writings of Robert
Zimmermann in the field of esthetics (science of art) show that even
attempts at philosophical formulations that do not reach the summit of
cultural impulses of a time can produce important stimulation's for
the development of the spirit.
Because of his mathematically inclined mind, Herbart successfully
investigated those processes of human soul life that really do go on
with a certain regularity in the same way with all human beings. These
processes will, of course, not prove to be the more intimate and
individually characteristic ones. What is original and characteristic
in each personality will be overlooked by such a mathematical
intellect, but a person of such a mentality will obtain a certain
insight into the average processes of the mind and, at the same time,
through his sure skill in handling the arithmetical calculations, will
control the measurement of the mental development. As the laws of
mechanics enable us to develop technical skills, so the laws of the
psychological processes make it possible for us to devise a technique
in education for the development of mental abilities. For this reason,
Herbart's work has become fruitful in the field of pedagogy. He has
found many followers among pedagogues, but not among them alone. This
seems at first sight hard to understand with regard to a world
conception offering a picture of meager, colorless generalities, but
it can be explained from the fact that it is just the people who feel
a certain need for a world conception who are easily attracted by such
general concepts that are rigidly linked together like terms of an
arithmetical operation. It is something fascinating to experience how
one thought is linked to the next as if it were through a
self-operative mechanical process, because this process awakens in the
observer a feeling of security. The mathematical sciences are so
highly appreciated because of this assurance. They unfold their
structure, so to speak, through their own force. They only have to be
supplied with the thought material and everything else can be left to
their logical necessity, which works automatically. In the progress of
Hegel's thinking, which is saturated with reality, the thinker
continually has to take the initiative. There is more warmth, more
direct life in this mode of thinking, but it also requires the
constant support of the soul forces. This is because it is reality in
this case that the thinker catches in his thoughts, an ever-flowing
reality that at every point shows its individual character and fights
against every logical rigidity. Hegel also had a great number of
pupils and followers, but they were much less faithful than those of
Herbart. As long as Hegel's powerful personality enlivened his
thoughts, they exerted their charm, and as long as his words were
heard under its spell, they carried great conviction. After Hegel's
death many of his pupils went their own paths. This is only natural,
for whoever is self-dependent will also shape his own attitude toward
reality in his own fashion. We observe a different process with
Herbart's pupils. They elaborate the master's doctrine, but they
continue the fundamental stock of his thoughts without change. A
thinker who finds his way into Hegel's mode of thinking penetrates
into the course of the world's development that is manifested in
innumerable evolutionary phases. The individual thinker, of course,
can be stimulated to follow this course of evolution, but he is free
to shape the various stages according to his own individual mode of
conception. In Herbart's case, however, we deal with a firmly
constructed thought system that commands confidence through the
solidity of its structure. One may reject it, but if one accepts it,
one will have to accept it in its original form. For the individual
personal element, which challenges and forces us to face the self of
another thinker with our own self, is lacking here.
Life is a miserable affair; I have decided to spend mine by
thinking about it. Arthur Schopenhauer (1788 1861)
spoke these words in a conversation with Wieland at the beginning of
his university years, and his world conception sprang from this mood.
Schopenhauer had experienced personal hardship and had observed the
sad lives of others when he decided upon concentrating on
philosophical thought as a new aim of life. The sudden death of his
father, caused by a fall from a storehouse, his bad experiences in his
career as a merchant, the sight of scenes of human miseries that he
witnessed as a' young man while traveling, and many other things of
similar kind had produced in him the wish, not so much to know the
world, but rather to procure for himself a means to endure it through
contemplation. He needed a world conception in order to calm his
gloomy disposition. When he began his university studies, the thoughts
that Kant, Fichte and Schelling introduced to the German philosophical
life were in full swing. Hegel's star was just then rising. In 1806 he
had published his first larger work, The Phenomenology of the
Spirit. In Goettingen, Schopenhauer heard the teachings of
Gottlob Ernst Schulze, the author of the book, Aenesidemus,
who was, to be sure, in a certain respect an opponent of Kant, but
who nevertheless drew the student's attention to Kant and Plato as the
two great spirits toward whom he would have to look. With fiery
enthusiasm Schopenhauer plunged into Kant's mode of conception. He
called the revolution that his study caused in his head a spiritual
rebirth. He found it even more satisfactory because he considered it
to be in agreement with the views of Plato, the other philosopher
Schulze had pointed out to him.
