World Conceptions of Scientific Factuality
An attempt to derive a general view of world and life from the basis
of strict science was undertaken in the course of the nineteenth
century by Auguste Comte (1798 1857). This enterprise, which
was presented as a comprehensive world picture in his Cours de
Philosophic Positive (6 vols., 1830 42), was sharply
antagonistic to the idealistic views of Fichte, Schelling and Hegel of
the first half of the nineteenth century. It also opposed, although
not to the same degree, all those thought structures that were derived
from the ideas of evolution along the lines of Lamarck and Darwin.
What occupied the central position of all world conception in Hegel,
the contemplation and comprehension of man's own spirit, was
completely rejected by Comte. He argues: If the human spirit wanted to
contemplate itself, it would actually have to divide into two
personalities; it would have to slip outside itself and place itself
opposite its own being. Even a psychology that does not confine itself
to the mere physiological view but intends to preserve the processes
of the mind by themselves is not recognized by Comte. Anything that is
to become an object of knowledge must belong to the objective
interconnections of facts, must be presented objectively as the laws
of the mathematical sciences. From this position there follows Comte's
objection to the attempts of Spencer and other thinkers whose world
pictures followed the approach of scientific thinking adapted by
Lamarck and Darwin. So far as Comte is concerned, the human species is
given as a fixed and unchangeable fact; he refuses to pay any
attention to Lamarck's theory. Simple, transparent natural laws as
physics uses them for its phenomena are ideals of knowledge for him.
As long as science does not work with such simple laws, it is
unsatisfactory as knowledge for Comte. He has a mathematical bent of
mind. If it cannot be treated clearly and simply like a mathematical
problem, he considers it to be not ready for science. Comte has no
feeling for the fact that one needs ideas that become increasingly
more life-saturated as one rises from the purely mechanical and
physical processes to the higher formations of nature and to man. His
world conception owed a certain lifeless and rigid quality to this
fact. The whole world appears to him like the mechanics of a machine.
What escapes Comte everywhere is the element of life; he expels life
and spirit from things and explains merely what is mechanical and
machinelike. The concrete historical life of man appears in his
presentation like the conceptual picture that the astronomer draws of
the motions of the heavenly bodies. Comte constructed a scale of the
sciences. Mathematics represents the lowest stage; it is followed by
physics and chemistry and these again by the science of organisms; the
last and concluding science in this sequence is sociology, the
knowledge of human society. Comte strives to make all these sciences
as simple as mathematics. The phenomena with which the individual
sciences deal are supposed to be different in every case but the laws
are considered to be fundamentally always the same.
The reverberations of the thought of Holbach, Condillac and others are
still distinctly perceptible in the lectures on the relation between
soul and body (Les Rapports du Physique et du Moral de L'homme)
that Pierre Jean Georges Cabanis (1757 1808) gave in 1797
and 1798 in the medical school founded by the National Convention in
Paris. Nevertheless, these lectures can be called the beginning of the
development of the world conception of the nineteenth century in
France. They express a distinct awareness of the fact that Condillac's
mode of conception for the phenomena of the soul life had been too
closely modeled after the conception of the mechanical processes of
inorganic nature and their operation. Cabanis investigates the
influence of age, sex, way of life and temperament on man's
intellectual and emotional disposition. He develops the conception
that the physical and the spiritual are not two separated entities
that have nothing in common but that they constitute an inseparable
whole. What distinguishes him from his predecessors is not his
fundamental view but the way in which he elaborates it. His
predecessors simply carry into the spiritual the views they have
derived from the inorganic world. Cabanis is convinced that if we
start by observing the world of the spiritual as open-mindedly as we
observe the inorganic, it will reveal its relation to the rest of the
natural phenomena.
Destutt de Tracy (1754 1836) proceeded in a similar way.