Plato had said, As long as we approach the things and events
merely through sensual perceptions, we are like men who are chained in
a dark cave in such a way that they cannot turn their heads;
therefore, they can only see, by means of the light of a fire burning
behind them, the shadows upon the opposite wall, the shadows of real
things that are carried between the fire and their backs, the shadows
of each other and of themselves. These shadows are to the real things
what the things of sensual perception are to the ideas, which
are the true reality. The things of the sensually perceptible world
come into existence and pass again, the ideas are eternal.
Did not Kant teach this, too? Is not the perceptible world only a
world of appearances for him also? To be sure, the sage from
Koenigsberg did not attribute this eternal reality to the ideas, but
with respect to the perception of the reality spread out in space and
time, Schopenhauer thought Plato and Kant to be in complete agreement.
Soon he also accepted this view as an irrevocable truth. He argued,
I have a knowledge of the things insofar as I see, hear, feel
them, etc., that is to say, insofar as I have them as a thought
picture in my mind's eye. An object then can be there for me only
by being represented to my mind as a thought image. Heaven, earth,
etc., are therefore my mind's imaginations, for the thing
in itself' that corresponds to them has become my mind's object only
by taking on the character of a thought representation.
Although Schopenhauer found everything that Kant stated concerning the
subjective character of the world of perception absolutely correct, he
was not at all satisfied with regard to Kant's remarks concerning the
thing in itself. Schulze had also been an opponent of Kant's view in
this respect. How can we know anything at all of a thing in
itself"? How can we even express a word about it if our knowledge
is completely limited to thought pictures of our mind, if the
thing in itself lies completely outside their realm?
Schopenhauer had to search for another path in order to come to the
thing in itself. In his search he was influenced by the
contemporary world conceptions more than he ever admitted. The element
that Schopenhauer added to the conviction that he had from Kant and
Plato as the thing in itself, we find also in Fichte,
whose lectures he had heard in 1811 in Berlin. We also find this
element in Schelling. Schopenhauer could hear the most mature form of
Fichte's views in Berlin. This last form is preserved in Fichte's
posthumous works. Fichte declared with great emphasis, while
Schopenhauer, according to his own admission, listened
attentively, that all being has its last roots in a universal
will. As soon as man discovers will in himself, he gains the
conviction that there is a world independent of himself as an
individual. Will is not a knowledge of the individual but a form of
real being. Fichte could also have called his world conception,
The World as Knowledge and Will. In Schelling's book,
Concerning the Nature of Human Freedom and Matters Connected with
This Problem, we actually find the sentences, In the last
and deepest analysis there is no other being than will. Will is
fundamental being and will alone can claim all its predicates: To be
without cause, eternal, independent of time, self-assertive. All
philosophy is striving for just this aim, to find this highest
expression.
That will is fundamental being becomes Schopenhauer's view also. When
knowledge is extinguished, will remains, for will also precedes
knowledge. Knowledge has its origin in my brain, says
Schopenhauer, but my brain must have been produced through an
active, creative force. Man is aware of such a creative energy in his
own will. Schopenhauer now attempts to prove that what is active
in all other things is also will. The will, therefore, is, as
the thing in itself, at the root of all reality that is
merely represented in the thought pictures of our mental life,
and we can have a knowledge of this thing in itself. It is
not, as Kant's thing in itself, beyond our perceptive
imagination but we experience its actuality within our own organism.