He also wanted first to observe the processes of the spirit without
bias as they appear when we approach them without philosophical or
scientific prejudice. According to this thinker, one is in error if
one conceives the soul as a mechanism as Condillac and his followers
had done. This mechanistic character cannot be upheld any longer if
one honestly observes oneself. We do not find in us an automaton, a
being that is directed from without. We always find within us spontaneous
activity and an inner self. We should actually not know anything of the
effects of the external world if we did not experience a disturbance
in our inner life caused by a collision with the external world. We
experience our own being. We develop our activity out of ourselves,
but as we do this we meet with opposition. We realize not only our
own existence but also an external world that resists us.
Although they started from de Tracy, two thinkers Maine de Biran
(1766 1824) and André-Marie Ampère (1775 1826) were led
by the self-observation of the soul in entirely different directions.
Biran is a subtle observer of the human spirit. What in Rousseau seems
to emerge as a chaotic mode of thought motivated by an arbitrary mood,
we find in Biran in the form of clear and concrete thinking. Two
factors of man's inner life are made the objects of observation by
Biran who is a profoundly thoughtful psychologist: What man is through
the nature of his being, his temperament, and what he makes out of
himself through active work, his character. He follows the
ramifications and changes of the inner life, and he finds the source
of knowledge in man's inner life. The forces of which we learn through
introspection are intimately known in our life, and we learn of an
external world only insofar as it presents itself as more or less
similar and akin to our inner world. What should we know of forces
outside in nature if we did not experience within our self-active soul
a similar force and consequently could compare this with what
corresponds to it in the external world? For this reason, Biran is
untiring in his search for the processes in man's soul. He pays
special attention to the involuntary and the unconscious element in
the inner life processes that exist long before the light of
consciousness emerges in the soul. Biran's search for wisdom within
the soul led him to a peculiar form of mysticism in later years. In
the process of deriving the profoundest wisdom from the soul, we come
closest to the foundation of existence when we dig down into our own
being. The experience of the deepest soul processes then is an
immersion in the wellspring of existence, into the God within us.
The attraction of Biran's wisdom lies in the intimate way in which he
presents it. He could have found no more appropriate form of
presentation than that of a journal intime, a form of diary.
The writings of Biran that allow the deepest insight into his thought
world were published after his death by E. Naville (compare Naville's
book, Maine de Biran. Sa vie et ses pensées, 1857, and his
edition, Oeuvres inédités de Maine de Biran). As old men,
Cabanis and Destutt de Tracy belonged to a small circle of
philosophers; Biran was a younger member among them. Ampère was among
those who were acquainted with Biran's views. As a natural scientist,
he became prominent through the extension of Oersted's observation
concerning the relation of electricity to magnetism (compare above
in Part II Chapter I).
Biran's mode of conception is more intimate, that of Ampère
more scientific-methodical. Ampère follows with interest the
interrelationship of sensations and conceptions in the soul, and also
the process through which the spirit arrives at a science of the world
phenomena with the aid of thinking.
What is significant in this current of world conception, which
chronologically represents the continuation of the teachings of
Condillac, is the circumstance that the life of the soul itself is
decidedly emphasized, that the self-activity of the inner personality
of the human being is brought into the foreground of the
investigation, and that all these thinkers are striving nevertheless
for knowledge in the strict sense of natural science. Initially, they
investigate the spirit with the methods of natural science, but they
do not want to treat its phenomena as homogeneous with the other
processes of nature. From these more materialistic beginnings there
emerges finally a tendency toward a world conception that leans
distinctly toward the spirit.
Victor Cousin (1792 1867) traveled through Germany several
times and thus became personally acquainted with the leading spirits of
the idealistic period. The deepest impression was made on him by Hegel
and Goethe. He brought their idealism to France. As a professor at the
École normale (1814), and later at the Sorbonne, he was able to do a
great deal for this idealism through his powerful and fascinating
eloquence that always produced a deep impression. Cousin received
from the idealistic life of the spirit the conviction that it is not
through the observation of the external world but through that of the
human spirit that a satisfactory viewpoint for a world conception can
be obtained. He based what he wanted to say on the self observation of
the soul. He adopted the view of Hegel that spirit, idea and thought
do not merely rule in man's inner life but also outside in nature and
in the progress of the historical life, and that reason is contained
in reality. Cousin taught that the character of a people of an age was
not merely influenced by random happenings, arbitrary decisions of
human individuals, but that a real idea is manifested in them and that
a great man appears in the world merely as a messenger of a great idea,
in order to realize it in the course of history. This produced a
profound impression on Cousin's French audience, which in its most
recent history had had to comprehend world historical upheavals without
precedent, when they heard such a splendid speaker expound the role
that reason played in the historical evolution in accordance with some
great and fundamental ideas.