The development of modern world conception is progressive in
Schopenhauer insofar as he is the first thinker to make the attempt to
elevate one of the fundamental forces of the self-consciousness
to the general principle of the world. The active self-consciousness
contains the riddle of the age. Schopenhauer is incapable of finding a
world picture that contains the roots of self-consciousness.
Fichte, Schelling and Hegel had attempted to do that. Schopenhauer
takes one force of the self-consciousness, will, and
claims that this element is not merely in the human soul but in the
whole world. Thus, for him, man is not rooted with his full
self-consciousness in the world's foundation, but at least with a part
of it, with his will. Schopenhauer thus shows himself to be one of
those representatives of the evolution of modern world conception who
can only partially encompass the fundamental riddle of the time within
their consciousness.
Goethe also had a profound influence on Schopenhauer. From the autumn
of 1813 until the following spring, the young Schopenhauer enjoyed the
company of the poet. Goethe introduced him personally to his doctrine
of colors. Goethe's mode of conception agreed completely with the view
that Schopenhauer had developed concerning the behavior of our sense
organs and our mind in the process of perception of things and events.
Goethe had undertaken careful and intensive investigations concerning
the perceptions of the eye and phenomena of light and colors, and had
elaborated their results in his work, Concerning the Doctrine of
Colors. He had arrived at results that differed from those of
Newton, the founder of the modern theory of color. The antagonism that
exists in this field between Newton and Goethe cannot be judged
properly if one does not start by pointing to the difference between
the world conceptions of these two personalities. Goethe considered
the sense organs of man as the highest physical apparatuses. For the
world of colors, he therefore had to estimate the eye as his highest
judge for the observation of law-determined connections. Newton and
the physicists investigated the phenomena that are pertinent to this
question in a fashion that Goethe called the greatest misfortune
of modern physics, and that consisted in the fact that the
experiments have been separated, as it were, from man.
One wants to know nature only according to the indications of
artificial instruments and thereby even intends to limit and to prove
what nature is capable of.
The eye perceives light and darkness and, within the light-dark field
of observation, the colors. Goethe takes his stand within this field
and attempts to prove how light, darkness and the colors are
connected. Newton and his followers meant to observe the processes of
light and colors as they would go on if there were no human eye. But
the stipulation of such an external sphere is, according to Goethe's
world conception, without justification. We do not obtain an insight
into the nature of a thing by disregarding the effects we observe, but
this nature is given to us through the mind's exact observation of the
regularity of these effects. The effects that the eye perceives, taken
in their totality and represented according to the law of their
connection are the essence of the phenomena of light and color,
not a separated world of external processes that are to be determined
by means of artificial instruments.
It is really of no avail that we attempt to express directly the
nature of a thing. What we are aware of are effects, and a complete
account of these effects might possibly encompass the essence of that
thing. Vainly do we endeavor to describe the character of a man;
we put his deeds and actions together, however, and a picture of his
character arises before our eyes. Colors are the actions of light;
they are what light does and suffers. In this sense we can expect
information from them concerning the nature of light. Color and light
are indeed in close relation but we must think of them both as
belonging to nature as a whole; for it is nature as a whole that is
ready to manifest itself in special ways to the sense of the eye.
Here we find Goethe's world view applied to a special case. In the
human organism, through its senses, through the soul of man, there is
revealed what is concealed in the rest of nature. In man, nature
reaches its climax. Whoever, therefore, like Newton, looks for the
truth of nature outside man, will not find it, according to Goethe's
fundamental conviction.