Comte, with energy and resolution, found his place in the development
of French philosophy with his principle: only in the method of
science, which proceeds from strict mathematical and directly observed
truths as in physics and chemistry can the point of departure for a
world conception be found. The only approach he considered mature was
the one that fought its way through to this view. To arrive at this
stage, humanity had to go through two phases of immaturity one in
which it believed in gods, and subsequently, one in which it
surrendered to abstract ideas. Comte sees the evolution of mankind in
the progression from theological thinking to idealistic thinking, and
from there to the scientific world conception. In the first stage,
man's thinking projected anthropomorphic gods into the processes of
nature, which produce these processes in the same arbitrary manner in
which man proceeds in his actions. Later, he replaces the gods with
abstract ideas as, for instance, life force, general world reason,
world purpose, and so forth. But this phase of development must give
way to a higher one in which it must be understood that an explanation
of the phenomena of the world can be found only in the method of
observation and a strictly mathematical and logical treatment of the
facts. For the purpose of a world conception, thinking must merely
combine what physics, chemistry and the science of living organisms
obtain through their investigation. Thinking must not add anything to
the results of the individual sciences as theology had done with its
divine beings and the idealistic philosophy with its abstract
thoughts. Also, the conceptions concerning the course of the evolution
of mankind, the social life of men in the state, in society, etc.,
will become clear only when the attempt is made to find in them laws
like those found in the exact natural sciences. The causes that bring
families, associations, legal views and state institutions into
existence must be investigated in the same way as the causes that make
bodies fall to the ground and that allow the digestive organs to
operate. The science of human social life, of human development,
sociology, is therefore what Comte is especially concerned with, and
he tries to give it the exactness that the other sciences have
gradually acquired.
In this respect he has a predecessor in Claude-Henri de Saint-Simon
(1760 1825). Saint-Simon had presented the view that man would
only learn to guide his own fate completely when he conceived of his
own life in the state, in society and in the course of history in a
strictly scientific sense, and when he arranged it like a process
following a natural law. For awhile, Comte was on intimate terms with
Saint-Simon. He parted ways with him when it seemed to him that
Saint-Simon's views turned into all sorts of groundless dreams and
utopias. Comte continued to work with a rare zeal in his original
direction. His Cours de Philosophic Positive is an attempt to
elaborate, in a style of spirit-alienation, the scientific
accomplishments of his time into a world conception by presenting them
merely in a systematized survey, and by developing sociology in the
same way without the aid of theological and idealistic thoughts. Comte
saw no other task for the philosopher than that of such a mere
systematized survey. The philosopher would add nothing of his own to
the picture that the sciences have presented as the connection of
facts. Comte expressed thereby, in the most pointed manner, his view
that the sciences alone, with their methods of observing reality, have
a voice in the formulation of a world conception.
Within German spirit-life Eugen Dühring (1833 1921) appeared
as a forceful champion of Comte's thought. This was expressed in 1865
in his Natural Dialectic. As a further exposition, he expounded
his views in his book, Course of Philosophy as a Strictly
Scientific World Conception and Art of Life (1875), and in
numerous other writings in the fields of mathematics, natural science,
philosophy, history of science and social economy. All of Dühring's
work proceeds, in the strictest sense of the word, from a mathematical
and mechanistic mode of thought. Dühring is outstanding in his
endeavor to analyze his observations of nature in accordance with
mathematical law, but where this kind of thinking is insufficient, he
loses all possibility of finding his way through life. It is from this
characteristic of his spirit that the arbitrariness and bias is to be
explained with which Dühring judges so many things. Where it is
necessary to judge the conflicts of life in accordance with higher
ideas, he has, therefore, no other criterion than his sympathies and
antipathies that have been aroused in him through accidental personal
circumstances. This man, with his mathematically objective mind,
becomes completely arbitrary when he undertakes to evaluate human
accomplishments of the historical past or of the present. His rather
unimaginative mathematical mode of conception led him to denounce a
personality like Goethe as the most unscientific mind of modern times,
whose entire significance consisted, in Dühring's opinion, in a few
poetical achievements. It is impossible to surpass Dühring in his
under-valuation of everything that lies beyond a drab reality as he
does in his book, The Highlights of Modern Literature. In spite
of this one-sidedness, Dühring is one of the most stimulating figures
in the development of modern world conception. No one who has
penetrated his thought-saturated books can help but confess that he
has been profoundly affected by them.