Schopenhauer sees in the world that the mind perceives in space and
time only an idea of this mind. The essence of this world of thought
pictures is revealed to us in our will, by which we see our own
organism permeated. Schopenhauer, therefore, cannot agree with a
physical doctrine that sees the nature of light, not in the mental
content of the eye, but in a world that is supposed to exist separated
from the eye. Goethe's mode of conception was, for this reason, more
agreeable to Schopenhauer because Goethe did not go beyond the world
of the perceptual content of the eye. He considered Goethe's view to
be a confirmation of his own opinion concerning this world. The
antagonism between Goethe and Newton is not merely a question of
physics but concerns the world conception as a whole. Whoever is of
the opinion that a valid statement about nature can be arrived at
through experiments that can be detached from the human being must
take his stand with Newton's theory of color and remain on that
ground. Modern physics is of this opinion. It can only agree with the
judgment concerning Goethe's theory of colors that Helmholtz expressed
in his essay, Goethe's Anticipations of Future Ideas in Natural
Science:
Wherever it is a question of problems that can be solved through
poetic divination producing imaginative pictures, the poet has shown
himself capable of the most excellent work; wherever only a
consciously applied inductive method could have helped, Goethe has
failed.
If one sees in the pictures of human imagination only products that
are added to an already complete nature, then it is of course
necessary to determine what goes on in nature apart from these
pictures. But if one sees in them manifestations of the essence
contained in nature as Goethe did, then one will consult them in
investigating the truth. Schopenhauer, to be sure, shares neither the
first nor the second standpoint. He is not at all ready to recognize
sense perceptions as containing the essence of things. He rejects the
method of modern physics because physics does not limit itself to the
element that alone is directly given, namely, that of perceptions as
mental pictures. But Schopenhauer also transformed this question from
a problem of physics into one of world conception. As he also begins
his world conception with man and not with an external world apart
from man, he had to side with Goethe, who had consistently drawn the
conclusion for the theory of colors that necessarily follows if one
sees in man with his healthy sense organs the greatest and most
exact physical apparatus. Hegel, who as a philosopher stands
completely on this foundation, had for this reason forcefully defended
Goethe's theory of colors. He says in his Philosophy of Nature:
For the description of the color phenomenon that is adequate to its
concept, we are indebted to Goethe, who was attracted early by the
phenomena of color and light and who was drawn to their contemplation
especially in painting; his pure and simple sense of nature had to
revolt against such barbarism of reflected thought as is found in
Newton. Goethe took up everything about light and color that had been
stated and experimentally demonstrated since Plato. He conceived the
phenomenon as simple, and the truest instinct of reason does consist
in the ability of approaching a phenomenon from that side that allows
its simplest representation.
For Schopenhauer, the essential ground for all world processes is the
will. It is an eternal dark urge for existence. It contains no
reason because reason comes into existence only in the human brain,
which in turn is created by the will. Hegel sees the spirit as the
root of the world in self-conscious reason, and in human reason, only
as individual realization of the general world reason. Schopenhauer,
by contrast, recognizes reason only as a product of the brain, as a
mere bubble that comes into being at the end of the process in which
will, the unreasoning blind urge, has created everything else first.
In Hegel, all things and processes are permeated by reason; in
Schopenhauer, everything is without reason, for everything is the
product of the will without reason. The personality of Schopenhauer
exemplifies unequivocally a statement of Fichte, The kind of
world conception a man chooses depends on the kind of man he is.
Schopenhauer had bad experiences and had become acquainted with the
worst side of the world before he decided to spend his life in
contemplation of it. It is for this reason that he is satisfied to
depict the world as essentially deprived of reason as a result of
blind will. Reason, according to his mode of thinking, has no power
over unreason, for it is itself the result of unreason; it is illusion
and dream, produced out of will. Schopenhauer's world conception is
the dark, melancholy mood of his soul translated into thought. His eye
was not prepared to follow the manifestations of reason in the world
with pleasure. This eye saw only unreason that was manifest in sorrow
and pain. Thus, his doctrine of ethics could only be based on the
observation of suffering. An action is moral only if it has its
foundation in such an observation. Sympathy, pity, must be the
source of human actions. What better course could be taken by a man
who has gained the insight that all beings suffer than to let his
actions be guided by pity. As everything unreasonable and evil has its
roots in will, man will stand morally the higher the more he mortifies
his unruly will in himself. The manifestation of this will in the
individual person is selfishness, egotism. Whoever surrenders to pity
and thereby wills not for himself but for others, has become master of
the will.
One method of freeing oneself from the will consists in surrendering
to artistic creations and to the impressions that are derived from
works of art. The artist does not produce to satisfy a desire for
something; he does not produce his works because of a will that is
selfishly directed toward things and events. His production proceeds
out of unegotistic joy. He plunges into the essence of things in pure
contemplation. This is also true of the enjoyment of art. As long as
we approach a work of art with the desire stirring in us to own it, we
are still entangled in the lower appetites of the will. Only when we
admire beauty without desiring it have we raised ourselves to the
lofty stage where we no longer are dependent on the blind force of
will. Then art has become for us a means to free ourselves for the
moment from the unreasoning force of the blind will to exist. The
deliverance takes place in its purest form in the enjoyment of the
musical work of art, for music does not speak to us through the
medium of representative imagination as do the other arts. Music
copies nothing in nature. As all things and events are only mental
pictures, so also the arts that take these things as models can only
make impressions on us as manifestations of imaginations. Man produces
tone out of himself without a natural model. Because man has will as
his own essence within himself, it can only be the will through which
the world of music is directly released. It is for this reason that
music so deeply moves the human soul. It does this because music is
the manifestation of man's inner nature, his true being, his will, and
it is a triumph of man that he is in possession of an art in which he
enjoys selflessly, freed from the fetters of the will, what is the
root of all desire, of all unreason. This view of Schopenhauer
concerning music is again the result of his most personal nature. Even
before his university years, when he was apprenticed to a merchant in
Hamburg, he wrote to his mother:
How did the heavenly seed find a place on the hard ground on which
necessity and poverty struggle for every little spot? We have been
banished from the primordial spirit and are not to reach up to him.
Yet, a pitiful angel has begged the heavenly flower for us and it
blossoms in full glory rooted in this soil of misery. The pulsation's
of the divine art of music have not ceased to beat through the
centuries of barbarism, and a direct resonance of the eternal
is preserved in this art for us, understandable to every soul and
exalted above even vice and virtue.
From the attitude that is taken toward art by the two antipodes of
world conception, Hegel and Schopenhauer, one can learn how a world
conception deeply affects the personal relation of man toward the
various realms of life. Hegel, who saw in man's world of conceptions
and ideas the climax toward which all external nature strives as its
perfection, can recognize as the most perfect art only the one in
which the spirit appears in its most perfect form, and in which this
spirit at the same time clings to the element that continuously
strives toward the spirit. Every formation of external nature tends
to be spirit, but it does not reach this aim. When a man now
creates such an external spatial form, endowing it as an artist with
the spirit for which material itself strives without being capable of
reaching it, then he has produced a perfect work of art. This is the
case in the art of sculpture. What otherwise appears only in
the inward life of the soul as formless spirit, as idea, is shaped by
the artist out of matter. The soul, the inner life that we perceive in
our consciousness as being without shape, is what speaks out of a
statue, out of a formation of space. This marriage of the sensual
world with the world of the spirit represents the artistic ideal of a
world conception that sees the purpose of nature in the creation of
the spirit, and therefore can also recognize the beautiful only in a
work that appears as immediate expression of the spirit emerging in
the form of nature. Whoever, like Schopenhauer, however, sees in all
nature only mental pictures, cannot possibly recognize the ideal of
art in a work that imitates nature. He must choose an art as his ideal
that is free of all nature, that is to say, music.