Dühring uses rude language for all world conceptions that do not
proceed from strictly scientific basic views. All such unscientific
modes of thought found themselves in the state of childish
immaturity or feverish fits, or in the decadence of senility, no
matter whether they infest entire epochs and parts of humanity under
these circumstances or just occasionally individual elements or
degenerated layers of society, but they always belong to the category
of the immature, the pathological or that of over-ripeness that is
already decomposed by putrefaction, (Course of Philosophy).
What Kant, Fichte, Schelling and Hegel achieved, Dühring
condemns as the outflow of a professorial wisdom of mountebanks;
idealism as a world conception is for him a theory of insanity. He
means to create a philosophy of reality that is alone adequate to
nature because it does away with all artificial and unnatural
fictions, and for the first time makes the concept of reality the
measure of all ideal conceptions; reality is conceived in this
philosophy in a manner that excludes all tendencies toward a
dreamlike and subjectivistically limited world conception.
(Course of Philosophy)
One should think like a real expert in mechanics, a real physicist who
confines himself to the results of sense perception, of the logical
combinations of the intellect and the operations of calculations.
Anything that goes beyond this is idle playing with empty concepts.
This is Dühring's verdict. Dühring means to raise this form of
thinking, however, to its justified position. Whoever depends
exclusively on that form of thinking can be sure that it supplies him
with insight concerning reality. All brooding over the question of
whether or not we actually can penetrate into the mysteries of the
world process, all investigations, which, like Kant's, want to limit
the faculty of knowledge, are caused by logical distortion. One should
not yield to the temptation of a self-sacrificing self-denial of the
mind that does not dare to make a positive statement about the world.
What we can know is a real and untarnished presentation of the real.
The totality of things has a systematic order and an inner
logically consistent structure. Nature and history have a constitution
and a development that correspond to a large extent to the general
logical relations of all concepts. The general qualities and relations
of the concepts of thought with which logic deals must also be valid
for the special case, that its object is the totality of being,
together with its chief forms. Since the most general thinking decides
to a large extent what can be and how it can be, the highest
principles and the main forms of logic must set the standard for all
reality and its forms. (Course of Philosophy)
Reality has produced for itself an organ in human thinking in which it
can reproduce itself mentally in the form of thought in an ideal
picture. Nature is everywhere ruled by an all-penetrating law that
carries its own justification within itself and cannot be criticized.
How could there be any meaning in an attempt to criticize the
relevance of thinking, the organ of nature? It is mere foolishness to
suppose that nature would create an organ through which it would
reflect itself only imperfectly or incompletely. Therefore, order and
law in this world must correspond to the logical order and law in
human thinking. The ideal system of our thought is the picture
of the real system of objective reality; the completed knowledge has,
in the form of thoughts, the same structure that the things possess in
the form of real existence.