Schopenhauer considered everything that leads toward the extirpation,
the mortification of the will quite consistently as desirable, for an
extirpation of the will means an extinction of the unreasonable in the
world. Man is to give up will. He is to kill all desire within
himself. Asceticism is, for this reason, Schopenhauer's moral
ideal. The wise man will extinguish within himself all wishes; he will
annihilate his will completely. He will reach the point where no
motivation forces him to exert his will. All striving consists merely
in quietistic yearning for deliverance from all life. In the
world-renouncing life-views in Buddhism, Schopenhauer acknowledged a
doctrine of profound wisdom. Compared to Hegel's, one can thus call
Schopenhauer's world view reactionary. Hegel attempted everywhere to
affect a reconciliation of man with life; he always strove to present
all action as a cooperation with a reason-directed order of the world.
Schopenhauer regarded enmity to life, withdrawal from reality and
world flight as the ideal of the wise man.
Hegel's mode of world and life conception contains an element that can
produce doubts and questions. Hegel's point of departure is pure
thinking, the abstract idea, which he himself once called an
oyster-like, gray or entirely black being (in a letter to Goethe
on February 20, 1821), of which he maintained at the same time should
be considered the representation of God as he is in his eternal
essence before the creation of nature and a finite spirit. The
aim that he reaches is the individual human spirit endowed with a
content of its own, through whom first comes to light what led only a
shadow-like existence in a gray, oyster-like element. This can easily
be understood to mean that a personality as a living
self-conscious being does not exist outside the human spirit. Hegel
derives the content-saturated element that we experience within
ourselves from the ideal element that we obtain through thinking.
It is quite comprehensible that a spirit of a certain inner
disposition felt repulsed by this view of world and life. Only
thinkers of such a selfless devotion as that of Karl Rosenkranz
(1805 1879) could so completely find their way into Hegel's
movement of thought and, in such perfect agreement with Hegel, create
for themselves structures of ideas that appear like a rebirth of
Hegel's own thought structure in a less impressive medium. Others
could not understand how man is to be enlightened through pure idea
with respect to the infinity and variety of the impressions that pour
in on him as he directs his observations toward nature, crowded as it
is with colors and forms, and how he is to profit if he lifts his soul
from experiences in the world of sensation, feeling and
perception-guided imagination to the frosty heights of pure thought.
To interpret Hegel in this fashion is to misunderstand him, but it is
quite comprehensible that he should have been misunderstood in this
way.
This mood that was dissatisfied with Hegel's mode of thinking found
expression in the current thought that had representatives in Franz
Xaver von Baader (1765 1841), Karl Christian Friedrich Krause
(1781 1832), Immanuel Hermann Fichte (1797 1879),
Christian Hermann Weisse (1801 1866), Anton Guenther
(1783 1863), Karl Friedrich Eusebius Thrahndorff (1782
1863) Martin Deutinger (1815 1864), and Hermann Ulrici
(1806 1884). They attempted to replace the gray, oyster-like
pure thought of Hegel by a life-filled, personal, primal entity, an
individual God. Baader called it an atheistic conception
to believe that God attained a perfect existence only in man. God must
be a personality and the world must not, as Hegel thought, proceed
from him like a logical process in which one concept always
necessarily produces the next. On the contrary, the world must be
God's free creation, the product of his almighty will. These thinkers
approach the Christian doctrine of revelation. To justify and fortify
this doctrine scientifically becomes the more-or-less conscious
purpose of their thinking. Baader plunged into the mysticism of
Jakob Boehme (1757 1624), Meister Eckhardt (1250
1329), Tauler (1290 1361) and Paracelsus (1494
1541), whose language, so rich in pictures, he considered a much more
appropriate means to express the most profound truths than the pure
thoughts of Hegel's doctrine. That Baader also caused Schelling to
enrich his thoughts with a deeper and warmer content through the
assimilation's of conceptions from Jakob Boehme has already been
mentioned.
In the course of the development of the modern world conception
personalities like Krause will always be remarkable. He was a
mathematician who allowed himself to be swayed by the proud, logically
perfect character of this science, and attempted a solution of the
problems of world conception after the model of the method he was used
to as a mathematician. Typical of this kind of thinker is the great
mathematician, Newton, who treated the phenomena of the visible
universe as if it were an arithmetical problem but, at the same time,
satisfied his own need concerning the fundamental questions of world
conception in a fashion that approached the belief to be found in
revealed religion. Krause finds it impossible to accept a conception
that seeks the primal being of the world in the things and
processes. Whoever, like Hegel, looks for God in the world cannot find
him, for the world, to be sure, is in God, but God is not in the
world. He is a self-dependent being resting within himself in blissful
serenity. Krause's world of ideas rests on thoughts of an
infinite, self-dependent being, outside of which there is nothing;
this being comprises everything by itself and in itself as the one
ground, and that we have to think of as the ground of reason,
nature and humanity. He does not want to have anything in common
with a view that takes the finite or the world as the sum total
of everything finite to be God itself, idolizing and confusing it with
God. No matter how deep one may penetrate into the reality given
to the senses and the mind, one will never arrive in this way at the
fundamental ground of all being. To obtain a conception of this being
is possible only if one accompanies all finite observation with a
divinatory vision of an over-worldly reality.
Immanuel Hermann Fichte settled his account with Hegelianism
poignantly in his essay, Propositions for the Prolegomena of
Theology (1826), and Contributions Toward a Characterization of
Modern Philosophy (1829). Then, in numerous works, he tried to
prove and elaborate his view that a conscious personal being must be
recognized as the basis of all world phenomena. In order to procure an
emphatic effect for the opposition to Hegel's conception, which
proceeded from pure thought, Immanuel Hermann Fichte joined hands with
friends who were of the same opinion. In 1837, together with Weisse,
Sengler, K. Ph. Fischer, Chalybäs, Fr. Hoffmann, Ulrici, Wirth and
others, he began the publication of the Journal for Philosophy and
Speculative Theology. It is Fichte's conviction that we have risen
to the highest knowledge only if we have understood that the
highest thought that truly solves the world problem is the idea of a
primal subject or absolute personality, which knows and fathoms
itself in its ideal as well as real infinity.
The world creation and preservation that comprises the world
reality, consists solely in the uninterrupted
consciousness-permeated will-direction of God, such that he is only
consciousness and will, but both in a highest union, therefore, only
person, or person in the most eminent sense of the word.
Chr. Hermann Weisse believed that it was necessary to proceed from
Hegel's world conception to a completely theological mode of
conception. In the Christian idea of the three personalities in the
one deity, he saw the aim of his thinking. He attempted to
represent this idea as the result of a natural and unsophisticated
common sense and did so with an uncommon array of ingenuity. In his
triune, Weisse believed that in a personal deity possessing a living
will he had something infinitely richer than Hegel with his
gray idea. This living will is to give to the inner godly nature
with one breath the one definite form and no other that is implied at
all places in the Holy Writ of the Old and New Testaments. In it, God
is shown prior to the creation of the world as well as during and
after that event in the shining element of his glory as surrounded by
an interminable heavenly host of serving spirits in a fluid immaterial
body, which enables him to fully communicate with the created
world.
Anton Guenther, the Viennese Philosopher, and Martin
Deutinger, who was under his influence, move with the thoughts of
their world conception completely within the framework of the catholic
theological mode of conception. Guenther attempts to free man from the
natural world order by dividing him into two parts a natural being
that belongs to the world of necessary law, and a spirit being that
constitutes a self-dependent part of a higher spirit world and has an
existence comparable to an entity as described by Herbart.