In spite of this general agreement between thinking and reality, there
exists for the former the possibility to go beyond the latter. In the
element of the idea, thinking continues the operations that reality
has suggested to it. In reality all bodies are divisible, but only up
to a certain limit. Thinking does not stop at this limit but continues
to divide in the realm of the idea. Thought sweeps beyond reality; for
thought, the body is divisible into infinity. Accordingly, to thought
it consists of infinitely small parts. In reality, this body consists
only of a definite, finite number of small, but not infinitely small
parts. In this way all concepts of infinity that transcend reality
come into existence. From every event we proceed to another event that
is its cause; from this cause we go again to the cause of that cause
and so forth. As soon as our thinking abandons the firm ground of
reality, it sweeps on into a vague infinity. It imagines that for
every cause a cause has to be sought in turn so that the world is
without a beginning in time. In allotting matter to space, thinking
proceeds in a similar way. In transversing the sky it always finds
beyond the most distant stars still other stars; it goes beyond this
real fact and imagines space as infinite and filled with an infinite
number of heavenly bodies. According to Dühring, one ought to realize
that all such conceptions of infinity have nothing to do with reality.
They only occur through the fact that thinking, with the methods that
are perfectly appropriate within the realm of reality, rises above
this realm and thereby gets lost in the indefinite.
If in our thinking, however, we remain aware of this separation from
reality, we need no longer refrain from applying our concepts borrowed
from human action, to nature. Dühring, as he proceeds from such
presuppositions, does not even hesitate to attribute to nature in its
production an imagination any more than he does to man in his
creation. Imagination extends . . . into nature itself; it has
its roots, as does all thinking in general, in the processes that
precede the developed consciousness but do not produce any elements of
subjective feelings (Course of Philosophy). The thought
upheld by Comte, that all world conception should be confined to a
mere rearrangement of the purely factual, dominates Dühring so
completely that he projects the faculty of imagination into the
external world because he believes that he would simply have to reject
it if it occurred merely in the human mind. Proceeding from these
conceptions he arrives at other projections of such concepts as are
derived from human activities. He thinks, for instance, that not only
man could, in his actions, undertake fruitless attempts, which he then
gives up because they do not lead to the intended aim, but that such
attempts could also be observed in nature.
The character of the tentative in the formations of nature is not at
all alien to reality itself, and one cannot see why one should allow
only one half of the parallelism between nature outside man and nature
in man, just for the sake of pleasing a shallow philosophy. If
subjective error of thinking and imagining springs from the relative
separation and independence of this sphere, why should not a practical
error or blunder of the objective and non-thinking nature be possibly
the result of a relative separation and mutual alienation of its
various parts and driving forces? A true philosophy that is not
intimidated by common prejudices will finally recognize the perfect
parallelism and the all-pervading unity of the constitution in both
directions. (Course of Philosophy)
Dühring is not in the least shy when it is a question of applying the
concepts to reality that thinking produces in itself. But since he
has, because of his disposition, only a sense for mathematical
conceptions, the picture he sketches of the world has a
mathematical-schematic character. He rejects the mode of thought that
was developed by Darwin and Haeckel and does not understand what
motivates them to search for a reason to explain why one being
develops from another. The mathematician places the forms of a
triangle, square, circle and ellipse side by side; why should one not
be satisfied with a similar schematic coordination in nature as well?
Dühring does not aim at the genesis of nature but at the fixed
formations that nature produces through the combinations of its
energies, just as the mathematician studies the definite, strictly
delineated forms of space. He finds nothing inappropriate in
attributing to nature a purposeful striving toward such definite
formations. Dühring does not interpret this purposeful tendency of
nature as the conscious activity that develops in man, but he supposes
it to be just as distinctly manifested in the operation of nature as
every other natural manifestation. In this respect, Dühring's view is,
therefore, the opposite pole of the one upheld by Friedrich Albert
Lange. Lange declares the higher concepts, especially all those in
which imagination has a share, to be justifiable poetic fiction;
Dühring rejects all poetic imagination in concepts, but he attributes
actual reality to certain higher ideas that are indispensable to him.
Thus, it seems quite consistent for Lange to separate the foundation
of the moral life entirely from all ideas that are rooted in reality
(compare above,
to Part II Chapter III).
It is also consistent if Dühring wants to
extend the ideas that he sees as valid in the realm of morality to
nature as well. He is completely convinced that what happens in man
and through man belongs to the natural events as much as do the
inanimate processes. What in human life is right cannot be wrong in
nature.