He believes that he overcomes Hegelianism in this manner and that he
supplies the foundation for a Christian world conception. The Church
itself was not of this opinion, for in Rome Guenther's writings were
included in the Prohibitory Index. Deutinger fought vehemently against
Hegel's pure thinking, which, in his opinion, ought to be
prevented from devouring life-filled reality. He ranks the living will
higher than pure thought. It can, as creative will, produce something;
thought is powerless and abstract. Thrahndorff also takes living will
as his point of departure. The world cannot be explained from the
shadowy realm of ideas, but a vigorous will must seize these ideas in
order to create real being. The world's deepest content does not
unfold itself to man in thoughtful comprehension, but in an emotional
reaction, in love through which the individual surrenders to
the world, to the will that rules in the universe. It is quite
apparent that all these thinkers endeavor to overcome thinking and its
object, the pure idea. They are unwilling to acknowledge thinking as
the highest manifestation of the spirit of man. In order to comprehend
the ultimate substance of the world, Thrahndorff wants to approach it,
not with the power of knowledge, but of love. It is to become
an object of emotion, not of reason. It is the belief of these
philosophers that through clear, pure thinking the ardent, religious
devotion to the primordial forces of existence are destroyed.
This opinion has its root in a misconception of Hegel's thought world.
Its misunderstanding becomes especially apparent in the views
concerning Hegel's attitude toward religion that spread after his
death. The lack of clarity that began to prevail regarding this
attitude resulted in a split among Hegel's followers into one party
that considered his world conception to be a firm pillar of revealed
Christianity, and another that used his doctrine to dissolve the
Christian conceptions and to replace them by a radically liberal view.
Neither party could have based its opinion on Hegel if they had
understood him correctly, for Hegel's world conception contains
nothing that can be used for support of a religion or for its
destruction. He had meant to do this with respect to any religion as
little as he had intended to create any natural phenomena through his
pure thought. As he had set out to extract the pure thought from the
processes of nature in order to comprehend them in that way, so he had
also, in the case of religion, merely the intention to bring its
thought content to the surface. As he considered everything that is
real in the world as reasonable just because it is real, so he held
this view also in regard to religion. It must come into existence by
soul forces quite beyond those that are at the disposal of the thinker
when he approaches them in order to comprehend them.
It was also an error of such thinkers as Fichte, Weisse, Deutinger and
others that they fought against Hegel because he had not proceeded
from the realm of pure thought to the religious experience of the
personal deity. Hegel had never set himself a task of this kind. He
considered that to be the task of the religious consciousness. The
younger Fichte, Weisse, Krause, Deutinger and the rest wanted to
create a new religion through their world conception. Hegel
would have considered such a task to be as absurd as the wish to
illuminate the world through the idea of light, or to create a
magnet out of the thought of magnetism. To be sure, in Hegel's
opinion, religion has its root in the idea, just as the whole world of
nature and the spirit. For this reason, it is possible that the human
spirit can rediscover this idea in religion, but as the magnet was
created out of the thought of magnetism before the human mind
came into being, and as the latter only afterwards has to
comprehend the magnet's creation, so also religion has become
what it is before its thought emerged in the human soul as an
illuminating part of world conception. If Hegel had lived to
experience the religious criticism of his pupils, he would have felt
compelled to say, Take your hands off all foundation of
religion, off all creation of religious conceptions, as long as
you want to remain thinkers and do not intend to become
messiahs. The world conception of Hegel, if it is correctly
understood, cannot have a retroactive effect on the religious
consciousness. The philosopher who reflects on the realm of art has
the same relation to his object as the thinker who wants to fathom the
nature of religion.
The Halle Yearbooks, published from 1838 to 1843 by Arnold Ruge
and Theodor Echtermeyer, served as a forum for the philosophical
controversies of the time. Starting with a defense and explanation of
Hegel, they soon proceeded to develop his ideas independently, and
thus made the transition to the views that are called radical
world conceptions in the next chapter. After 1841, the editors
called their journal, The German Yearbook, and, as one of their
aims, they considered the fight against political illiberality,
against theories of feudalism and landed property. In the
historical development of the time they became active as radical
politicians, demanding a state in which perfect freedom prevails.
Thus, they abandoned the spirit of Hegel, who wanted to understand
history, not to make it.
|