Such considerations contributed to making Dühring an energetic
opponent to Darwin's doctrine of the struggle for existence. f the
fight of all against all were the condition of perfection in nature,
it would have to be the same with man's life:
Such a conception that claims to be scientific is the most immoral
thing thinkable. The character of nature is in this way conceived in
an anti-moral sense. It is not merely indifferent to the better
morality of man but it is actually in agreement and in alliance with
the bad moral principles that are followed by scoundrels. (Course
of Philosophy)
According to Dühring's life-conception, what man feels as moral
impulses must have its origin in nature. It is possible to observe in
nature a tendency toward morality. As nature produces various forces
that purposefully combine into stable formations, so it also plants
into man instincts of sympathy. By them he allows himself to be
determined in his social life with his fellow men. In man, the
activity of nature is continued on an elevated level. Dühring
attributes the faculty to produce sensations automatically out of
themselves to the inanimate mechanical forces.
The mechanical causality of the forces of nature becomes, so to peak,
subjectified in the fundamental sensation. The fact of this elementary
process of subjectification is evidently incapable of any further
explanation, for somewhere and under some conditions the unconscious
mechanism of the world must develop a feeling of itself. (Course of
Philosophy)
But when the world arrives at this stage, it is not that a new law
begins, a realm of the spirit, but merely a continuation occurs of
what had already been there in the unconscious mechanism. This
mechanism, to be sure, is unconscious, but it is nevertheless wise,
for the earth with all it produces, as well as all causes of
life's maintenance that lie outside, especially in the sun and all
influences that come from the whole surrounding world in general
this entire organization and arrangement must be thought of as
essentially produced for man, which is to say, in agreement with his
well-being. (Course of Philosophy)
Dühring ascribes thought and even aims and moral tendencies to nature
without admitting that he thereby idealizes nature. But, for an
explanation of nature, higher ideas are necessary that transcend the
real. According to Dühring, however, there must be nothing like that;
he therefore changes their meaning by interpreting them as facts.
Something similar happened in the world conception of Julius
Hermann von Kirchmann (1802 84), who published his Philosophy
of Knowledge in 1864 at about the same time Dühring's Natural
Dialectic appeared. Kirchmann proceeds from the supposition that
only what is perceived is real. Man is connected with reality through
his perception. Everything that he does not derive from perception he
must eliminate from his knowledge of reality. He succeeds in doing
this if he rejects everything that is contradictory.
"Contradiction is not, is Kirchmann's second principle,
which follows his first principle, The perceived is.
Kirchmann admits only feelings and desires as the states of the soul
of man that have an existence by themselves.
Knowing forms a contrast to the other two states, to feeling and
desire. . . . It is possible that there is in knowing something
underlying, perhaps something similar to, pressure and tension, but if
it is conceived in this way it cannot be grasped in its essence. As
knowing, and it is only as such that it is to be investigated here, it
merely makes itself into a mirror of another being. There is no better
parable for this than the mirror. Just as the mirror is the more
perfect the less it shows of itself and the more it reflects another
being, so it is also with knowing. Its essence is the pure reflection
of a being other than itself, without mixing in its own state of
being. (Philosophy of Knowledge, 1864)
One cannot imagine a greater contrast to Hegel's mode of conception
than this view of knowledge. While with Hegel the essence of a thing
appears in thinking, in the element that the soul adds in spontaneous
activity to the percept, Kirchmann's ideal of knowledge consists of a
mirror picture of percepts from which all additions by the soul itself
have been eliminated.
To judge Kirchmann's position in the intellectual life correctly, one
must consider the great difficulty with which somebody who had the
will to erect an independent structure of world conception was met in
his time. The results of natural science, which were to produce a
profound influence on the development of world conceptions, were still
young. They were just sufficient to shake the belief in the classical
idealistic world conception that had had to erect its proud structure
without the aid of modern natural science. In the face of the wealth
of detailed knowledge, it became difficult to reconstruct fundamental
philosophical thoughts. The thread that led from the scientific
knowledge of facts to a satisfactory total conception of the world was
gradually lost in the general consciousness. A certain perplexity took
hold of many. An understanding for the lofty flight of thought that
had inspired the world conception of Hegel was scarcely to be found
anywhere.
|